Abstract
This article examines request for confirmation (RfC) sequences in Low German (LoG) conversation, a dialect variety of German. The study is based on both a quantitative analysis of 200 RfC instances and a qualitative analysis of selected excerpts in the framework of conversation analysis (CA). As for the question design of RfCs, declarative and phrasal formats, as well as modulations and tags prevail in the LoG data. Concerning the response design, LoG is characterized as a polarity system in which language contact with the high variety plays a decisive role in the answer possibility space. In particular, High German response tokens are predominantly used as unmarked response types, while LoG response tokens are deployed as marked types. Moreover, LoG seems to be a language between the poles of token- and repeat-type languages. Full repeats index different degrees of ‘markedness’ in LoG interaction. Contrary to previous studies on polar answers, repeats in LoG are frequently deployed as unmarked responses in subordinate lines of actions. Repeats are also used as more marked answers after understanding displays. This article attempts to stress the importance of investigating non-standard languages and variety contact in CA, thereby addressing the monolingual bias in research on polar questions.
1 Introduction
Polar questions and the responses they invite are a prominent area of inquiry in interactional linguistics (e.g., Raymond 2003, Steensig and Drew 2008, Enfield et al. 2010, 2019, Stivers 2022, Bolden et al. 2023). However, as the main body of research is based on insights from standard languages, little is known about how social actions and their response designs vary in non-standard languages. This article studies request for confirmation (RfC) sequences in Low German (LoG), a regional variety of German spoken in the north of Germany.
The results of this study are part of the Scientific Network ‘Interactional Linguistics’, which examines RfCs and their sequential trajectories from a pragmatic typological perspective (König and Pfeiffer, Forthcoming). RfCs are understood as a type of polar question, where a speaker establishes a B-event-statement (Labov and Fanshel 1977, 100). RfCs display partial knowledge about a matter at hand, which has to be confirmed by another interlocutor with a higher epistemic [K+] status (e.g., Heritage and Roth 1995, Heritage 2012a, b, Heritage and Raymond 2012, Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018, 227–30). In contrast to information questions indexing a steep epistemic gradient, the slope of the epistemic gradient between the questioner using an RfC and the recipient is more shallow (Heritage 2012b, 32). In addition to the epistemic stance conveyed by RfCs, polar questions often do ‘double duty’ (Schegloff 2007, 169), both enacting a request and serving as a vehicle for other actions like topic-proffering, upshots, understanding checks, candidate understandings, or challenges (e.g., Heritage 2002, Koshik 2002, 2005, Heinemann 2006, Schegloff 2007, 169–80, Küttner and Ehmer 2024). This ‘double-barreled’ nature is also reflected in the two-part structure of participant responses (Sacks 1992, 8, Raymond 2013). Moreover, RfCs differ in their form and sequential positioning. They are deployed with negative or positive polarity, as clauses or phrases, with or without question tags (QTs).
The objective of this article is to examine RfC designs, their responsive uptakes, and the sequential trajectories they engender in LoG interaction within the framework of conversation analysis (CA). Section 2 outlines existing research on RfCs, QTs, and response designs in LoG. Section 3 introduces the LoG data from which 200 instances of RfCs were derived for analysis. The linguistic resources routinely used to build RfCs are described in Section 4, and the response system is detailed in Section 5. Section 6 summarizes the results with a special focus on ‘markedness’ of repeats and variety-specific differences between LoG and High German (HG) RfC designs by comparing the results of this study with those of Deppermann et al. (2024).
2 Literature review
To date, no comprehensive empirical studies have been conducted on RfCs, modulations, QTs, or response designs in LoG talk-in-interaction. Even in dictionaries on LoG, no entries address question or response formats (Lindow 1998, Thies 2010), with remarks on syntactic peculiarities focusing mainly on the absence of conjunctions, especially subjunctions, in Low compared to (High) German (Thies 2010, 231–47).
Research on modal particles in interaction has primarily focused on HG (e.g., Thurmair 1989, Schoonjans 2018). The exception is Weber (2020b), whose analysis of the modal particles wall [LoG]/wohl [HG]) (usually translated as ‘probably’) demonstrates that speakers from the north-west LoG area deploy these particles as resources for indexing both an unknowing [K–] and a knowing [K+] epistemic stance. At the same time, speakers of other German varieties use this modal particle exclusively as an index of a [K–] stance.
Concerning QTs as ‘response mobilizing features’ in interaction (Stivers and Rossano 2010), CA research has primarily focused on HG (e.g., Hagemann 2009, Drake 2016, König 2020), with only a small body of this work analyzing QTs as regional specific phenomena (e.g., Elspaß and Möller 2005, Glaser 2003, Frey 2010, Lanwer 2019). The QT ne (‘not’) is described as a supraregional resource in interaction, which varies only in terms of its specific forms, e.g., net, nech, or nich (Duden 2006, 602, Imo 2011, 128). From a historical perspective, some scholars argue that ne emerged as a phonetically reduced variant of nicht and nich (Bublitz 1978, 126, Burkhardt 1982, 164). Lanwer (2019) shows that the QT ne is the predominant variant used in north HG by speakers in Westphalia and Low Anglo-Saxony. Regional differences with regard to the interactional impact in the deployment of ne are not addressed in Lanwer’s study. In addition to ne, the QT wa (‘what’) is supposed to be an exclusive northern German variant (Duden 2006, 602), while woll seems to be a typical Westphalian QT (Imo 2011, 128). In sum, previous research on QTs has primarily investigated (regional) HG data rather than LoG varieties, considering various social actions that QTs can be attached to. RfCs have not yet been the focus of this research field.
In sum, there are no studies that have examined features of question and response design, the use of modulating resources, and QTs in LoG RfC sequences. While the study by Pfeiffer et al. (Forthcoming) has revealed frequency-based similarities and differences in the design and response system of RfCs in LoG and HG, this article aims to extend those findings by providing an in-depth analysis of LoG RfC sequences.
3 Description of the data set
The data set consists of naturally occurring interactions in LoG, a West Germanic language containing different varieties spoken throughout the north of Germany. Scholars have not reached a consensus as to whether LoG should be defined as a language on its own or as a variety of German (Wirrer 1998). Fundamental structural differences exist between LoG and HG. One of the most important differences is that in LoG neither the Second High German Consonant Shift (‘Zweite Hochdeutsche Lautverschiebung’) nor the phonological process of diphthongization has taken place. Moreover, “the word order of Low German is relatively restricted and tends to be expressed by a default SVO order” (Langer 2003, 284). Based on a synchronic perspective, this article will treat LoG as a variety of German (see also Sanders 1982, 34, Langer 2003, 282). In line with the decline of German dialects, LoG is primarily a spoken variety at this point, used informally among friends and family, particularly by rural, older generations; numbers of middle-aged or younger speakers are decreasing (Adler et al. 2018).[1] Due to the increasing language contact between LoG and HG, the speakers are bilingual (or bilectal) and show interferences in the use of one or the other variety (Hansen-Jaax 1995).
The LoG data in this study comprise approximately 60 h of authentic everyday talk-in-interaction collected in the north-western part of Germany (Weber 2020a). All speakers are native Westphalians who acquired LoG as their first language or in a bilingual fashion, i.e., along with (regional) HG. Consequently, the results of the study do not apply to the entire LoG language area, but are limited to speakers from the Westphalian region. According to the guidelines of the research network’s comparative enterprise (Pfeiffer et al., Forthcoming), 200 RfC sequences were collected from 5.9 h of talk (15 interactions: 11 multiparty interactions and 4 dyadic interactions, min = 09.23 min, max = 32.27 min) by 35 native Westphalian LoG speakers. The majority of speakers are between 50 and 80 years old; only three individuals are younger than 40. The data comprise recordings of co-present interactions between family members sitting around a table talking in over 80% of the cases. In some recordings, the participants are empractically involved in the action of eating (about 20% of cases). Data were coded according to the research network’s coding manual (König et al., Forthcoming). As the data are available in audio only, a multimodal analysis is not possible.
4 Resources for requesting confirmation in LoG
4.1 Syntactic design
In LoG, RfCs are routinely deployed in clause structure (n = 144/200; 72%), especially with declarative syntax, i.e., clauses with verb-second position (SVO structure; n = 108/200; 54%, Table 1). In 60% of the cases (n = 65/108), declarative RfCs are equipped with a tag, as in Extract (1). In 40% (n = 43/108), these RfCs are deployed as ‘declarative questions’ without a tag, a typical syntactic RfC design in Germanic languages (Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018, 228).
Syntactic design of RfCs in LoG
Syntactic format | Frequency (total n = 200) |
---|---|
Declarative clause | 108 (54%) |
Phrase | 49 (24.5%) |
Polar interrogative clause | 27 (13.5%) |
Subordinate clause | 9 (4.5%) |
Elliptical confirmables | 7 (3.5%) |
Section 1 outlines that RfCs often have a ‘double-barreled’ nature. Declaratively formatted polar questions are said to convey a bunch of different social actions in interactions, besides the action of questioning (e.g., Seuren and Huiskes 2017). In the LoG data, declarative RfCs with and without a tag are predominantly used as a means to accomplish three different social actions: (1) topic proffers, (2) understanding displays, and (3) understanding checks. With topic proffers “a speaker proposes a particular topic …, but does not actively launch or further develop the proposed topic” (Schegloff 2007, 169–70). Consider (1). Heidi and Annika are talking about Heidi’s training course. After a sequence closure of the just-prior talk (lines 01–02), Heidi marks a departure from the ongoing sequence and manages a topic change by means of the conjunction ower (‘but’) and the following RfC formatted as a tag question (line 03).
Extract 1: LoG-HES02_06 (00:01:24 – 00:01:27), No. 77
01 | Heidi: | [jo kAs UTha:ln]; | |||||||
Yes that is worthwhile | |||||||||
02 | Annika: | [dAt is ganz MOI] so; | |||||||
That is nice | |||||||||
03 | Heidi: | ower | du | hast | late | FIERowend | mAkt; | =ne? | |
But | you.SG | have.2SG.AUX | late | off work | made.PST.PTCP NE_QT | ||||
But you got off work late, right | |||||||||
04 | Annika: | (0.3) IK? | |||||||
Me |
In addition to topic proffers, declarative RfCs are also deployed as understanding displays (Heritage 1984, 320–3; see also Zinken and Küttner 2022). With this action type, speakers “wish to show that prior talk has been adequately descriptive and/or they have competently understood its import” (Heritage 1984, 321). Typically, these displays are deployed as confident inferences prefaced with a change-of-state token indexing independent ‘then and there’-understanding “prior to any possible confirmation” (Heritage 1984, 321). Consider (2). Helga refers in line 01 to a recent meeting with a person called Tim, implementing the action of delivering news to Ben. In lines 06–07, he deploys a confident inference prefaced with the change-of-state token ach ja (‘I see/I remember’) to index an independent understanding of the class reunion Helga was referring to in line 01. Because of this index of independence, understanding displays require subsequent (dis)confirmation to a lesser extent compared to understanding checks (Heritage 1984, 323).
Extract 2: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:00:01 – 00:00:09), No. 48
01 | Helga: | sAmstach hebbt_wi (0.5) ju TIM auch seijn; | ||||
Guess what, we saw Tim on Saturday | ||||||
02 | Ben: | (0.5) Use ↑TIM? | ||||
Our Tim | ||||||
03 | Paul: | <<f> JO, | ||||
Yes | ||||||
04 | ja hh°; | |||||
Yes | ||||||
05 | de hebb (.) de hebb ik siet JOHren nich mehr seijn; | |||||
I hadn't seen him in years | ||||||
06 | Ben: | (0.2) <<f> ach JA, | ||||
I see/I remember | ||||||
07 | de | heff | KLAssentreffen | hat; | =ne, | |
they.PL | have.2PL.AUX | class reunion | had.PST.PTCP | NE_QT | ||
They had a class reunion, right | ||||||
08 | Paul: | de heff KLAssentreffen hat, | ||||
They had a class reunion |
Finally, declarative RfCs are also used as understanding checks in LoG interaction. Following Heritage (1984, 318–20), this article considers understanding checks to be clarificatory repair-like sequences, where a speaker proposes “a candidate understanding of what an earlier speaker had intended, the producer of an understanding check thereby invites that speaker to confirm (or disconfirm) the adequacy of that proposal” (Heritage 1984, 319). Consider (3). Annika deploys a topic proffer in the form of a telling question referring to a meeting that Heidi attended. Heidi embraces the topic and starts to elaborate on the event in lines 03–04. The beginning of Heidi’s elaboration overlaps with an understanding check of Annika in line 05 as a side sequence, which requires clarification of the organizing institution of that meeting.
Extract 3: LoG-HES02_06 (00:00:08 – 00:00:13), No. 75
01 | Annika: | wu WAS dat auf versAmmlung so? |
How was the meeting | ||
02 | (-) GEEFT do [wAt]1, | |
Did anything happen | ||
03 | Heidi: | [uff]1- |
Ugh | ||
04 | DU dat_w[as]2- | |
It was | ||
05 | Annika: | [SP] 2 Arkasse was dat;=[ne] 3 ? |
Sparkasse (German bank) was it NE_QT | ||
It was at Sparkasse, wasn’t it | ||
06 | Heidi: | [DAT]3 was bi de spArkasse; |
It was at Sparkasse | ||
07 | det was GANZ interessant, | |
It was very interesting |
Besides declarative formats, RfCs in LoG are also produced as phrases in about a quarter of cases (n = 49/200, 24.5%), with the majority being nominal (e.g., dat Grüne ‘the green one’) or prepositional in nature (e.g., mit Auto ‘by car’). 28.5% of all phrasal RfCs are used with a tag (n = 14/49). In 8% (n = 4/49), these phrases are deployed as a candidate answer (Pomerantz 1988), following an information question as in (4). Previous to the extract, Lukas told Tina that he regularly attends swimming courses.
Extract 4: LoG-BÖR01_07 (00:03:45 – 00:03:48), No. 19
01 | Tina: | !WANN! geih_ih da hEn; |
When do you go there | ||
02 | DÖNNerdachs? | |
Thursdays | ||
03 | Lukas: | (0.3) mh `DÖNNdachs- |
uh Thursdays |
In contrast to the functional diversity of declarative RfCs, phrasal RfCs are the predominant format to accomplish understanding checks. Consider Extract (5). Following Anna’s narrative about a guided tour of a German food company (lines 01–02), Heinz launches a “side sequence within an ongoing sequence” (Jefferson 1972, 294) in order to clarify the referential food company by proposing the candidate bi apetito (‘At apetito’s’) in the form of a phrasal RfC. Anna confirms the RfC in line 05 by using a full repeat, thus closing the side sequence and moving back to the main line of action in line 06.
Extract 5: LoG-HES01_07_09 (00:23:12 – 00:23:20), No. 108
01 | Anna: | un: bÜnt da ja mo wÄ:n up EINladung; | |
I was invited there once | |||
02 | von (.) von mÜllers HERbert; | ||
By Herbert Müller | |||
03 | Heinz: | (0.2) wie- | |
What do you mean | |||
04 | bi apeTIto; | ||
At Apetito’s (German company that produces food) | |||
05 | Anna: | bI apeTIto; | |
At Apetito’s | |||
06 | d[e HETT] de: °hh- | ||
They have they | |||
07 | Heinz: | [hm_hm] | |
information receipt |
RfCs are also formatted with interrogative syntax (VSO structure) in the LoG data (n = 27/200; on interrogative syntax as a typical format of RfCs, refer to Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018, 218). In particular, polar interrogative RfCs are predominantly used to accomplish understanding displays, presenting an inference or a highly likely knowledge about a matter at hand. Consider (6) (larger Extract (6) in 4.2). In line 01, Paul deploys a candidate understanding of Ben’s prior turn formatted with interrogative syntax and a negative polarity item. In contrast to declarative understanding displays, interrogatively formatted inferences are not prefaced with change-of-state tokens indexing an independent understanding. Thus, interrogative RfCs require subsequent (dis)confirmation to a greater extent. This is in line with the idea that interrogative questions propose a steeper epistemic gradient than declarative questions (Heritage and Raymond 2012).
Extract 6: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:07:50 – 00:07:52), No. 57
01 | Paul: | kÜmmst | da (.) | kÜmmst | da | NICH | mit | tousAmm- | |
come_you.2SG | there | come_you.2SG | there | not | with | together | |||
You’re not coming together | |||||||||
02 | Ben: | < < f>↑nä>; | |||||||
No (way) |
In only 4.5% of the data (n = 9/200), RfCs are designed with an SOV structure (subordinate clause), like in Extract (7). Ben launches a topic change to an old photo of a mutual aunt and uncle’s wedding party. Within a side sequence, Helga starts a remedy of the referred event by deploying an RfC in SOV structure (line 01), which is minimally confirmed by Ben in line 02.
Extract 7: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:16:06 – 00:16:07), No. 61
01 | Helga: | wo | de | da | an | FRIEN | sind? |
Where | they | there | are | celebrating | |||
Where they are celebrating | |||||||
02 | Ben: | ja; | |||||
Yes |
Elliptical confirmables make up only a small part of the corpus (n = 7/200, 3.5%). Consider (8). Concerning the social actions that elliptical RfCs and RfCs formatted as subordinate clauses accomplish, no clear picture has emerged in the analysis.
Extract 8: LoG-BÖR09_11 (00:01:04 – 00:01:08), No. 125
01 | Walter: | SESShunnert | to | mInn | also? |
Six hundred | to | little | so | ||
So, six hundred (euros) to little | |||||
02 | Frank: | wEnn überHAUPT; | |||
If at all |
In sum, in LoG RfC designs are typically formatted with declarative and phrasal syntax, but also – to a lesser extent – with interrogative syntax, subordinate clauses, or ellipticals.
4.2 Polarity
Research on English has shown that polarity influences the preference constraints and the epistemic stance display of polar questions (on reversed polarity questions, refer to the study by Koshik (2002), and on negatively polarized questions [NPQs], refer to the study by Heritage and Raymond (2021)). NPQs in English can be designed with interrogative or declarative syntax and are supposed to be tilted toward polarity-matched ‘no’-responses. However, Heritage (2002) has shown that negative interrogatives beginning with frames such as Isn’t it, Don’t you or modal phrases like Shouldn’t you X are different from NPQs with regard to the level of preference organization as they strongly invite affirmative responses. Epistemically, these assertive negative interrogatives differ from ‘questioning’ NPQs by (a) referring to shared knowledge, thereby not displaying a relative epistemic gradient to a matter at hand, and (b) the following response design, where responses only briefly acknowledge their interrogative packaging. In sum, specific modulations can have an impact on the preference organization of questions with negative polarity items.
In the LoG data, RfCs are predominantly formatted with positive polarity (n = 176/200; 88%); RfCs with negative polarity occur in only a limited number of cases (n = 24/200; 12%). Table 2 outlines the lexical items of negative polarity in LoG. In 87.5% of the cases (n = 21/24), the item nich (‘not’) is used for marking negative polarity in LoG, followed by the negative pronoun/article kein (‘no’) and the negative adverb nix (‘nothing’). The item nich falls into two distinct classes regarding its semantic and syntactic scope: it is used as (1) a negation particle (n = 18) and (2) a modal particle (n = 3). The following analyses will focus on these two usages of nich in RfCs and their preference organization. RfCs with the negation particle nich in LoG are directed to states of affairs that are unlikely by virtue of prior talk and thus inferential in nature (Heritage and Raymond 2021, 46–51, Drew 2018; see also Section 4.4). Consider again Extract (6). Ben and Paul are talking about their acquaintance, Margot. In lines 02–03, Ben reacts to Paul’s information request (line 01) with two epistemic disclaimers (lines 02–03). In line 04, Paul tries again by deploying the RfC kümmst da nich mit tousamen (‘you’re not coming together’). Based on his understanding of the just-prior turn, Paul marks a contact between Ben and Margot as unlikely. Constructing this RfC with the negative polarity item nich (‘not’) displays an orientation toward a ‘no’-type answer. Ben confirms the RfC in line 05 with the response token nä (‘no’). In sum, all NPQs with the negative particle nich (‘not’) are formatted with either declarative or interrogative syntax. When NPQs are confirmed in LoG, they are responded to with a polarity-matched ‘no’-type response token (Extract 14 shows a disconfirming response to a prior NPQ).
Negative polarity marking in LoG RfCs
Negative polarity marker | Frequency (total n = 24) |
---|---|
nich/ni (‘not’) | 21 (87.5%) |
kein[HG]/kien[LG] (‘no’) | 2 (8.3%) |
nix (‘nothing’) | 1 (4.2%) |
Extract 6: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:07:46 – 00:07:54), No. 57
01 | Paul: | (0.6) wu cheit DE eegentlIch; | ||||||||
How is she doing | ||||||||||
02 | Ben: | (0.6) kAnn ik di NICH seggen;= | ||||||||
I can’t tell | ||||||||||
03 | = ik WEET nich; | |||||||||
I don’t know | ||||||||||
04 | Paul: | kÜmmst | da (.) | kÜmmst | da | NICH | mit tousAmm- | |||
come_you.2SG | there | come_you.2SG | there | not.NEG.PRT | with together | |||||
You’re not coming together | ||||||||||
05 | Ben: | <<f>↑nä>; | ||||||||
No (way) | ||||||||||
06 | (0.6) <<p > nä:> °h; | |||||||||
No | ||||||||||
07 | DE- | |||||||||
She | ||||||||||
08 | (0.7) hEbbt us dat lEwen TO schwor makt; | |||||||||
She made our lives too difficult |
On the other hand, RfCs with the modal particle nich (‘not’) are directed to states of affairs that speakers treat as (highly) likely. In its function as a modal particle, nich (‘not’) has lost its negative semantic scope and therefore its negative polarity in the course of grammaticalization (Thurmair 1989, 160–3). Compared to RfCs with negation particles, these RfCs are different with regard to preference organization, as they are tilted towards a ‘yes’-type response. All of the nich (‘not’) modal particles occur in RfCs formatted with interrogative syntax. Consider (9). In line 01, Lukas launches an RfC regarding the mode of transportation Tina and Theo used on their last vacation. Both confirm the RfC in lines 02 and 03 with a ‘yes’-response token. Thus, RfCs with the modal particle nich (‘not’) are not to be counted as NPQs in the sense of Heritage and Raymond (2021).
Extract 9: LoG-BÖR01_07 (00:14:39 – 00:14:43), No. 32
01 | Lukas: | wAs | dat | nich | _n | dOppelstocking | BUS (-) | do, |
Was.SG | that.3SG | not.PRT(modal) | a | double-decker | bus | there | ||
Wasn’t that a double-decker bus | ||||||||
02 | Theo: | ja; | ||||||
Yes | ||||||||
03 | Tina: | jo;= | ||||||
Yes | ||||||||
04 | =do hAm_wi INsätten; | |||||||
We were on it |
As can be seen, making a B-event statement by means of negative polarity is applied (a) rarely and (b) with a small spectrum of lexical items in LoG. The item nich is used in two different ways inviting different response types. RfCs with the negation particle nich are directed to states of affairs that are treated as unlikely, meaning they are tilted towards a ‘no’-response, as previously described for NPQs. However, RfCs with the modal particle nich are tilted towards a ‘yes’-type response, comparable with Heritage’s (2002) negative interrogatives. The difference between Heritage’s (2002) negative interrogatives and LoG RfCs is that the first is treated as accomplishing opinion statements to an object of common knowledge, while the latter is still understood as questioning in the information-seeking sense.
4.3 Modulation
Compared to negative polarity, marking epistemic modulation in RfCs with modal particles, modal words or modal phrases is more pronounced in LoG, with modulations occurring in approximately a third of all cases (n = 60/200; 30%). In five of those instances, two modal items occur in one RfC, resulting in a slightly higher total number of markers (n = 65).
Table 3 provides an overview of the lexical elements that serve as modal markers in LoG RfCs. On the one hand, the data suggest a structural convergence with HG lexical material due to variety contact (see also Goss and Salmons (2000) on the loss of modal particles in long-term language contact). The HG modal particles ja (‘yes’) and doch (‘yes’) are the most frequent resources. Moreover, the modal particle nich(t) (‘not’) and the modal phrase ich glaube/ik glöw (‘I believe’) are also typical means of modulations in LoG RfCs. With the modal particle ja (‘yes’), speakers activate a communal or personal common ground in RfCs, indexing that the presented knowledge is shared and highly likely (see Reinecke (2018) on ja (‘yes’) in HG). Consider (10). In line 01, Paul deploys a declarative + tag RfC with the modal particle ja (‘yes’), indexing shared knowledge and a relatively strong assumption about the proposition.
Modulation of RfCs with epistemic markers in LoG
Epistemic marker | Frequency (total n = 65) |
---|---|
ja (‘yes’, modal particle) | 20 |
doch (‘yes’, modal particle) | 18 |
nich(t) (‘not’, modal particle) | 7 |
denn/dann (‘because’, modal particle) | 5 |
glöw ik/glaub ich (‘I think’, modal phrase) | 3 |
wall/wohl (‘probably’, modal particle) | 3 |
jetzt (‘now’, modal particle) | 2 |
hal (‘just’, modal particle) | 1 |
bloß (‘only’, modal particle) | 1 |
eigentlich (‘actually’, modal word) | 1 |
eventuell (‘possibly’, modal word) | 1 |
nu (‘now’, modal particle) | 1 |
normalerweise (‘usually’, modal word) | 1 |
siker (‘sure’, modal word) | 1 |
Extract 10: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:07:44 – 00:07:46), No. 56
01 | Paul: | nohEr | kam | SANdra | ja; | =ne- |
After that | came | Sandra | yes.PRT | QT_NE | ||
After that, Sandra came; right | ||||||
02 | Ben: | ja; | ||||
Yes |
The modal particle doch (‘yes’) is also deployed as a means of marking common ground in LoG RfCs, strongly committing to a proposition (Pittner 2007, 75–6). Only in a few cases, speakers contradict a prior turn by using doch (Extract 15). Consider (11). With the RfC in lines 01–02, Ben initiates an activity of co-remembering by referring to an event in a club called Eiskümmel (‘ice cumin’), at which Paul is presumed to have met his wife Sandra for the first time. The modal particle doch indexes this situation as part of the common ground.
Extract 11: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:16:34 – 00:16:39), No. 66
01 | Ben: | do | hEs | du | doch | SANdra | kennenlernt; | ||
There | have.2SG.AUX | you.SG | PRT | Sandra | met.PST.PCTP | ||||
There you met Sandra | |||||||||
02 | mit EISkümmel; | ||||||||
With ice cumin | |||||||||
At the ice cumin club | |||||||||
03 | Paul: | (0.8) <<f>ik>? | |||||||
Me | |||||||||
04 | Ben: | (0.5) <<f > ↑`JA>; | |||||||
Yes | |||||||||
05 | Paul: | <<f>NÄ nä [nä]1>; | |||||||
No no no |
On the other hand, Table 3 reveals LoG-specific modal markers which are not applied in HG (see Deppermann et al. 2024). This includes the modal particles wall [LoG]/wohl [HG] (‘probably’) and nu (‘now’). Weber (2020b) shows that with the modal particles wall [LoG]/wohl [HG], LoG speakers can index an epistemic stance towards the assumed high probability of a matter at hand ([K+] stance; Section 2). Consider (12).
Extract 12: LoG-BÖR01_08 (00:02:18 – 00:02:25), No. 02
01 | Tina: | dessen (.) MÜLler, | |||||
This Müller (name of the teacher) | |||||||
02 | de wOhnt ja in VREden; | ||||||
He lives in Vreden (Westphalian village) | |||||||
03 | (0.6) | ||||||
04 | Theo: | du | KENNST | de | wall; | =nich? | |
You.SG | know.2SG | him | PRT | NICH_QT | |||
You know him (well); right? | |||||||
05 | den (.) den MÜLler- | ||||||
This this Müller (name) | |||||||
06 | da LEHrer hier, | ||||||
The teacher here | |||||||
07 | (0.8) | ||||||
08 | Theo: | von VREden kummt de; | |||||
He is from Vreden | |||||||
09 | (0.4) | ||||||
10 | Jakob: | <<p> joa,> | |||||
Yes (mitigated) |
In lines 01–02, Tina speaks to Jakob about a teacher who offers LoG courses for children, providing his name and his origin. She frames this knowledge as part of the common ground by using the modal particle ja (‘yes’). After a short delay, Theo, who also has knowledge about this teacher, adds an RfC in line 04 with the modal particle wall and the tag nich (‘not’). Theo expects Jakob to know the person in question, thus treating Tina’s action of informing Jakob as inappropriate.[2] However, Theo’s following pursuit, Jakob’s delay in responding, and his qualified response joa (‘yes (mitigated)’) in line 10 show that Jakob does not have the expected knowledge about the teacher that Theo presupposes.
In sum, LoG speakers deploy modal markers frequently in order to index epistemic stances within RfC actions. Thereby, structural resemblances between LoG and HG due to variety contact but also LoG-specific markers in the question design of RfCs are noticeable.
4.4 Inference marking
Section 4.2 reveals that RfCs with negative polarity are mainly used when formulating inferences from prior talk. There are other linguistic resources in LoG, which overtly mark RfCs as inferential actions. Following Drew (2018), this article understands inferences as ubiquitous interactional actions, where a speaker attributes an implication to a prior speaker’s turn. Overall, RfCs in LoG are only rarely marked as inferences (n = 19/200; 9.5%). Table 4 provides the different lexical resources that LoG speakers apply to introduce inferential displays. Most of these resources are also deployed in HG, including more implicit markers (e.g., also (‘so’; n = 3)) as well as explicitly attributing phrases (e.g., du meinst/meenste (‘you mean’; n = 2)).
Inference marking in LoG RfCs
Inference markers | Frequency (total n = 19) |
---|---|
achso/so a (‘oh I see’; change-of-state tokens) | 5 |
also (‘so’) | 3 |
ach (ja) (change-of-state token) | 3 |
ah (‘oh’; change-of-state tokens) | 2 |
dann (‘then’/‘so’) | 2 |
du meinst/meenste (‘you mean’) | 2 |
ich dachte (‘I thought’) | 1 |
oh (‘oh’, change-of-state token) | 1 |
a So (‘oh’) is counted as a phonetically reduced variant of achso (‘oh’) as they both mainly occur as prefaces to understanding displays with similar prosodic details (achso and so are deployed as separate TCUs, prosodically not integrated into the following RfC, with falling intonation). It is unlikely that so is to be considered as a variant of the conjunction also (‘so’), as also is used prosodically integrated into the RfC and shares no prosodic or sequential details with so (‘oh’) in the data.
For the LoG data, it is noticeable that speakers frequently use change-of-state tokens as explicit indexes of inferential actions. Extract (13) gives an example of an achso (‘oh I see’)-plus-RfC format. Ben informs Paul about the professional career of an acquaintance’s daughter (lines 01–03). In line 04, Paul reacts with the overt understanding marker achso (‘oh I see’; Golato 2010, 157–61), equipped with accentuation on the second syllable and falling intonation in a separate TCU. After that, he deploys a candidate understanding in line 05. In the LoG data, achso-plus-RfC formats are always designed as inferences of prior turns-at-talk and therefore as understanding displays (Heritage 1984, 320–3).
Extract 13: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:02:40 – 00:02:49), No. 52
01 | Ben: | un äh (.) äh DEren dOchtern äh- | ||
And their daugther | ||||
02 | de_s in_äh MÜNchen, | |||
She is (works) in Munich | ||||
03 | °h (-) mh bi de (-) BAYrische hypo, | |||
At the bavarian hypo (bank) | ||||
04 | Paul: | achSO; | ||
Oh I see | ||||
05 | BANKmens[chen]; | |||
Banking people | ||||
06 | Ben: | [bank]- | ||
Bank | ||||
07 | BANKmenschen;= | |||
Banking people | ||||
08 | =ˇ[ja], | |||
Yes |
In sum, RfCs in the LoG data are only rarely (linguistically) marked as inferences from a prior speaker’s turn. It is, however, worth highlighting that the speakers use change-of-state tokens frequently as inferential markers. LoG seems to provide almost no variety-specific resources for the explicit marking of inferences. Speakers therefore fall back on HG lexemes.
4.5 Connectives
In 37.5% of all cases, LoG speakers introduce RfC sequences with connectives like conjunctions, subjunctions, discourse markers, or change-of-state tokens (n = 75/200). Table 5 reveals the different connective formats. The conjunctions ower [LoG]/aber [HG] (‘but’; n = 16) and un(d) (‘and’; n = 15) show the highest absolute frequency in the data. Moreover, change-of-state tokens are used frequently as connectives in the LoG data (n = 12). In the following, we focus on the most frequent conjunction ower/awer [LoG] (‘but’) as a turn-initial and TCU-initial practice in LoG.
Connectives in LoG RfCs
Connective | Frequency (total n = 75) | ||
---|---|---|---|
ower/awer/aber (‘but’) | 16 | was jetzt? (‘what now’) | 1 |
un(d) (‘and’) | 15 | hm_hm (continuer) | 1 |
achso/so (change-of-state token) | 5 | oh (‘oh’, change-of-state token) | 1 |
ja (‘yes’) | 4 | ja weil (‘yes because’) | 1 |
oder (‘or’) | 4 | weil (‘because’) | 1 |
ja aber/ower (‘yes but’) | 4 | ja wenn (‘yes when’) | 1 |
ach (ja) (change-of-state token) | 4 | ne? (question tag) | 1 |
also (‘so’) | 3 | nocher (‘then’) | 1 |
ah (change-of-state token) | 2 | uk (‘also’) | 1 |
ja und (‘yes and’) | 2 | ich dachte (‘I thought’) | 1 |
dann (‘then’/‘so’) | 2 | wie? (‘how’) | 1 |
ja ja (‘yes yes’) | 2 | ja stimmt (‘yes right’) | 1 |
In the majority of cases, turn-initial ower/awer (‘but’) in LoG is used as a conjunction marking a departure from the ongoing course of action, as Extract (1) shows. In this example, Heidi marks a departure from the ongoing sequence and manages a recipient-oriented topic change (Schegloff 2007, 170) by means of the turn-initial conjunction ower (‘but’). After a [K–]-display of Annika, Extract (14) starts immediately afterward, where Heidi tries a second time, explaining that she saw Annika passing by in the car. With the RfC in line 02, Heidi deploys an awer (‘but’)-prefaced inference in the TCU-initial position. Thereby, Heidi launches a different line of talk that presents her attribution to Annika’s behavior as a lack of mutual perception and thus a presupposed [K–] status of Annika. After this second proffer, Annika embraces the topic by strongly disconfirming Heidi’s presupposition in lines 03–05 with a [K+] display.
Extract 14: LoG-HES02_06 (00:01:31 – 00:01:34), No. 78
01 | Heidi: | as ik HEEM föhr; | ||||||
As I drove home | ||||||||
02 | awer | du | HAS | mi | ni | seijn; | =ne, | |
But | you.2SG | have.AUX | me | not | seen.PST.PTCP; | NE_QT | ||
But you didn’t see me; right? | ||||||||
03 | Annika: | <<f> DOCH; | ||||||
Yes | ||||||||
04 | STIMMT>; | |||||||
Right | ||||||||
05 | ik hab noch SEIJN, | |||||||
I did see (you) |
In some cases, however, turn-initial ower/awer (‘but’) marks a contradiction to a prior turn-at-talk. Consider (15). Heinz, his sister Anna, and his niece Svenja are talking about a priest from the village. Anna disaffirms Heinz’s request for information in line 03 with the negative response particle nä (‘no’) and a concessive format, leading to a sequence closure. After a short delay, Heinz resumes the topic by deploying an RfC, prefaced by the sequential conjunction aber (‘but’) in line 04. In contrast to turn-initial ower (‘but’) in Extract (1), with aber (‘but’) in (15) Heinz directly ties his RfC to the prior sequence and the ongoing course of action by contrasting his knowledge with Anna’s prior turn. By co-constructing it with the modal particle doch (‘yes’), Heinz displays a strong commitment to the proposition.
Extract 15: LoG-HES01_07_09 (00:05:47 – 00:05:54), No. 98
01 | Heinz: | kann he dann PLATT? | ||||||||
Does he speak Low German? | ||||||||||
02 | IS dat (.) dat IS [doch]_n- | |||||||||
Is that he is a | ||||||||||
03 | Anna: | [nä:]; | ||||||||
No | ||||||||||
(omission 00:05:49–00:05:51; concessive format + sequence closure) | ||||||||||
04 | Heinz: | aber | de | kUmmt | doch | hier | ut | EMSland; | =[ne], | |
But | he | comes | PRT | here | from | Emsland; | NE_QT | |||
But he is from Emsland; =right? | ||||||||||
05 | Svenja: | [ut] WERLte; | ||||||||
From Werlte |
In sum, conjunctions are part of LoG RfCs formats in about one-third of all cases. Focusing on awer/ower (‘but’), the analysis shows that it can be used both as a turn- and a TCU-initial resource indexing (a) a departure from the ongoing course of action (Extract 1, line 03), (b) a contradiction to a prior speaker’s turn (Extract 15, line 04), or (c) a projection of a contrasting proposition within a speaker’s turn (Extract 14, line 02). All uses index a contrast in one way or another, either to a previous turn-internal proposition, a prior turn, or to a prior topic.
4.6 Tags
In LoG, RfCs are frequently equipped with tags in 45% of the cases (n = 90/200). Table 6 illustrates the different tag formats that occur in RfC question designs in the data.
Tags in RfC sequences in LoG
Tags | Frequency (total n = 90) |
---|---|
ne (‘not’) | 69 (77%) |
nich (‘not’)a | 11 (12%) |
oder (‘or’) | 6 (7%) |
oder wat (‘or what’) | 2 (2%) |
oder wann (‘or when’) | 1 (1%) |
kann dat (‘is that possible’) | 1 (1%) |
aWe found no instances of nech (‘not’) tag variants in the LoG data.
With regard to the formal resources, only five different lexical items/phrases are discernible: ne (‘not’), nich (‘not’), oder (‘or’), oder wat (‘or what’), oder wann (‘or when’), and kann dat (‘is that possible’). Tags like wa or woll, considered typical Northern German tags (Section 2), do not occur in the data. However, this is in line with Harren’s (2001, 104–5) study on wa, which shows a frequent occurrence of this tag with assessments and not with RfCs.
Concerning the frequency ratios, the supraregional ne-tag prevails in the LoG data (n = 69/90; 77%) followed by the lexically similar, more regional tag nich (n = 11/90; 12%). While Harren (2001) shows a frequent co-occurrence of ne-turns with modal particles in HG, modulations in tag-attached RfCs in LoG are found in only 39% of cases (n = 27/69). In line with Harren (2001, 128), the most frequent co-occurring modal particles with ne-tagged RfCs are ja (‘yes’; n = 12) and doch (‘yes’; n = 8). Both serve as markers of an established common ground (Section 4.3). With respect to nich, the relative frequency ratios look similar: 36% (n = 4/11) of all nich-tagged RfCs are constructed with modal particles, while 64% are not (n = 7/11). Sequential analyses of RfCs with ne- and nich-tags in the LoG data show that both exhibit a wide range of similar social actions. Thus, the deployment of ne and nich in RfCs is not driven by the accomplishment of different social actions in LoG. In addition, ne and nich are deployed with similar final intonation that is predominantly rise-to-mid and rise-to-high intonation, as indicated in Table 10. In sum, the analyses could not reveal a robust link between final intonation contour and social action. However, for the second most frequent tag, nich (‘not’; n = 11), an age effect is evident in the data, as only older speakers use nich, while younger speakers exclusively use the tag ne. This apparent-time comparison[3] supports the hypothesis of a phonetic erosion from nich to ne, outlined in Section 2, at least for LoG RfC actions. Accordingly, variety contact might cause a decline of the northern regional variant nich in favor of the supraregional variant ne.
Compared to ne (‘not’) and nich (‘not’), the tag oder (‘or’) with only 7% of the cases (n = 6/90) is not strongly conventionalized in LoG interaction. Almost all oder-RfCs in LoG are responded to with minimal responses. In only one instance, the oder-tagged RfC solicits topic talk and thus a non-minimal answer. Moreover, compared to HG, there is less of a connection between the final intonation of oder-RfCs and the complexity of the following actions in LoG (Section 4.7). Again, an age effect in the usage of the oder-tag is observable, as it is deployed only by younger speakers. It is therefore likely that the oder-tag is an interference from HG and a rather recent tag in LoG.
In sum, while tags are frequently used resources in LoG RfCs, the spectrum of items that serve as tags is noticeably small. The deployment of the two most frequent tags, ne and nich, is not driven by action or prosody. As noted, an age effect in the use of the tags nich and oder is evident. The apparent-time comparison for nich supports the hypothesis of a phonetic erosion from nich to ne. Accordingly, variety contact might cause a decline of the more regional variant nich in favor of the supraregional variant ne. The tag oder is mainly used by younger speakers and does not play a decisive role in the LoG RfC design (yet).
4.7 Prosodic design
In addition to the different tag-types, the attachment of tags also impacts the prosodic design of RfCs. Table 7 reveals that the majority of RfC confirmables[4] with or without a tag are equipped with a final falling intonation contour in LoG. However, confirmables without a tag show a higher relative frequency ratio of rising contours. In addition, Table 8 shows the distribution of tags with regard to prosodic integration into the anchor sentence (core proposition). In 98% of the cases, tags are not prosodically integrated. Moreover, Table 9 reveals that tags mainly occur with a final rising contour in 90% of the cases. A more fine-grained prosodic analysis of the tags ne and nich, analyzed in Section 4.6, reveals that they are predominantly deployed with similar final intonation, namely rise-to-mid and – to a lesser degree – rise-to-high intonation (Table 10). One exception in the data is the tag oder was (‘or what’), which is always produced as a prosodically integrated tag. In LoG, all non-integrated tags are latched to the confirmable such that no notable pause between the confirmable and the tag occurs. Overall, the data do not contain any cases of tags as resources to accomplish response pursuits after silences.
Final intonation of the confirmable in LoG
Final intonation confirmable (n = 200) | Final intonation confirmable without a tag (n = 110/200) | Final intonation confirmable with a tag (n = 90/200) | |
---|---|---|---|
Rise | 56 (28%) | 51 (46%) | 5 (6%) |
Level | 1 (0.5%) | 1 (1%) | 0 (0%) |
Fall | 143 (71.5%) | 58 (53%) | 85 (94%) |
Prosodic integration of tags into confirmable in LoG
ne (n = 69) | nich (n = 11) | oder (n = 6) | oder wat (n = 2) | oder wann (n = 1) | kann dat (n = 1) | Σ (n = 90) | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Non-integrated | 69 (100%) | 11 (100%) | 6 (100%) | 0 (0%) | 1 (100%) | 1 (100%) | 88 (98%) |
Integrated | 0 (0%) | 0 (0%) | 0 (0%) | 2 (100%) | 0 (0%) | 0 (0%) | 2 (2%) |
Final contour of tag (only non-integrated tags) in LoG
ne (n = 69) | nich (n = 11) | oder (n = 6) | oder wann (n = 1) | kann dat (n = 1) | Σ (n = 88) | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Rise | 65 (94%) | 10 (91%) | 3 (50%) | 0 (0%) | 1 (100%) | 79 (90%) |
Level | 4 (6%) | 1 (9%) | 1 (17%) | 0 (0%) | 0 (0%) | 6 (7%) |
Fall | 0 (0%) | 0 (0%) | 2 (33%) | 1 (100%) | 0 (0%) | 3 (3%) |
Final intonation of the tags ne and nich in LoG
ne (n = 69) | nich (n = 11) | |
---|---|---|
Rise-to-mid | 50 (72%) | 7 (64%) |
Rise-to-high | 13 (19%) | 2 (18%) |
Step-up | 2 (3%) | 1 (9%) |
Level | 4 (6%) | 1 (9%) |
Concerning RfCs with a tag, a stable pattern of final falling confirmables with an appended final rising is documented in the data. Notable exceptions concern oder (‘or’), and oder was (‘or what’), for which level and falling contours can be observed. Contrary to the study on HG oder by Drake (2016) and König (2020), the only oder-tagged RfC in the LoG data, which solicits topic talk, is not deployed with a level contour – as assumed by both studies – but with falling intonation. Thus, a robust link between the final intonation of oder (‘or’) and subsequent actions cannot be proclaimed for LoG RfCs. This may also be due to the small number of instances and would have to be investigated in more detail in a follow-up study.
5 Resources for responses to RfCs in LoG
5.1 Responsive actions
When speakers ask polar questions like RfCs in interaction, they make confirmation or disconfirmation relevant as a next action (e.g., Raymond 2003, Enfield et al. 2019). In LoG interactions, RfCs predominantly receive confirmatory responses (n = 141/200; 70.5%), with 60% being response tokens[5] (n = 85/141), 26% full(-expanded) repeats (n = 36/141), and 14% token + repeat combinations (n = 20/141). Disconfirming responses occur rather rarely in the data (n = 19/200; 9.5%), with 79% being response tokens (n = 15/19), 10.5% full-expanded repeats (n = 2/19), and 10.5% token + repeat combinations (n = 2/19). Only four RfCs do not receive a response in the data (n = 4/200; 2%). Since the data could only be analyzed in audio form (see Section 3), these four instances might include pure embodied responses like nods. This finding may therefore be biased due to the data format. Moreover, in 18% of the cases, responses neither confirm, nor disconfirm the previous RfC (n = 36/200; n = 8 response tokens, n = 2 full(-expanded) repeats, n = 1 token + repeat combination, n = 25 other types). These consist of epistemic disclaimers (e.g., ik weet nich ‘I don’t know’), conditional confirmations (e.g., joa; Gipper and Groß 2024), additional information (e.g., un die dochter ‘and the daughter’), concessive response formats (e.g., ausgeschlossen is dat nich, aber ‘this is not excluded, but’), ja aber (‘yes but’)-constructions (Szczepek Reed 2015), and corrections (e.g., A: sechs ‘six’?; B: sieben ‘seven’). The following analyses in Sections 5.2–5.6 will be based on the 196 instances where a response follows the RfC action. Consequently, the denominator will be 196 instead of 200.
5.2 Response tokens
Literature on answering systems distinguishes two semantic systems, a truth-value and a polarity system, as well as two-formal systems, a non-echo (‘interjection type[6]’)-system and an echo (‘repetition’)-system (Jones 1999, 42). However, Enfield et al. (2019, 280) criticize this rigid division into interjection vs repeat systems, since most languages use both formats in interaction, just with varying degrees of frequency. Following Raymond (2003), RfCs as a subtype of polar questions prefer equivalents of ‘yes’- or ‘no’-response types. To this point, research distinguishes between marked and unmarked interjection options (Heritage and Raymond 2005, 2012, Stivers 2011, 2022, 91–121). With unmarked (minimal) response tokens, speakers just do the action of (plain) confirmation to a prior question (Raymond 2003). Marked response tokens can be subdivided into upgraded, downgraded, and acquiescent interjections (Stivers 2022, 93), challenging the asking itself, the answerability or the action agenda of a prior question. In this section, we will analyze different response tokens and the interactional work they do as part of the ‘answer possibility space’ (Stivers 2022, 3) in LoG interaction. We will learn that both response formats play a strong role in the data.
In 67% of the cases in the LoG data, the responses include at least one response token of a ‘yes’- or ‘no’-type (n = 132/196 [with repeat combinations; for details on the minimality of response tokens see Section 5.5]; n = 105 confirming; n = 17 disconfirming; n = 10 neither confirming nor disconfirming; n = 109/196 [56% without repeat combinations]). In the following, we will focus on confirming and disconfirming response tokens (n = 122). Research on answers to polar questions stresses the importance of a question’s polarity for the preference organization and the response constraints (e.g., Jones 1999, 8–14). Thus, Table 11 first provides the confirming and disconfirming response tokens and their variants in response to RfCs with positive polarity (n = 104). The quantitative assignment is based on the first response token of the responsive action.
Response tokens used for (dis)confirming RfCs with positive polarity in LoG
Response tokens | Frequency (n = 104) | Variants and combinations | |
---|---|---|---|
‘Yes’-type responses (confirming) | ja ‘yes [HG]’ | 84 | ja (49), jo (13), ja ja (7), ja siker (‘yes sure‘) (4), jau (2), ja eben (‘yes as I said‘) (2), ja genau (‘yes exactly‘) (2), ja hm_hm (1), ja ja ja (1), ja klar (‘yes of course‘) (1), ja richtig (‘yes correct‘) (1), ja hm (1) |
jo ‘yes [LG]’ | |||
jau ‘yes [LG]’ | |||
richtig ‘correct’ | 1 | ||
hm_hm | 3 | hm_hm ja (1) | |
genau ‘exactly’ | 1 | genau ja (1) | |
‘No’-type responses (disconfirming) | nä ‘no’ | 6 | nä nä nä (2) |
nee ‘no’ | 6 | ||
nein ‘no’ | 3 | nein nein nein (1) |
The data show that RfCs with positive polarity are predominantly confirmed with variants of ‘yes’-response tokens. When studying variety contact of response particles, the assignment of response tokens to one or another variety is methodologically challenging. The historical development and the regional distribution of response tokens are important factors to consider. Regarding the variety contact between HG and LoG, Table 11 reveals that the HG token ja (‘yes’) prevails in the data, followed by the LoG variant jo (‘yes’; Damme [2015, column 463] for the classification of jo ‘yes’ as a LoG response token). Similar to modal markers (Section 4.3), a growing structural convergence of LoG toward HG is observable, especially when it comes to combinations of response tokens (e.g., ja genau ‘yes exactly’ or ja eben ‘yes as I said’). In contrast to these forms of structural convergence, the unmarked response token hm_hm, which Deppermann et al. (2024) describe as very common for HG, is not frequently deployed in the LoG data. Regarding disconfirming responses in Table 11, the tokens nee (‘no’) and nä (‘no’) prevail. Historically, nee [ne:] (‘no’) has its roots in LoG (nēn in Middle LoG; see Kluge and Mitzka 1960, 506). However, today, it is used as a supraregional response token (Elspaß and Möller 2004; see also Imo 2017 and Deppermann et al. 2024 on nee in HG data). As for nä (‘no’), there are no empirical studies on its regional distribution or variety-based specifics. In the study by Damme (2015, column 463), nä (‘no’) appears in a lexical entry in the Westphalian LoG dictionary. Its origin, however, seems to be in the Upper Saxon area (Adelung 1798, column 463). Today, nä [nɛ] (‘no’) also seems to be used both in LoG and in HG (Imo 2017 on nä in HG). In the following, we will not treat the use of nee (‘no’) and nä (‘no’) as variety specific. The HG variant nein (‘no’) occurs infrequently in the data, which is in line with existing research (Imo 2017, Deppermann et al. 2024).
In the LoG data, the HG variant ja (‘yes’) is deployed as both a minimal response and a non-minimal response, predominantly in combination with a repeat (see Section 5.5 for a discussion of token + repeat combinations). Minimal HG ja (‘yes’) occurs as an unmarked closure-implicative token in two sequential environments. First, it is used in series of little questions, as Extract (16) shows. Jakob and Theo are looking at an old picture of Theo’s parental home. In lines 02 and 04, HG ja (‘yes’) is used as a minimal response token to the previous RfC that prefers a minimal response. These occurrences follow the maxim described by Heritage and Raymond (2012, 184): ‘little questions get little answers’ (see also Heritage and Sorjonen 1994). In the majority of the cases, RfCs in this environment are formatted as tag questions.
Extract 16: LoG-BÖR01_08 (00:05:59 – 00:06:08), No. 5/6
01 | Jakob: | DAT is mÜllers FRED siene; =ne, | |
This belongs to <name>; right? | |||
02 | Theo: | (0.5) ((smacks)) ja; | |
Yes | |||
03 | Jakob: | un DÜT (-) DÜT is_n mEstfol hier; =ne, | |
And that that is a dung heap; isn‘t it? | |||
04 | Theo: | ja; | |
Yes |
Second, HG ja (‘yes’) as an unmarked response is deployed in understanding checks, realized as side sequences, or what Enfield et al. (2019, 284) call subordinate action sequences. Consider (17). In line 01, Tina manages a recipient-oriented topic change by deploying a telling question to Lukas on a surgery of his acquaintance Samuel. In lines 03–04, Lukas launches a side sequence to clarify person reference by proposing the origin of Samuel with an RfC formatted as a tag question. Tina minimally confirms Lukas’ RfC with HG ja (‘yes’), thus accepting the terms of the prior questioning and closing the side sequence. Lukas moves “quickly back to the main line of action” (Enfield et al. 2019, 291) and starts giving information about the surgery. RfCs prior to HG ja (‘yes’) are predominantly formatted as tag questions or – though less frequently – as phrases.
Extract 17: LoG-BÖR01_07 (00:01:55 – 00:02:03), No. 18
01 | Tina: | eeren sAmuel (.) was UK nu operIErt; | ||
(Your) Samuel underwent surgery; | ||||
02 | Lukas: | °h ja; | ||
Yes | ||||
03 | (0.3) an de (.) Usen SAmuel; | |||
Our Samuel | ||||
04 | dE in DÖRpen; [ni]ch? | |||
The one from Dörpen; right? | ||||
05 | Tina: | [ja]; | ||
Yes | ||||
06 | Lukas: | den SELben arzt den MI operiert hat- | ||
The same doctor who operated on me |
In contrast to HG ja (‘yes’), the LoG response token jo (‘yes’) is for the most part not used as a minimal response token, but in combination with other components – mostly repeats or marked tokens like in (18) (see also Extract 25 in Section 5.5). Prior to the extract, Helga tells Jakob about an LoG teacher from the neighboring village. In line 01, Jakob launches an RfC to clarify person reference, which Theo confirms with the LoG response token jo (‘yes’) and the marked token richtig (‘correct’) in line 03. In contrast to HG ja (‘yes’), LoG jo (‘yes’) is mainly deployed within marked interjection responses to RfCs, claiming agency and epistemic authority over a matter at hand.
Extract 18: LoG-BÖR01_08 (00:02:48 – 00:02:50), No. 4
01 | Jakob: | aber dE_s ja hier uk LEHrerin; | |
But she is a teacher here | |||
02 | Theo: | <<f> jo, | |
Yes | |||
03 | RICHtig;> | ||
Correct |
LoG jau (‘yes’) is deployed as an infrequent minimal response token. In contrast to LoG jo (‘yes’), jau (‘yes’) is more sequence closure implicative – mostly after an extended sequence as in (19). Gisela informs Sebastian in line 01 that the recording device is running. After a first possible sequence closure in line 04, Sebastian resumes the issue in line 06 with the RfC dann dö_t dat nau (‘so it works’), requesting confirmation regarding the proper functioning of the equipment. In line 07, Gisela confirms the RfC with the LoG response token jau (‘yes’), thereby (re-)confirming her prior proposition and closing the sequence. In comparison to HG ja (‘yes’), jau (‘yes’) closes extended sequences and is therefore used as a more marked token in its function as a sequence closure device.[7]
Extract 19: LoG-STEV02 (00:00:01 – 00:00:09), No. 132
01 | Gisela: | so JETZ löppt_et; | |
Okay now it works | |||
02 | Sebastian: | (0.7) ja? | |
Yes (really?) | |||
03 | Gisela: | wEnn (.) wenn DE teken do chOt; | |
When the digits are running there | |||
04 | Sebastian: | ja; | |
Yes | |||
05 | (1.5) | ||
06 | Sebastian: | dAnn DÖ_t dat nAU; | |
So it works; | |||
07 | Gisela: | (0.3) jau; | |
Yes | |||
08 | Sebastian: | (0.5) gut; | |
Okay |
Concerning disconfirming responses to RfCs, the supraregional token nee (‘no’) occurs as the most frequent unmarked response token in the LoG data. In the majority of cases, nee (‘no’) is deployed as a minimal response token prosodically integrated into the following TCU with no particular prosodic mark-up, as in (20). Prior to the extract, Anna tells Heinz that she will visit a mutual acquaintance for her birthday. In lines 01–02, Heinz deploys an RfC, insinuating that she is having a big party on the day of her actual birthday. Anna responds with nee (‘no’) that is prosodically integrated with the following disconfirming action. It is thus used in preface-position (Heritage 1998, 292), projecting same-speaker turn continuation.
Extract 20: LoG-HES01_09_07 (00:00:26 – 00:00:29), No. 86
01 | Heinz: | un de FIERT vandaage; | |||
And she is celebrating today | |||||
02 | UP_n dAch; | ||||
On her actual (birth)day | |||||
03 | Anna: | nee die | fiert | GAR | nich; |
No she_3.P.Sg. | celebrates | absolutely | not | ||
No she isn’t celebrating at all |
In contrast to nee (‘no’), the response token nä (‘no’) is frequently used as a marked response, challenging the presupposition or the askability of a prior question. Consider (21). The two siblings, Clara and Benno, discuss whether their uncle needs more care. In lines 01–03, Clara asks Benno if he knew whether their cousin would soon visit their uncle. After displaying resistance to the question’s agenda in line 04, Benno responds to the RfC of Clara in line 05 with the marked interjection nä (‘no’), rejecting the presupposition of the question that he could have knowledge about the matter at hand. A second attempt by Clara in lines 07–08 is also highly rejected by Benno with the HG response token nein (‘no’) in line 09.
Extract 21: LoG-LEV01 (00:15:39 – 00:23:06), No. 168
01 | Clara: | dat wOll ik di jetz GÜStern frOgn; | |
I wanted to ask you that yesterday | |||
02 | wat hEff use couSENK; | ||
What has our cousin | |||
03 | hEff de Irgendwie [AFF]- | ||
Has he something | |||
04 | Benno: | [!MI!] wulls du dat frogn? | |
You want to ask ME that? | |||
05 | Clara: | ja ih drEppet ja HÄUfiger mol; ne, | |
You meet from time to time, right? | |||
06 | Benno: | nä; | |
No | |||
07 | Clara: | biem (name of a bar), | |
At (name of a bar) | |||
08 | oder biem KORtenspeeln, | ||
Or when playing cards | |||
09 | Benno: | nein; | |
No |
Extract (21) indicates that speakers use HG nein (‘no’) as a marked response token highly rejecting a prior proposition. Consider also (22). In the preceding context, Tina, Theo’s wife, got up from the table to turn up the heat. Theo then addresses an RfC to Jakob, asking if he is cold. Jakob emphatically disconfirms the RfC with HG nein (‘no’), deployed with prosodic mark-up (increased loudness, rise-fall-contour). He adds an assessment (line 03) and a request for halting the action (lines 04–05).
Extract 22: LoG-BÖR01_08 (00:34:23 – 00:34:25), No. 14
01 | Theo: | Is di to KOLT? | |||
Are you cold? | |||||
02 | Jakob: | <<f, creaky voice>ˆNEIN;> | |||
No | |||||
03 | um gOttes WILlen; | ||||
For god’s sake | |||||
04 | (1.5) denn LAT dat- | ||||
Then turn it | |||||
05 | (1.2) BLOSS ut; | ||||
PRT | off |
In contrast to RfCs with positive polarity, RfCs with negative polarity are confirmed with variants of ‘no’-response tokens. Table 12 provides the different response tokens following RfCs with negative polarity in the LoG data.
Response tokens used for (dis)confirming RfCs with negative polarity in LoG
Response tokens | Frequency (n = 18) | Variants and combinations | |
---|---|---|---|
‘No’-type responses (confirming) | nee ‘no’ | 11 | nee; nee nee (1) |
nä ‘no’ | 5 | na; nä (1) | |
Disconfirming responses | doch | 1 | |
‘Yes’-type responses | jo ‘yes’ | 1 |
Concerning the different negative polarity items outlined in Section 4.2, RfCs with mere syntactic (e.g., nich) or lexical/derivational negation markers (e.g., kein, nix) show no difference in the preference for upcoming response tokens. With 61% of the cases, the supraregional variant nee (‘no’) is the most common way of confirming an RfC with negative polarity (n = 11/18), followed by nä (‘no’) in 28% of the cases (n = 5/18). Regarding nee (‘no’), considerable differences occur in responses to RfCs with negative and positive polarity. Consider (23). Heidi and Annika talk about their farsighted glasses. In lines 01–02, Annika invokes the common ground that Heidi is not as shortsighted as she is by using an RfC equipped with the modal particle ja (‘yes’). In line 03, Heidi confirms the RfC with the minimal response token nee (‘no’) with falling intonation. While nee (‘no’) following RfCs with positive polarity is predominantly deployed as a preface to other disconfirming actions, nee (‘no’) following RfCs with negative polarity is applied as an unmarked confirming response token in a TCU in its own right.
Extract 23: LoG-HES02_06 (00:11:32 – 00:11:35), No. 80
01 | Annika: | du bist ja auch nich GANZ so- | |||
You are not | |||||
02 | (0.2) | STARK | kurzsichtig | wie Ik;=ne- | |
As shortsighted as I am, right? | |||||
03 | Heidi: | (0.4) nee; | |||
No |
Nä (‘no’) following RfCs with negative polarity is commonly deployed with an affective stance toward the RfC proposition and at the same time contests the askability of the prior question, that is the question’s presupposition “that both yes and no are possible answers” (Stivers 2011, 86). Consider (24). Svenja talks about her struggle to stop smoking by naming typical situations in which she threatens to relapse from abstinence. In line 04, Svenja confirms Anna’s RfC with the response token nä (‘no’). She thus treats the alternative of the previous RfC that she could suffer a relapse as inconceivable. In sum, nä (‘no’) following RfCs with negative and positive polarity belong to the group of marked interjections (Stivers 2011). Prosodically, nä (‘no’) can be used with more (e.g., Extract 6) or less prosodic mark-up (e.g., Extracts 21 and 24) in LoG interaction.
Extract 24: LoG-HES01_07_09 (00:13:44 – 00:13:49), No. 105
01 | Svenja: | (0.5) un dann mÖchte_ik mi UK wall- | ||
And then I would also like to (light a cigarette) | ||||
02 | (0.6) mo [Ä:bn]- | |||
Just for a moment | ||||
03 | Anna: | [aber] das DEI_s nich; =ne? | ||
But you don't do that; don’t you? | ||||
04 | Svenja: | nä; | ||
No | ||||
05 | NÖ nö; | |||
No no |
Disconfirming responses to negative polar questions are designed with HG doch (e.g., Pittner 2007, Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018, 247–8). Wohl, which is also described as a typical disconfirming response token in LoG and North HG (Turco et al. 2014), was not found in the LoG data.[8] As for doch in HG, consider again (14). Heidi launches an RfC in line 02, presupposing that there are different knowledge states about her last encounter with Annika. Annika disconfirms the proposition with doch in line 03. She thus claims to have seen Heidi and counters the negative polarity of the prior RfC.
Extract 14: LoG-HES02_06 (00:01:31 – 00:01:32), No. 78 (shortened)
02 | Heidi: | awer du HAS mi ni seijn;=ne, | |
But you didn’t see me; right? | |||
03 | Annika: | <<f> DOCH; | |
Yes |
Besides confirming ‘no’-response tokens and the disconfirming item doch, Table 11 also shows one instance of a ‘yes’-type response token used to respond to RfCs with negative polarity. As analyzed in Section 4.2 (Extract 9), ‘yes’-response tokens mainly occur after RfCs with nich as a modal particle and therefore cannot be defined as proper NPQs.
Overall, the LoG data suggest a polarity response system, where the use of response token types is determined by the polarity of the prior RfC. In particular, the LoG response token system is a three-form system, which contains ‘yes’- and ‘no’-type tokens as well as additional forms like HG doch, which “counter the bias of a negative question” (Jones 1999, 42). Due to variety contact, LoG exhibits a large basic positive and negative response system, containing tokens that can be unequivocally characterized as HG (e.g., ja ‘yes’ or doch ‘yes (objecting)’) or as LoG (e.g., jo ‘yes’ and jau ‘yes’). Yet, other tokens are not variety specific (e.g., nee ‘no’ or nä ‘no’). As for non-variety-specific tokens, nee (‘no’) seems to be used as an unmarked token, while nä (‘no’) challenges the askability or the presuppositions of the previous RfC. Regarding variety-specific tokens, it is noticeable that HG response tokens serve as more unmarked ways of responding to a prior RfC, while LoG tokens are used in a more marked way (for an exception, see the use of nein [‘no’], which is also a marked response token in HG). However, we also see that LoG tokens persist more strongly in confirmations than in disconfirmations. Given that confirmations are preferred over disconfirmations (Stivers et al. 2009), a preference-induced effect is observable as the higher frequency of confirmations might enhance persistence with regard to the LoG ‘yes’-token types.[9]
5.3 Clusters of response tokens
In the LoG data, clusters show a low-frequency ratio (n = 20/132; 15%). They include forms like ja siker (‘yes sure’; n = 5), ja eben (n = 2), ja richtig (‘yes correct’; n = 1), ja genau (‘yes exactly’; n = 2), ja klar (‘yes sure’; n = 1), double sayings like ja ja (‘yes yes’; n = 7), and multiple sayings like nein nein nein (‘no no no’; n = 1) or nä nä nä (‘no no no’; n = 1).[10] All clusters do more than simply confirm the RfC. They reinforce the (dis-)confirmatory action, display epistemic primacy, or serve as devices to “properly halt course of action” (Stivers 2004, 260).
5.4 Position of the first response token
Section 5.2 reveals that in only 67% of the cases, the responses include one or more response token(s) in the LoG data (n = 132/196; including combinations). In the vast majority of cases, these response tokens occur in turn-initial position (n = 120/132; 91%). Eleven instances are used in the turn-final position, occurring mainly after repeats and being closure-implicative. Only in one instance is the response token deployed in mid-TCU-position.
5.5 Minimal and non-minimal responses
Answers containing a response token in the LoG data are designed either minimally, i.e., solo with a stand-alone response token (n = 43/132, 33%; e.g., Extracts 16 and 17), or non-minimally, i.e., a response token combined with other components (n = 89/132; 67%; e.g., Extract 9). Second response slots (Raymond 2013) in responses to RfCs accomplish many different actions in LoG interaction, e.g., assessments (e.g., Extract 22), corrections, further topic-related informings, accounts, or repeats. In the following, an in-depth analysis of response token + repeat combinations is provided (n = 23/132; 17%). In both combinations, response tokens are almost exclusively limited to confirming ‘yes’-type responses. By contrast, confirming ‘no’-response tokens or disconfirming ‘no’- response tokens are found rarely in combination with repeats. Thus, repeat + response token combinations predominantly accomplish confirmations in LoG interaction.
[‘yes’-token] + [repeat]
Extract (25) illustrates a ‘yes’-token + repeat combination in LoG interaction. In the preceding conversation, Svenja elaborates on an encounter with the local priest. In line 01, Heinz launches a phrasal RfC focusing on the origin of this priest. Svenja confirms the RfC with a [yes] + [repeat]-format. Using jo (‘yes’), Svenja first seems to accept all terms of the prior RfC. However, by combining jo (‘yes’) with a full repeat in the second response slot in line 03, Svenja partially retracts her acceptance by displaying agency over the proposition. She confirms only this spatial alternative compared to other spatially close alternatives that might be projected due to the use of the QT oder (‘or’; Drake 2016). The co-occurrence between LoG jo (‘yes’) and a full repeat reveals that jo (‘yes’) is rather used as a more marked confirmation token in the answer possibility space of LoG speakers (see also Section 5.2).
Extract 25: LoG-HES01_09_07 (00:05:45 – 00:05:47), No. 97
01 | Heinz: | NEUwerlte; =oder- |
Neuwerlte; right | ||
02 | Svenja: | jo; |
Yes | ||
03 | NEUwerlte; | |
Neuwerlte |
[repeat] + [yes-token]
Heritage and Raymond (2012) describe the deferred use of type-conforming response tokens as a practice to register qualifications. In LoG, repeats in this format do not display qualifications, but highlight epistemic agency in order to manage sequence closure and secure expansion of a previous turn. Consider again (13). By using a repeat, Ben asserts his epistemic rights over the matter at hand, which seem to be endangered by the preceding independent understanding display of Paul. In this excerpt, the speaker not only confirms the RfC, he also confirms that he has alluded to the categorization of these people as Bankmenschen (‘banking people’) with his prior turn in line 03 (Schegloff 1996). However, confirming allusion practices do not prevail in [repeat] + [token] combinations (see also Section 5.6 on confirming allusion practices). The response token in line 08 has a double-barreled nature: it confirms the previous understanding display together with the repeat as a marker of agency, but it also serves as a sequence closure-implicative device (Imo 2013, 188–9).
Extract 13: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:02:41 – 00:02:49), No. 52 (shortened)
03 | °h (-) mh bi de (-) BAYrische hypo, | |||
At the bavarian hypo (bank) | ||||
04 | Paul: | achSO; | ||
Oh I see | ||||
05 | BANKmens[chen]; | |||
Banking people | ||||
06 | Ben: | [bank]- | ||
Bank | ||||
07 | BANKmenschen;= | |||
Banking people | ||||
08 | =ˇja, | |||
Yes |
5.6 Full and expanded repeats
Yes/no-response tokens are described as the most frequent and type-conforming way of responding to polar questions like RfCs (Raymond 2003, Enfield et al. 2019). However, certain languages tend to be so-called ‘echo systems’, in which repeats serve as the most conventionalized way of confirming a polar question (Sadock and Zwicky (1985) and Jones (1999) on Welsh; Enfield et al. (2019) on Tzeltal). Existing research has described response tokens both as unmarked and as marked types of the answer possibility space (Section 5.2). Repeats, however, are almost exclusively described as marked responses in interaction (Schegloff 1996, Raymond 2003, Stivers 2005, Heritage and Raymond 2012).
‘Markedness’ of repeats is defined at very different levels: (1) on a semantic basis, as repeats assert a prior proposition rather than simply assent to it (Enfield et al. 2019, 284–5); (2) overall frequency, as repeats are often less frequent than response tokens (Enfield et al. 2019, 281), (3) epistemic, sequential, and thematic agency, as recipients claim “epistemic rights over the information required than the original polar question conceded” (Heritage and Raymond 2012, 187; see also Enfield et al. 2019, 292), and (4) sequential positioning, as repeats predominantly do not occur in minimal side sequences, but in ‘primary actions’ that bring new information to the talk (Enfield et al. 2019, 283–4). However, some studies on languages exhibiting a high number of repeats show that repeats are used as unmarked responses in subsidiary sequences (e.g., Keevallik 2010, Brown et al. 2021, Harjunpää and Ostermann 2023). Moreover, these languages also challenge the semantic argument with a minimality–maximality continuum of repeats, where verb-type repeats reassert the prior proposition only minimally (e.g., Hakulinen 2001, Harjunpää and Ostermann 2023). Moreover, Harjunpää and Ostermann (2023, 104–5) argue against the idea of repeats being markers of epistemic agency that in RfCs “the recipient’s greater agentive/epistemic role is sequentially implicated…, which would seem to reduce the need to specifically claim epistemic or agentive rights.”
LoG as a non-standard language exhibits the highest frequencies of repeat responses across the ten languages investigated in the research network (32% of the data; n = 63/196; Pfeiffer et al. Forthcoming) – together with the indigenous language Yurakaré (Gipper, Forthcoming). In the network’s framework only full and full-expanded repeats were included in the study; partial repeats were excluded due to inter-coder reliability issues (König et al. Forthcoming). Concerning the syntactic format of repeats in LoG, phrasal and clausal types prevail in the data. Verb-type repeats like in Finnish or Brazilian Portuguese are not grammaticalized in LoG. In 63% of the cases, repeats are used as stand-alone features (n = 40/63), while in 37% of the data, the repeat is combined with a response token (n = 23/63). 29% of these cases are full-expanded repeats (n = 18/63).[11] Full-expanded repeats are deployed as both confirming and disconfirming responsive actions in the LoG data, always displaying some form of epistemic agency to a prior proposition. In over 71% of the cases, the repeat is a full repeat of the prior RfC (n = 45/63 (n = 27 repeat only, n = 18 repeat + token combinations)). Using overall frequency as a criterion for markedness (Enfield et al. 2019), repeats seem to be marked response types (roughly 67% response tokens vs 32% repeats). Frequency, however, can be measured in different ways: (a) as an overall frequency, or (b) as an action-based frequency, counting frequencies in a specific sequential environment. The latter approach will be the basis of the following analyses. Since the results on full-expanded repeats do not contribute any new insights, the focus of the article is on full repeats without combinations.
Full repeats in the LoG data always confirm the prior RfC action.[12] The data feature that stand alone full repeats predominantly follow understanding checks (n = 14/27; 52%), understanding displays (n = 12/27; 44%) or allusions (Schegloff 1996; n = 1/27; 4%) in the LoG data. RfCs as topic-proffers or as ‘little questions’, however, are almost exclusively responded to with response tokens. Understanding check sequences as subordinate lines of actions are backward-oriented and prefer minimal responses. However, understanding checks do not only attract (minimal) response tokens (Section 5.2), but also full repeats in LoG interaction. In the majority of cases, these understanding checks are formatted as phrasal RfCs. Consider again Extract (5). Anna is telling about an invitation to a guided tour of a food company called Apetito. In lines 03–04, Heinz launches an understanding check in a side sequence by first deploying the open-class repair initiator wie (‘what do you mean’), followed by the candidate bi apetito (‘At apetito’s’). Anna confirms the RfC in line 05 by using a full repeat with a final falling intonation, thus closing the sequence and moving back to the main line of action in line 06. In line 07, Heinz adds the sequence-closing third hm_hm.
Extract 5: LoG-HES01_07_09 (00:23:12 – 00:23:20), No. 108
01 | Anna: | un: bÜnt da ja mo wÄ:n up EINladung; | |
I was invited there once | |||
02 | von (.) von mÜllers HERbert; | ||
By Herbert Müller | |||
03 | Heinz: | (0.2) wie- | |
What do you mean | |||
04 | bi apeTIto; | ||
At Apetito’s (German company that produces food) | |||
05 | Anna: | bI apeTIto; | |
At Apetito’s | |||
06 | d[e HETT] de: °hh- | ||
They have they | |||
07 | Heinz: | [hm_hm] | |
information receipt |
Regarding full repeats as marked options, frequency does not serve as a criterion for markedness in understanding check sequences. Minimal response tokens and repeats do not considerably differ based on the action-based frequency ratio in the LoG data (n = 16 minimal response tokens; n = 14 repeats). With regard to action ascription on the basis of sequential positioning, repeats can be analyzed as unmarked minimal ways of confirming a prior understanding check. Full repeats “seem to claim just the appropriate amount of rights for continuing the action in a way that the question warrants” (Harjunpää and Ostermann 2023, 104). This ascription as an unmarked response is also supported on a prosodic level. The repeat is not equipped with a marked focus accent shift, as discussed by Stivers (2005), but it is constructed similarly to the prior RfC design. Repeats, however, seem to compete with HG ja (‘yes’) in this environment (Section 5.2). In both cases, speakers confirm the prior RfC and then return to a course of action that was temporarily suspended. Thus, both formats are used as closure-implicative confirmations. The only difference between these response types in this context is that RfCs prior to repeat responses display a relatively flatter epistemic stance due to their formatting as phrases with falling intonation. By contrast, RfCs prior to HG ja (‘yes’) are mainly formatted as tag questions, displaying a slightly steeper epistemic gradient (Heritage and Raymond 2012, 180, and Section 5.2). Due to the differences in the epistemic displays set by the prior RfC, full repeats can be analyzed as marking epistemic agency to a slightly higher extent in this context. However, as the epistemic gradient is sequentially implicated in RfCs, the display of agency is rather minute.
In addition, repeats occur after RfCs as understanding displays (Heritage 1984), which index independent access to a matter at hand. They thus require subsequent (dis)confirmation to a lesser extent compared to understanding checks. Because of the flatter epistemic gradient, repeats following understanding displays index a higher level of epistemic agency. Consider the extended Extract (2). With the RfC in lines 06–07, Ben deploys a confident inference, which Paul responds to with a repeat in line 08, thus upgrading his own epistemic agency or primacy to the matter at hand. In Extract (5), the speaker first closes the sequence with a repeat and then comes back to the main line of action. In Extract (2), however, the repeat leverages[13] into a continuation, allowing for a fast resumption. The repeat in line 08 thus has a dual function: (1) it works as a confirmatory response to the prior RfC (as a prosodic unit in its own) and (2) it is syntactically integrated into the following continuation, thus indexing epistemic and thematic agency. Prosodically, these repeats are always equipped with a final rising intonation. In the majority of cases, understanding displays do not occur as subordinate lines of actions in Enfield et al.’s (2019) sense. Finally, repeats in this environment compete predominantly with non-minimal response token designs or repeat + response token combinations (n = 16 non-minimal response tokens; n = 12 repeats), which supports the index of ‘non-minimality’.
Extract 2: LoG-GEL01_02 (00:00:03 – 00:00:12), No. 48
06 | Ben: | (0.2) <<f> ach JA, |
Oh yeah | ||
07 | de heff KLAssentreffen hat; =ne, | |
They had class reunion, right? | ||
08 | Paul: | de heff KLAssentreffen hat, |
They had class reunion | ||
09 | und- | |
And | ||
10 | hier sAndra STEINkamp, | |
Here (name) |
Schegloff (1996) describes full repeats as a practice for accomplishing confirming allusions. In the LoG data, there are only three instances of full repeats that can be analyzed in this way (n = 1 repeat only; n = 2 repeat + token combination as in Extract 13). Consider (26). In the preceding context, Walter has started a longer sequence, requesting his daughter Petra’s help to get wood for his farm. In line 04, Petra provides a candidate RfC, asking if the wood should be collected from the forest. This information was not mentioned explicitly in the previous talk, but there might be an inexplicit conveyance in Walter’s use of the verb inhaln (‘to collect’). Walter confirms the RfC with a full repeat in line 05, reclaiming authorship of what was stated allusively by his prior turn. Confirming allusion practices are rare in the LoG data. In addition, all of these cases would not count as ‘core phenomena’, because none of them occur with follow-up remarks making the allusion obvious.
Extract 26: LoG-BÖR03_09_10 (00:05:24 – 00:05:31), No. 42
01 | Walter: | weil (.) wEIl ik den rest HOLT noch wall Äben_n bItken wall äh- | |
Because I want to catch up on the rest of the woods | |||
02 | (0.5) vör_n Obnd INholn wullt; | ||
For the evenings | |||
03 | Petra: | (0.5) ut_n WALD; | |
From the forest | |||
04 | Walter: | ut_n WALD; | |
From the forest | |||
05 | Petra: | (0.8) WUNner? | |
When |
Section 5.6 discusses different criteria of markedness and how these criteria can be applied to the action ascription of full repeats as (un-)marked response types in LoG interaction. As for the criterion of sequential positioning, the analysis indicates that full repeats sufficiently confirm previous RfCs in understanding check sequences. These subsidiary actions prefer minimal responses, which leads to a reconstruction of repeats as more unmarked responses in this context. As for the criterion of agency, the analyses reveal different degrees of agency that a speaker can index with a repeat in LoG interaction. In understanding check sequences, agency might be displayed due to the flatter epistemic gradient by the prior phrasal RfC, however, this display is rather minute compared to the index of agency with full repeats after understanding displays or as confirming allusions practices. As for the criterion of frequency, the action-based frequency of full repeats vs response tokens in understanding check sequences feature no significant difference between both response options. Thus, frequency does not serve as a criterion for ‘markedness’ in this environment. As for the semantic criterion, the research literature has discussed verb-type repeats as rather minimal ways of asserting a prior RfC. In LoG, verb-type repeats are not grammaticalized as responsive means of interaction. However, the analysis in Section 5.6 revealed that full repeats in understanding check sequences seem to be attracted by phrasal RfCs – a syntactically reduced variant of repeats compared to clausal repeats. RfCs formatted as tag questions in understanding check sequences seem to attract the minimal HG response token ja (‘yes’). Thus, the limitation of full repeats as responses to syntactically reduced phrasal RfCs leads to a categorization more on the minimal end of the minimality-maximality continuum of repeats (e.g., Hakulinen 2001). In sum, the sequential positioning of repeats in subordinate lines of actions, its prosodic design, the limitation to phrasal RfCs, and the action-based relative frequencies with minimal response tokens support the analysis of full repeats as being relatively unmarked response types in LoG.
6 Conclusion
This article detailed some particularities of the RfC question and response design in LoG talk-in-interaction. As for the syntactic design of RfCs, declarative and phrasal types prevail. Moreover, RfCs in LoG frequently contain forms of modulation, e.g., modal particles to index a specific epistemic stance, and tags as attached resources to RfCs. In addition to analyzing frequently deployed design features, this article also examined resources that contribute less frequently to the design of RfCs in LoG. For example, negative polarity as a means of displaying an epistemic stance is not frequently used in LoG RfCs. Furthermore, RfCs are only rarely marked as inferences from a prior speaker’s turn.
As for the LoG response system, three main conclusions can be drawn from this study. First, confirming responses to RfCs outweigh disconfirming responses. This is in line with the results of Stivers et al.’s (2009) comparative study that found an overall (universal) preference for confirmations over disconfirmations. Second, the LoG data suggest a polarity and no truth-value responding system to RfCs, which means that the polarity of the prior RfC determines the preference of the following response form. Third, LoG seems to be a language between the poles of token- and repeat-type languages, with response tokens being overall more frequent, but repeats also account for a non-negligible share of the data.
In the previous literature, response tokens have been analyzed as marked and unmarked response types, while repeats were classified as marked only. If markedness is defined on the basis of the overall frequency ratio, then Enfield et al.’s (2019) generalization that response tokens are preferred over repeats holds also true for LoG. However, the frequency ratio of 68% response tokens vs 32% repeats approximates the one Enfield et al. (2019) observed for Brazilian Portuguese, one of three stand-out cases, which shows a higher reliance on repeat types. The frequency ratio of the LoG data is thus interesting for a Germanic language. Moreover, Enfield et al. (2019, 291) found that “there is no sequential, action, or morpho-syntactic context that we could identify where repetition-type answers were more likely than interjections.” Looking into the action-based frequencies of this study, (minimal) response tokens and repeats occur with similar frequencies in understanding checks. Thus, frequency cannot be applied as a criterion of markedness here. In other sequential environments like series of little questions or topic proffers, however, response tokens clearly prevail in the LoG data.
Concerning sequential positioning, previous research on verb-type repeats revealed that repeats mainly occur in responses to requests for new information. By contrast, subordinate lines of actions appear to attract almost exclusively token-based responses (see e.g., Sorjonen (2001, 33–92) on Finish repeats). The results on LoG repeats are not perfectly comparable to previous research, as verb-type repeats are not grammaticalized in LoG. However, we see that unmarked full repeats are attracted by syntactically reduced – and thus more minimal – phrasal RfCs. Given that markedness is defined in a sequentially sensitive manner, repeats in subordinate lines of actions need to be defined as unmarked or minimal means of the answer possibility space. However, we have also learned that repeats compete with HG ja (‘yes’) in this environment. Bearing in mind the morpho-syntactic differences of RfCs prior to full repeats and HG ja (‘yes’), repeats might be analyzed as low-marked resources displaying epistemic agency to a slightly higher extent than ja (‘yes’). However, this difference in the index of agency is minute compared to more marked uses of repeats (e.g., after understanding displays). It should lead us to think about pragmatic markedness not as an ‘either-or’ principle, but more as a continuum of repeats being more or less marked.[14]
Finally, this study emphasized the role of variety contact in the investigation of social actions in interaction. For the question design, this article revealed both contact-induced structural convergence of LoG to HG, partly for resources of modulation, inference marking, and connectives, as well as maintenance of language-specific LoG structures in the design of RfCs, e.g., for the modulation marker wall or the tags nich. Comparing the results of this article with Deppermann et al. (2024) on RfCs in HG, similarities in the question design but also considerable differences in the response design emerge. First, due to the variety contact situation outlined in Section 3, LoG exhibits a larger basic positive and negative response token system containing both HG and LoG token types. On the one hand, the analysis revealed that unmarked responses are mainly formatted with HG tokens, while LoG tokens are mainly deployed as more marked responses. This result raises the question of whether dialectal response tokens generally tend to take on additional functions of stance-taking in the course of variety contact. Jones (1999, 43–4) lends support to this idea by observing stronger modulation of dialectal response tokens for Welsh. This opens up new directions for future interactional research of contact varieties. On the other hand, the data suggest a preference-induced effect as the higher frequency of confirmations might enhance persistence with regard to the LoG ‘yes’-token types. Finally, the comparison with Deppermann et al. (2024) on HG RfCs reveals variety-specific differences in the answer possibility space. It shows that speakers of an HG variety seem to use answer types like repeats differently compared to LoG dialect speakers.[15] This study addresses the monolingual bias in CA research on polar questions and answers so far. It shows that there is a value added by including non-standard varieties in interactional linguistic research, allowing us to gain better insights into question and response systems beyond standard languages and the interactional work they do.
Transcription conventions
See Selting et al. (2009) for GAT2 conventions
- []
-
overlap and simultaneous talk
- =
-
latching
- (.)
-
micropause (shorter than 0.2 s)
- (2.85)
-
measured pause
- geht_s
-
assimilation of words
- :, ::, :::
-
segmental lengthening, according to duration
- ((laughs))
-
non-verbal vocal actions and events
- akZENT
-
focal accent
- akzEnt
-
secondary stress
- ?
-
pitch rising to high at end of intonation phrase
- ,
-
pitch rising to mid
- -
-
level pitch
- ;
-
pitch falling to mid
- .
-
pitch falling to low
- <<p>>
-
piano, soft
- <<f>
-
forte, loud
- <<h>>
-
high pitch register
- <<p>>
-
piano, soft
- <<all>>
-
allegro, fast
- °h
-
inbreath, according to duration
- h°
-
outbreath, according to duration
- <<creaky voice>>
-
commentaries regarding voice qualities with indication of scope
- (solche)
-
assumed wording
Abbreviations
- HG
-
High German
- LoG
-
Low German
- RfC
-
Request for confirmation
Glossing
See Bickel et al. (2015) on the Leipzig Glossing Rules
- 2
-
Person
- AUX
-
Auxiliary
- NEG
-
Negation
- QT
-
Question tag
- PL
-
Plural
- PST
-
Past
- PTCP
-
Participle
- PRT
-
Particle (modal)
- SG
-
Singular
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank all research network members for valuable and intensive discussions about RfCs. In addition, I am also grateful for comments on an earlier draft of the article provided by Katharina König and Martin Pfeiffer. Furthermore, I would like to acknowledge the input from two anonymous referees, who helped me clarify my arguments. Their suggestions improved this article to a great extent. All remaining issues are of course my own responsibility.
-
Funding information: Work on this article was funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) project number 413161127 – Scientific Network ‘Interactional Linguistics - Discourse particles from a cross-linguistic perspective’, led by Martin Pfeiffer and Katharina König.
-
Author contributions: The author confirms the sole responsibility for the conception of the study, presented results, and manuscript preparation.
-
Conflict of interest: The author states no conflict of interest.
References
Adelung, Johann Christoph. 1798. Grammatisch-kritisches Wörterbuch der hochdeutschen Mundart, mit beständiger Vergleichung der übrigen Mundarten, besonders aber der Oberdeutschen; Volume 3 (M-Scr). Leipzig: Breitkopf.Search in Google Scholar
Adler, Astrid, Christiane Ehlers, Reinhard Goltz, Andrea Kleene, and Albrecht Plewnia. 2018. The current status and use of Low German. Initial results of a representative study. Mannheim: Institut für Deutsche Sprache.Search in Google Scholar
Antaki, Charles. 2012. “Affiliative and Disaffiliative Candidate Understandings.” Discourse Studies 14 (5): 531–47.10.1177/1461445612454074Search in Google Scholar
Betz, Emma, Carmen Taleghani-Nikazm, Veronika Drake, and Andrea Golato. 2013. “Third-position Repeats in German: The Case of Repair- and Request-for-Information Sequences.” Gesprächsforschung – Online Zeitschrift zur verbalen Interaktion 14: 133–66.Search in Google Scholar
Bickel, Balthasar, Bernard Comrie, and Martin Haspelmath. 2015. The Leipzig Glossing Rules. Available online at https://www.eva.mpg.de/lingua/resources/glossing-rules.php, checked on 2/29/2024.Search in Google Scholar
Bolden, Galina B., John Heritage, and Marja-Leena Sorjonen, eds. 2023. Responding to Polar Questions across Languages and Contexts. Amsterdam: John Benjamins (Studies in language and social interaction (SLSI) 35).10.1075/slsi.35Search in Google Scholar
Brown, Penelope, Mark A. Sicoli, and Olivier Le Guen. 2021. “Cross-speaker Repetition and Epistemic Stance in Tzeltal, Yucatec, and Zapotec Conversations.” Journal of Pragmatics 183: 256–72.10.1016/j.pragma.2021.07.005Search in Google Scholar
Bublitz, Wolfram. 1978. Ausdrucksweisen der Sprechereinstellung im Deutschen und im Englischen. Untersuchungen zur Syntax, Semantik und Pragmatik der deutschen Modalpartikeln und Vergewisserungsfragen und ihrer englischen Entsprechungen. Tübingen: Niemeyer.10.1515/9783111712369Search in Google Scholar
Burkhardt, Arnim. 1982. “Gesprächswörter. Ihre lexikologische Bestimmung und lexikographische Beschreibung.” In Konzepte zur Lexikographie. Studien zur Bedeutungserklärung in einsprachigen Wörterbüchern, edited by Wolfgang Mentrup, 138–71. Tübingen: Niemeyer.10.1515/9783111371061.138Search in Google Scholar
Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth and Margret Selting. 2018. Interactional Linguistics. Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781139507318Search in Google Scholar
Damme, Robert. 2015. Westfälisches Wörterbuch; Band 3, H-L. Kiel, Hamburg: Wachholtz.Search in Google Scholar
Deppermann, Arnulf, Alexandra Gubina, Katharina König, and Martin Pfeiffer. 2024. “Request for Confirmation Sequences in German.” Open Linguistics 10 (1): 20240008. 10.1515/opli-2024-0008.Search in Google Scholar
Drake, Veronika. 2016. “German Questions and Turn-Final Oder.” Gesprächsforschung - Online Zeitschrift zur verbalen Interaktion 17: 168–95.Search in Google Scholar
Drew, Paul. 2018. “Inferences and Indirectness in Interaction.” Open Linguistics 4 (1): 241–59. 10.1515/opli-2018-0013.Search in Google Scholar
Duden. 2006. Die Grammatik. Unentbehrlich für richtiges Deutsch: nach den Regeln der neuen deutschen Rechtschreibung 2006. Mannheim: Dudenverlag.Search in Google Scholar
Elspaß, Stephan and Robert Möller. 2004. Atlas zur deutschen Alltagssprache (AdA), Round 1 (nein (Lautform)). Available online at https://www.atlas-alltagssprache.de/runde-1/f10/, checked on 2/29/2024.Search in Google Scholar
Elspaß, Stephan and Robert Möller. 2005. Atlas zur deutschen Alltagssprache (AdA) Round 2 (gell?/oder?). Available online at https://www.atlas-alltagssprache.de/runde-2/f19a-b/, checked on 2/29/2024.Search in Google Scholar
Enfield, Nick J., Tanya Stivers, and Stephen C. Levinson. 2010. “Question–response Sequences in Conversation Across Ten Languages: An Introduction.” Journal of Pragmatics 42 (10): 2615–9.10.1016/j.pragma.2010.04.001Search in Google Scholar
Enfield, Nick J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, et al. 2019. “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55 (2): 277–304.10.1017/S0022226718000336Search in Google Scholar
Frey, Natascha. 2010. “Frage-Tags im Schweizerdeutschen: Alles klar, oder?” In Alemannische Dialektologie. Wege in die Zukunft; Beiträge zur 16. Arbeitstagung für Alemannische Dialektologie in Freiburg/Fribourg vom 07. - 10.09.2008, edited by Helen Christen, Sibylle Germann, Walter Haas, Nadia Montefiori, and Hans Ruef, 85–96. Stuttgart: Steiner.Search in Google Scholar
Gipper, Sonja and Alexandra Groß. 2024.“Less than Confirming, and Doing More than that in German and Yurakaré: A Mixed form- and Function-based Approach for Comparing Response Strategies Across Languages.” Contrastive Pragmatics (1–2): 347–91.10.1163/26660393-bja10100Search in Google Scholar
Gipper, Sonja. Forthcoming. “Request for Confirmation Sequences in Yurakaré.” Open Linguistics.Search in Google Scholar
Glaser, Elvira. 2003. ““Is de für Herrn König, oder?.” Zur Sprachgeographie von Gliederungspartikeln.” In Sprachgeschichten. Ein Lesebuch für Werner König zum 60. Geburtstag, edited by Edith Funk, 63–79. Heidelberg: Winter.Search in Google Scholar
Golato, Andrea. 2010. “Marking understanding versus receipting information in talk: Achso. and ach in German interaction.” Discourse Studies 12 (2): 147–76.10.1177/1461445609356497Search in Google Scholar
Goss, Emily L. and Joseph C. Salmons. 2000. “The Evolution of a Bilingual Discourse Marking System: Modal Particles and English Markers in German-American Dialects.” International Journal of Bilingualism 4 (4): 469–84.10.1177/13670069000040040501Search in Google Scholar
Hagemann, Jörg. 2009. “Tag Questions Als Evidenzmarker. Formulierungsdynamik, Sequentielle Struktur und Funktionen Redezuginterner Tags.” Gesprächsforschung – Online Zeitschrift zur verbalen Interaktion 10: 145–76.Search in Google Scholar
Hakulinen, Auli. 2001. “Minimal and Non-Minimal Answers to Yes–No Questions.” Pragmatics 11 (1): 1–15.10.1075/prag.11.1.01hakSearch in Google Scholar
Hansen-Jaax, Dörte. 1995. Transfer bei Diglossie. Synchrone Sprachkontaktphänomene im Niederdeutschen. Hamburg: Kovac.Search in Google Scholar
Harjunpää, Katariina and Anna Cristina Ostermann. 2023. “Responding to polar questions in Brazilian Portuguese.” In Responding to Polar Questions across Languages and Contexts, edited by Galina B. Bolden, John Heritage and Marja-Leena Sorjonen, 76–108. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/slsi.35.03harSearch in Google Scholar
Harren, Inga. 2001. “ne?” in Alltagsgesprächen – Interaktive Funktionen und Positionierungen in Turn und Sequenz. Staatsexamensarbeit: Universität Oldenburg. Available online at https://www.researchgate.net/publication/298792177_ne_in_Alltagsgesprachen_-_Interaktive_Funktionen_und_Positionierungen_in_Turn_und_Sequenz, checked on 2/29/2024.Search in Google Scholar
Heinemann, Trine. 2006. “‘Will You or Can’t You?’: Displaying Entitlement in Interrogative Requests.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (7): 1081–104.10.1016/j.pragma.2005.09.013Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John and Andrew Roth. 1995. “Grammar and Institution: Questions and Questioning in the Broadcast News Interview.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 28: 1–60.10.1207/s15327973rlsi2801_1Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John and Chase W. Raymond. 2021. “Preference and Polarity: Epistemic Stance in Question Design.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 54 (1): 39–59.10.1080/08351813.2020.1864155Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John and Geoffrey Raymond. 2005. “The Terms of Agreement: Indexing Epistemic Authority and Subordination in Talk-in-Interaction.” Social Psychology Quarterly 68 (1): 15–38.10.1177/019027250506800103Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John and Geoffrey Raymond. 2012. “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions. Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, edited by Jan-Peter de Ruiter, 179–92. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139045414.013Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John and Marja-Leena Sorjonen. 1994. “Constituting and Maintaining Activities Across Sequences: And-prefacing as a Feature of Question Design.” Language in Society 23: 1–29.10.1017/S0047404500017656Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John. 1984. “A Change-of-State Token and Aspects of its Sequential Placement.” In Structures of Social Action. Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. Maxwell Atkinson and John Heritage, 299–345. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511665868.020Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John. 1998. “Oh-prefaced Responses to Inquiry.” Language in Society 27 (3): 291–334.10.1017/S0047404500019990Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John. 2002. “The Limits of Questioning: Negative Interrogatives and Hostile Question Content.” Journal of Pragmatics 34: 1427–46.10.1016/S0378-2166(02)00072-3Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John. 2012a. “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45 (1): 1–29.10.1080/08351813.2012.646684Search in Google Scholar
Heritage, John. 2012b. “The Epistemic Engine: Sequence Organization and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45 (1): 30–52.10.1080/08351813.2012.646685Search in Google Scholar
Imo, Wolfgang. 2011. ““Jetzt Geh’n Wir Einen Trinken, Gell?.” Vergewisserungssignale (tag questions) und ihre Relevanz für den DaF-Unterricht.” In Deutsch aktuell. Einführung in die Tendenzen der deutschen Gegenwartssprache, edited by Sandro M. Moraldo, 127–50. Roma: Carocci.Search in Google Scholar
Imo, Wolfgang. 2013. Sprache in Interaktion. Berlin, New York: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110306323Search in Google Scholar
Imo, Wolfgang. 2017. “Über Nein.” Zeitschrift für Germanistische Linguistik 45 (1): 40–72.10.1515/zgl-2017-0002Search in Google Scholar
Jefferson, Gail. 1972. “Sides Sequences.” In Studies in Social Interaction, edited by David Sudnow, 294–338. New York: The Free Press.Search in Google Scholar
Jones, Bob Morris. 1999. The Welsh Answering System. New York: Mouton de Gruyter.10.1515/9783110800593Search in Google Scholar
Keevallik, Leelo. 2010. “Minimal Answers to Yes/No Questions in the Service of Sequence Organization.” Discourse Studies 12 (3): 283–309.10.1177/1461445610363951Search in Google Scholar
Kluge, Friedrich and Walther Mitzka. 1960. Etymologisches Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache. Berlin, New York: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783111561028Search in Google Scholar
König, Katharina and Martin Pfeiffer. Forthcoming. “Request for Confirmation Sequences in ten Languages. An Introduction.” Open Linguistics.Search in Google Scholar
König, Katharina, Martin Pfeiffer, and Kathrin Weber. Forthcoming. “A Coding Scheme for Request for Confirmation Sequences Across Languages.” Open Linguistics.Search in Google Scholar
König, Katharina. 2020. “Prosodie und Epistemic Stance: Konstruktionen mit finalem oder.” In Prosodie und Konstruktionsgrammatik, edited by Wolfgang Imo and Jens Lanwer, 167–99. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110637489-006Search in Google Scholar
Koshik, Irene. 2002. “A Conversation Analytic Study of Yes/No Questions Which Convey Reversed Polarity Assertions.” Journal of Pragmatics 34 (12): 1851–77.10.1016/S0378-2166(02)00057-7Search in Google Scholar
Koshik, Irene. 2005. Beyond Rhetorical Questions. Assertive Questions in Everyday Interaction. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/sidag.16Search in Google Scholar
Küttner, Uwe-A. and Oliver Ehmer. 2024. “Affordances and Actions: Requests for Confirmation as Devices for Implementing Challenging and Other Disagreement-Implicative Actions.” Contrastive Pragmatics (1–2): 27–71.10.1163/26660393-bja10089Search in Google Scholar
Labov, William and David Fanshel. 1977. Therapeutic Discourse. Psychotherapy as Conversation. New York: Academic Press.Search in Google Scholar
Labov, William. 2010. Principles of Linguistic Change. Vol. 2: Social Factors. Malden: Blackwell.10.1002/9781444327496Search in Google Scholar
Langer, Nils. 2003. “Low German.” In Germanic standardizations. Past to Present, edited by Ana Deumert and Wim Vandenbussche, 281–301. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/impact.18.11lanSearch in Google Scholar
Lanwer, Jens. 2019. “Alignmentmarker in Norddeutscher Alltagssprache (AINA).” Niederdeutsches Wort 59: 33–75.Search in Google Scholar
Lindow, Wolfgang. 1998. Niederdeutsche Grammatik. Leer: Schuster.Search in Google Scholar
Pfeiffer, Martin, Kathrin Weber, Katharina König, Arnulf Deppermann, Oliver Ehmer, Sonja Gipper, Alexandra Gubina, et al. Forthcoming. “Request for Confirmation Sequences in Ten Languages. A Quantitative Comparison.” Open Linguistics.Search in Google Scholar
Pittner, Karin. 2007. “Common Ground in Interaction: The Functions of Medial doch in German.” In Lexical Markers of Common Grounds, edited by Anita Fetzer and Kerstin FischerAmsterdam: Brill, edited by Anita Fetzer and Kerstin Fischer, 67–87. Amsterdam: Brill.10.1163/9780080466316_006Search in Google Scholar
Pomerantz, Anita. 1988. “Offering a Candidate Answer: An Information Seeking Strategy.” Communication Monographs 55(4): 360–73.10.1080/03637758809376177Search in Google Scholar
Raymond, Geoffrey. 2003. “Grammar and Social Organization: Yes/No Interrogatives and the Structure of Responding.” American Sociological Review 68 (6): 939–67.10.1177/000312240306800607Search in Google Scholar
Raymond, Geoffrey. 2013. “At the Intersection of Turn and Sequence Organization: On the Relevance of “Slots” in Type-Conforming Responses to Polar Interrogatives.” In Units of talk – Units of action, edited by Beatrice Szczepek Reed and Geoffrey Raymond, 169–206. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/slsi.25.06raySearch in Google Scholar
Reinecke, Silke. 2018. “Interaktionale Analysen kognitiver Phänomene. Wissenszuschreibungen mit der Modalpartikel ja.” In Sprachliches Handeln und Kognition: Theoretische Grundlagen und empirische Analysen, edited by Simon Meier and Konstanze Marx, 183–204. Berlin, New York: De Gruyter Mouton.10.1515/9783110575484-189Search in Google Scholar
Sacks, Harvey. 1992. Lectures on Conversation. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar
Sadock, Jerrold M. and Arnold M. Zwicky. 1985. “Speech Act Distinctions in Syntax.” In Language Typology and Syntactic Description, edited by Timothy Shopen, 155–96. Cambridge, UK, New York: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Sanders, Willy. 1982. Sachsensprache, Hansesprache, Plattdeutsch. Sprachgeschichtliche Grundzüge des Niederdeutschen. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht.Search in Google Scholar
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1996. “Confirming Allusions: Toward an Empirical Account of Action.” American Journal of Sociology 102 (1): 161–216.10.1086/230911Search in Google Scholar
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007. Sequence Organization in Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511791208Search in Google Scholar
Schoonjans, Steven. 2018. Modalpartikeln als multimodale Konstruktionen. Eine korpusbasierte Kookkurrenzanalyse von Modalpartikeln und Gestik im Deutschen. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110566260Search in Google Scholar
Selting, Margret, Peter Auer, Dagmar Barth-Weingarten, Jörg Bergmann, Pia Bergmann, Karin Birkner, Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen, et al. 2009. “Gesprächsanalytisches Transkriptionssystem 2 (GAT 2).” Gesprächsforschung 10: 353–402.Search in Google Scholar
Seuren, Lucas M. and Mike Huiskes. 2017. “Confirmation or Elaboration: What Do Yes/No Declaratives Want?” Research on Language and Social Interaction 50 (2): 188–205.10.1080/08351813.2017.1301307Search in Google Scholar
Sorjonen, Marja-Leena. 2001. Responding in Conversation: A study of response particles in Finnish. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/pbns.70Search in Google Scholar
Steensig, Jakob and Paul Drew. 2008. “Introduction: Questioning and Affiliation/Disaffiliation in Interaction.” Discourse Studies 10 (1), 5–15.10.1177/1461445607085581Search in Google Scholar
Steensig, Jakob and Tine Larsen. 2008. “Affiliative and Disaffiliative Uses of You Say x Questions.” Discourse Studies 10 (1): 113–33.10.1177/1461445607085593Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya and Frederico Rossano. 2010. “Mobilizing Response.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 43 (1): 3–31.10.1080/08351810903471258Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya, Nick J. Enfield, and Penelope Brown. 2009. “Universals and Cultural Variation in Turn-Taking in Conversation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 106 (26): 10587–92.10.1073/pnas.0903616106Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya. 2004. ““No no no” and Other Types of Multiple Sayings in Social Interaction.” Human Communication Research 30 (2): 260–93.10.1093/hcr/30.2.260Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya. 2005. “Modified Repeats: One Method for Asserting Primary Rights from Second Position.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 38 (2): 131–58.10.1207/s15327973rlsi3802_1Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya. 2011. “Morality and Question Design: “of course” as Contesting a Presupposition of Askability.” In The Morality of Knowledge in Conversation, edited by Jakob Steensig, Lorenza Mondada, and Tanya Stivers, 82–106. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.10.1017/CBO9780511921674.005Search in Google Scholar
Stivers, Tanya. 2022. The Book of Answers. Alignment, Autonomy, and Affiliation in Social Interaction. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780197563892.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Szczepek Reed, Beatrice. 2015. “Managing the Boundary Between Yes and But: Two Ways of Disaffiliating with German ja aber and jaber.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 48 (1): 32–57.10.1080/08351813.2015.993843Search in Google Scholar
Thies, Heinrich. 2010. Plattdeutsche Grammstik A – Z. Formen und Funktionen. Neumünster: Wachholtz.Search in Google Scholar
Thurmair, Maria. 1989. Modalpartikeln und ihre Kombinationen. Tübingen: Niemeyer.10.1515/9783111354569Search in Google Scholar
Turco, Giuseppina, Bettina Braun, and Christine Dimroth. 2014. “When Contrasting Polarity, the Dutch Use Particles, Germans Intonation.” Journal of Pragmatics 62: 94–106.10.1016/j.pragma.2013.09.020Search in Google Scholar
Weber, Kathrin. 2020a. Regionale Auxiliarvariation: Interaktion, Schrift, Kognition. Berlin, New York: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110708875Search in Google Scholar
Weber, Kathrin. 2020b. “The German Modal Particle wohl between Epistemics and Evidentiality – An Interactional and Regional Perspective.” Journal of Pragmatics 170: 334–63.10.1016/j.pragma.2020.09.023Search in Google Scholar
Wirrer, Jan. 1998. “Zum Status des Niederdeutschen.” Zeitschrift für Germanistische Linguistik 26 (3): 308–40.Search in Google Scholar
Zinken, Jörg and Uwe-A. Küttner. 2022. “Offering an Interpretation of Prior Talk in Every-Day Interaction: A Semantic Map Approach.” Discourse Processes 59: 1–28.10.1080/0163853X.2022.2028088Search in Google Scholar
© 2024 the author(s), published by De Gruyter
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Research Articles
- Describing smell: A comparative analysis of active smell lexicon in Estonian and German
- The sound of the Italian comic book: Representing noises, senses, and emotions across 80 years
- Framing victimhood, making war: A linguistic historicizing of secessionist discourses
- Under pressure: Exploring the impact of cognitive factors on clitics placement in L2 Slovak
- The syntax of non-canonical coordination in Jordanian Arabic: An experimental investigation
- Suffixation in Zhangzhou
- Alignment in Vamale, South Oceanic: Diachrony and contact influence
- A corpus-based study of epicene pronouns used by Macedonian learners of English
- Iconicity as the motivation for morphophonological metathesis and truncation in Nigerian Pidgin
- ‘Little Arabia’ on Buddhist land: Exploring the linguistic landscape of Bangkok’s ‘Soi Arab’ enclave
- Mother tongue in Serbia: A speakers’ perspective on the meaning of the concept
- Role of six turn-initial demonstrative and emotive particles in Lithuanian
- Verbal numeral classifiers in languages of Eastern Eurasia: A typological survey
- The multilingual repertoire of the Haitian community in Chapecó (SC, Brazil): Patterns of linguistic evolution in a South–South migration context
- ‘Aquí toman mucho sopa’: Linguistic variables as predictors of non-standard gender agreement production in Basque Spanish
- Data-driven identification of situated meanings in corpus data using Latent Class Analysis
- Adverbs and adverbials in contemporary Arabic syntax: A phase-based account
- Spatial effects with missing data
- Instability of interactives: The case of interjections in Gorwaa
- Linguistic explication of rational and irrational knowledge types in the content of toponyms (on the material of the linguocultural dictionary)
- Review Articles
- Discourse-related expletives: Challenges and opportunities
- Vietnamese tense marking since the seventeenth century: A historiographical analysis
- Special Issue: Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity in Language, edited by Külli Habicht, Tiit Hennoste, Helle Metslang, and Renate Pajusalu - Part II
- Editorial: Exploring subjectivity and intersubjectivity in language
- Two past forms inducing conjectural or non-intrusive questions
- A typological approach to intersubjective uses of the Finnish clitic markers =hAn and =se from the perspectives of engagement and their interrelations with subject person
- Repetition and variation in a Finnish music-related discourse: A case study
- Biased interrogatives in Camuno
- On the overlapping discourse functions of Spanish ‘cómo que’ and French ‘comment ça’ interrogatives
- Repetition in discourses across languages and genres
- Reducing the severity of incidents or emergency in Estonian emergency calls
- Special Issue: Request for confirmation sequences across ten languages, edited by Martin Pfeiffer & Katharina König - Part I
- Request for confirmation sequences in Mandarin Chinese
- Request for confirmation sequences in Korean
- Request for confirmation sequences in British and American English
- Request for confirmation sequences in German
- Request for confirmation sequences in Low German
- Request for confirmation sequences in Egyptian Arabic
- Request for confirmation sequences in Yurakaré
- Request for confirmation sequences in Hebrew
- Request for confirmation sequences in Czech
Articles in the same Issue
- Research Articles
- Describing smell: A comparative analysis of active smell lexicon in Estonian and German
- The sound of the Italian comic book: Representing noises, senses, and emotions across 80 years
- Framing victimhood, making war: A linguistic historicizing of secessionist discourses
- Under pressure: Exploring the impact of cognitive factors on clitics placement in L2 Slovak
- The syntax of non-canonical coordination in Jordanian Arabic: An experimental investigation
- Suffixation in Zhangzhou
- Alignment in Vamale, South Oceanic: Diachrony and contact influence
- A corpus-based study of epicene pronouns used by Macedonian learners of English
- Iconicity as the motivation for morphophonological metathesis and truncation in Nigerian Pidgin
- ‘Little Arabia’ on Buddhist land: Exploring the linguistic landscape of Bangkok’s ‘Soi Arab’ enclave
- Mother tongue in Serbia: A speakers’ perspective on the meaning of the concept
- Role of six turn-initial demonstrative and emotive particles in Lithuanian
- Verbal numeral classifiers in languages of Eastern Eurasia: A typological survey
- The multilingual repertoire of the Haitian community in Chapecó (SC, Brazil): Patterns of linguistic evolution in a South–South migration context
- ‘Aquí toman mucho sopa’: Linguistic variables as predictors of non-standard gender agreement production in Basque Spanish
- Data-driven identification of situated meanings in corpus data using Latent Class Analysis
- Adverbs and adverbials in contemporary Arabic syntax: A phase-based account
- Spatial effects with missing data
- Instability of interactives: The case of interjections in Gorwaa
- Linguistic explication of rational and irrational knowledge types in the content of toponyms (on the material of the linguocultural dictionary)
- Review Articles
- Discourse-related expletives: Challenges and opportunities
- Vietnamese tense marking since the seventeenth century: A historiographical analysis
- Special Issue: Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity in Language, edited by Külli Habicht, Tiit Hennoste, Helle Metslang, and Renate Pajusalu - Part II
- Editorial: Exploring subjectivity and intersubjectivity in language
- Two past forms inducing conjectural or non-intrusive questions
- A typological approach to intersubjective uses of the Finnish clitic markers =hAn and =se from the perspectives of engagement and their interrelations with subject person
- Repetition and variation in a Finnish music-related discourse: A case study
- Biased interrogatives in Camuno
- On the overlapping discourse functions of Spanish ‘cómo que’ and French ‘comment ça’ interrogatives
- Repetition in discourses across languages and genres
- Reducing the severity of incidents or emergency in Estonian emergency calls
- Special Issue: Request for confirmation sequences across ten languages, edited by Martin Pfeiffer & Katharina König - Part I
- Request for confirmation sequences in Mandarin Chinese
- Request for confirmation sequences in Korean
- Request for confirmation sequences in British and American English
- Request for confirmation sequences in German
- Request for confirmation sequences in Low German
- Request for confirmation sequences in Egyptian Arabic
- Request for confirmation sequences in Yurakaré
- Request for confirmation sequences in Hebrew
- Request for confirmation sequences in Czech