Home Vagueness of Language: Indeterminacy under Two-Dimensional State-Uncertainty
Article
Licensed
Unlicensed Requires Authentication

Vagueness of Language: Indeterminacy under Two-Dimensional State-Uncertainty

  • Saori Chiba ORCID logo EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: October 22, 2019

Abstract

We study indeterminacy of indicative meanings (disagreements about meanings of messages among players), a kind of language vagueness examined in Blume and Board (2013. “Language Barriers.” Econometrica 81 (2): 781–812). They, using a cheap talk model in which the state-distribution and the players’ language competence were ex-ante uncertain, demonstrated that this vagueness occurs as an equilibrium language. We expand the work of Blume and Board by using a model between an uninformed decision maker and an informed agent in which the state-distribution and the state are both ex-ante uncertain. We show that this two-dimensional uncertainty also leads to indeterminacy of indicative meanings, that is, to a set of conditions in which an agent with different perceptions of the state-distribution intentionally uses the same symbol for the different extents of information on the state. The vagueness, contrary to common expectations, can actually lead to welfare improvement.

JEL Classification: D82; D83; M14

Acknowledgements

I benefited from suggestions made by Sambuddha Ghosh, Kohei Kawamura, Ming Li, Marco LiCalzi, Barton Lipman, Tadashi Sekiguchi, Nora Wegner, and two anonymous reviewers as well as seminar participants at XXIX Jornadas de Economía Industrial, XXXIX Simposio de la Asociación Española de Economía, Hitotsubashi University, and Tsukuba University. I appreciate the editorial support from Jose de Jesus Herrera Velasquez and Rahel O’More. I am grateful to Dipartimento di Management, Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia for grants (project SSD SECS-S/06, 536/2013 and 569/2014) and Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, Grants-in-Aid for Scientific Research (C) (no. 16K03549). This paper is a substantially revised version of an earlier paper entitled “Extensions and Vagueness of Language under Two-Dimensional State Uncertainty” (Chiba 2014). All remaining errors are my own.

Appendix

A

A.1 Proofs for Section 3

A.1.1 Definitions

Define al for l{R,S}:

aS(θ;b):=argmaxaRUS(a,θ,b) for θb

aR is characterized similarly. From assumptions, al is well defined.

Define Ul¯ for l{R,S}:

US¯(a,s,b;i)=E[US(a,θ,b)|s=s,t=i]=(p+(1p)qi)US(a,Fi(s),b)+j{1,2,...,n}{i}(1p)qjUS(a,Fj(s),b).

UR¯ is expressed similarly. Ul¯ is a convex combination of Ul and hence preserves the following properties: Ul¯ is continuously twice differentiable; UR¯(a,s;i)=US¯(a,s,0;i) for ∀a, ∀s; U11S¯<0<U12S¯ for ∀a, ∀s; and 0<U13S¯ for ∀a, ∀b.

Thus, there also exists a well-defined Al for l{R,S}:

AS(s,i,b):=argmaxaRUS¯(a,s,b;i)

Then, it follows from 0<U13S¯ that AS(s,i,b)=AR(s,i) if b = 0 for ∀s,∀i and AS(s,i,b)AR(s,i) increases with b for any b and θ. Al is bounded below and above by Al(0,i) and Al(1,i), respectively, because the support j{1,2,...,n}Tj is bounded.

A.1.2 Proof for Lemma 1

Under one-dimensional state-uncertainty, there are n subgames, one game per type of S. Lemma 1 and Theorem 1 in CS directly applies to each subgame since S perfectly knows that θ and the payoff functions satisfy the required conditions. Thus, each type uses finite messages and induces finite actions. Last, even if different types commonly use some message, R infers differently for different types. Thus, the claim holds.

A.1.3 Proof for Lemma 2

It follows from Lemma 1 and Theorem 1 in CS. Thus, if the set of actions induced in equilibrium is finite, the equilibrium should have a partitional form because U12S¯>0. Thus, it suffices to show that if multiple actions are induced by one type, for every two distinct actions a and a' induced by one type, there is ε > 0 such that |aa|ϵ.

Consider two cases: first, no message is commonly used by multiple types; second, at least one message is used by at least two types.

In the first case, the analysis is equivalent to the proof of Lemma 1 because a message reveals the type and payoff functions Ul¯ satisfy the required conditions for Lemma 1 and Theorem 1.

In the second case, suppose a is induced by type 1 and type 2. Suppose a' > a is also induced by both types. Let a be induced by type 1 given s1 and type 2 given s2, respectively. Let a' be induced by type 1 given s1 and type 2 given s2 , respectively. Hence, by weakly revealed preferences and continuity there exists a unique si¯ such that US¯(a,si¯,b;i)=US¯(a,si¯,b;i). Thus:

a<AS(si¯,i,b)<afor i{1,2}

Type k, where k{1,2}, does not induce a for any s>si¯ nor a' for any s>si¯. This and U12R¯>0 imply that:

aγAR(s1¯,1)+(1γ)AR(s2¯,2)a for some γ(0,1).

Thus, there is an ε > 0 such that a' – a ≥ ε.

Last, suppose a is induced by type 1 and type 2. Suppose a' > a is induced only by type 1. For type 1, there exists a unique s1¯ such that US¯(a,s1¯,b;1)=US¯(a,s1¯,b;1), but for type 2, US¯(a,s,b;2)>US¯(a,s,b;2) holds for any s. Thus:

a<AS(s1¯,1,b)<a,a<AS(1,2,b)<a.

Both types induce a, but type 1 does not induce it for any s>si¯. Only type 1 induces a' and he does not induce it for s<s1¯:

AR(s1¯,1)a,aγAR(s1¯,1)+(1γ)AR(1,2)for some γ(0,1).

Thus, there is an ε > 0 such that a' – a ≥ ε.

A.1.4 Proof for Proposition 1

Fix b(0,) and p[0,1]. Consider any equilibrium under two-dimensional state-uncertainty (i.e. t is S’s private information).

Consider a set of types N¯ such that iN¯Ti has a positive measure and condition (1) (i.e. Fi(θ)Fj(θ) almost everywhere over TiTj) holds for every pair of i,jN¯, where ij.

Let Fi represent an inverse function of Fi supported on [0,1].

The next claim suffices to show that all types belonging to N¯ should commonly use at least one message.

Claim 1. Take θiN¯Ti such that Fi(θ)Fj(θ) for every pair of i,jN¯, where ij. Let si=Fi(θ). Then, for any iN¯, an action a ' induced by type i given s = si (and hence in its neighborhood) should be induced by type j given some s[min{sj,si},max{sj,si}] (and hence in its neighborhood) for every jN¯.

This claim implies that all types belonging to N¯ should induce at least one same action. Hence, all types belonging to N¯ should commonly use at least one message.

Proof.

Without loss of generality, consider 1,2N¯ and s1>s2. Then:

F1(s2)<F1(s1)=θ=F2(s2)<F2(s1)aS(F1(s2))<aS(θ)<aS(F2(s1)).

Besides, type 1 (i.e. S observing t = 1) infers:

F={F1withprobabilityp+(1p)q1F2withprobability(1p)q2,FjwherejN{1,2}otherwise

and type 2 (i.e. S observing t = 2) infers:

F={F1withprobability(1p)q1F2withprobabilityp+(1p)q2.FjwherejN{1,2}otherwise

Hence:

US¯(a,s1,b;1)=(p+(1p)q1)US(a,θ,b)+(1p)q2US(a,F2(s1),b)+jN{1,2}(1p)qjUS(a,Fj(s1),b),US¯(a,s1,b;2)=(1p)q1US(a,θ,b)+(p+(1p)q2)US(a,F2(s1),b)+jN{1,2}(1p)qjUS(a,Fj(s1),b),US¯(a,s2,b;1)=(p+(1p)q1)US(a,F1(s2),b)+(1p)q2US(a,θ,b)+jN{1,2}(1p)qjUS(a,Fj(s2),b),US¯(a,s2,b;2)=(1p)q1US(a,F1(s2),b)+(p+(1p)q2)US(a,θ,b)+jN{1,2}(1p)qjUS(a,Fj(s2),b).

Then,

AS(s2,b;1)<AS(s2,b;2)<AS(s1,b;1)<AS(s1,b;2)

due to U11S<0, Fj(s2)<Fj(s1), F1(s2)<θ<F2(s1) because:

U1S¯(a,s2,b;1)>US¯1(a,s2,b;2)>US¯1(a,s1,b;1)>US¯1(a,s1,b;2)for any a.

Also, for any a > a'

US¯(a,s2,b;1)US¯(a,s2,b;1)<US¯(a,s2,b;2)US¯(a,s2,b;2)<US¯(a,s1,b;1)US¯(a,s1,b;1)<US¯(a,s1,b;2)US¯(a,s1,b;2)

due to U12S>0, Fj(s2)<Fj(s1), F1(s2)<θ<F2(s1).

Take an action a' induced by type 1 given s = s1 (and hence in its neighborhood). Then, a' should be induced by type 2 given some s[s2,s1] (and hence in its neighborhood) as follows.

If a(AS(s2,b;2),AS(s1,b;2)), by continuity, there must be s(s2,s1) such that AS(s,b;2)=a. The action a' should be induced by type 2 given s in the neighborhood of s'.

Consider aAS(s2,b;2). If some action a~>a is inducible on the equilibrium path, due to the revealed preference:

0US¯(a~,s1,b;1)US¯(a,s1,b;1),

and

US¯(a~,s1,b;1)US¯(a,s1,b;1)>US¯(a~,s2,b;2)US¯(a,s2,b;2).

In this case, because type 1 given s1 weakly prefers a' to a~, type 2 given s = s2 strictly prefers a' to a~. If a' is the highest inducible action, type 2 given s = s2 strictly prefers a' to any action a < a' because US¯(a,s2,b;2) is increasing with a for a < a'. The action a' should be induced by type 2 given s in the neighborhood of s2.

Consider aAS(s1,b;2). If some action a~<a is inducible on the equilibrium path, due to the revealed preference:

0US¯(a,s1,b;2)US¯(a~,s1,b;2)

and:

US¯(a,s1,b;1)US¯(a~,s1,b;1)<US¯(a,s1,b;2)US¯(a~,s1,b;2).

In this case, because type 1 given s1 weakly prefers a' to a~, type 2 given s = s1 strictly prefers a' to a~. If a' is the lowest inducible action, type 2 given s = s1 strictly prefers a' to any action a > a' because US¯(a,s1,b;2) is decreasing with a for a > a'. The action a' should be induced by type 2 given s in the neighborhood of s1.

Similarly, an action induced by type 2 given s = s2 is also induced by type 1. (Take a' induced by type 2 given s = s2. If a(AS(s2,b;1),AS(s1,b;1)), a' should be induced by type 1 given s in the neighborhood of s' where AS(s,b;1)=a. If aAS(s2,b;1), a' should be induced by type 1 given s in the neighborhood of s2. If aAS(s1,b;1), a' should be induced by type 1 given s in the neighborhood of s1).

The above proof applies to any types i,jN¯.  ■

The next claim suffices to show that if p(0,1), all types belonging to N¯ should commonly use at least one message for different extensions.

Claim 2. Fix p(0,1). When two types commonly use some message and at least one type use multiple messages, then, the two types use the common message for different extensions.

Proof.

If three actions a < a' < a" are induced by type 1, and a and a" are induced by type 2 as well, then, a' should be induced by type 2.

It suffices to consider two cases: first, two actions are induced by type 1 and type 2; second, only one action is induced by both types.

In the first case, let a and a' be induced by type 1 and type 2, where a < a' . Type 1 and type 2 are indifferent between the two actions at s = x and s = y, respectively. Let m be used to induce a. The underlying states (given which each sends m) include the neighborhoods of θ=F1(x) and θ=F2(x) for type 1 and the neighborhoods of θ=F1(y) and θ=F2(y) for type 2. Thus, it suffices to show xy. This inequality holds because S’s indifference conditions require:

US¯(a,x,b;1)=US¯(a,x,b;1)p+(1p)q1(1p)q2=US(a,F2(x),b)US(a,F2(x),b)US(a,F1(x),b)US(a,F1(x),b)

and:

US¯(a,y,b;2)=US¯(a,y,b;2)(1p)q1p+(1p)q2=US(a,F2(y),b)US(a,F2(y),b)US(a,F1(y),b)US(a,F1(y),b),

but p+(1p)q1(1p)q2(1p)q1p+(1p)q2.

In the second case, suppose type 1 induces a for s(x,x) and a' for s(x,x"), where a < a'; type 2 induces a for s(y,y) and a" for s(y,y"), where a < a" a'. Single crossing properties imply xy . Suppose not, x=y. Then, min{a,a"}>max{AS(x,1,b),AS(x,2,b)}. US¯(a,x,b;1) and US¯(a,y,b;2) both decrease with a over amax{AS(x,1,b),AS(x,2,b)}, and type 1’s choice implies that a' is the highest inducible action over amax{AS(x,1,b),AS(x,2,b)}, i.e. a' ≥ a". Type 2’s choice implies a' a". There is a contradiction. ■

If p = 1 or p = 0, x = y should hold. If p = 1, multiple types belonging to N¯ can commonly use a message (messages) for the same extension. If p = 0, the sender does not have type information.

A.2 Section 4 (the Uniform-Quadratic Case)

We present results to support the arguments in Section 4, including Remark 1.

A.2.1 One-Dimensional State-Uncertainty

In A.2.1, we consider a game under one-dimensional state-uncertainty (i.e. p = 1 and type signal t is public information).

Lemma.

Fix b(0,). Consider a partition equilibrium with N1N2intervals. In a subgame given type t, where t{1,2}:

(1) Type t’s partition satisfies Δθi=Δθi1+4b for i{2,...,Nt}.

(2) Type t sends m = migiven θ(θi1,θi) so that mimi for any ii.

(3) R selects a = aigiven m = misuch that ai=θi1+θi2 for i{1,...,Nt}.

Proof.

For each subgame, the outcome is defined by S’s indifference conditions (S’s ICs) and R’s best responses (R’s BRs).

At any boundary point θ = θi for i{1,...,Ni1}, any type of S should be indifferent between two actions, a = ai and a = ai + 1:

(θi+bai)2=(ai+1θib)2ai+1+ai=2θi+2b(S's ICs)

Given m = mi for i{1,...,Nt}, R updates his belief on the state using Bayes’ rule and selects the optimal action a=ai:

ai=E[θ|θ(θi1,θi)]=θi1+θi2.(R's BRs)

Hence, regardless of S’s type, S’s ICs and R’s BRs define the partition such that Δθi=Δθi1+4b for i{2,...,Nt}. ■

Lemma 4.

Fix b(0,). Consider a subgame given type t, where t{1,2}. Then, there is a positive integer NtCS(b) such that there is an equilibrium where type t partitions the state space into N intervals for N{1,2,...,NtCS(b)}. Further, NtCS(b) decreases with b.

Proof.

The previous lemma implies Δθi=θ1+4(i1)b for i{1,...,N} for any type. Hence, the existence of an equilibrium with N intervals requires θ1 > 0 and:

θN=i=1NΔθi=Nθ1+2N(N1)b=i.

For any b > 0, NtCS(b) is well defined such that N1CS(b)=n for b[bn+1,bn) for n ≥ 1 and N2CS(b)=N for b[LbN+1,LbN) for N ≥ 1. ■

A.2.2 Two-Dimensional State-Uncertainty

In A.2.2, we consider a game under two-dimensional state-uncertainty (i.e. type signal t is S’s private information).

Lemma 5.

Fix p(0,1) and b(0,). Any PBE is a partition equilibrium. Further, in a partition equilibrium with N1N2intervals:

  1. There is a unique N1for N2, and N1N2.

  2. Gb,p(N1)=ΔxN1ΔxN1+ΔyN1((L(1+p)+1p)(yN11+yN1)4(1+p+L(1p))(xN11+xN1)4)0.

  3. Type 1’s partition x(N1) satisfies:

    Δ x i = Δ x i 1 + 8 b 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) f o r i { 2 , . . . , N 1 1 } . Δ x i Δ x i 1 + 8 b 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) f o r i = N 1 .

  4. Type 2’s partition y(N2) satisfies:

    Δ y i = { Δ y i 1 + 8 b L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p f o r i { 2 , . . . , N 2 } { N 1 , N 1 + 1 } , Δ y i 1 + 8 b L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p + 4 L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p G b , p ( N 1 ) f o r i { N 1 , N 1 + 1 } .

  5. Relationship between partitions of both types is:

    x i = { L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) y i f o r i { 1 , . . . , N 1 1 } , 1 ( L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) y N 1 ) f o r i = N 1 .

  6. Both types send m = migiven s(xi1,xi) (if this interval exists) and s(yi1,yi), respectively, for i{1,...,N2}, where mimj for any ji.

  7. R selects a = aigiven m = misuch that:

    a i = { ( L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p ) ( y i 1 + y i ) 4 \textit{for}   i { 1 , . . . , N 2 } { N 1 } , ( L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p ) ( y i 1 + y i ) 4 G b , p ( N 1 ) \textit{for}   i = N 1 ,

    where a1, ..., aN1 is also described as follows:

    a i = { ( 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) ) ( x i 1 + x i ) 4 \textit{for}   i { 1 , . . . , N 2 } { N 1 } , ( 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) ) ( x i 1 + x i ) 4 + Δ y N 1 Δ x N 1 G b , p ( N 2 ) \textit{for}   i = N 1 .

Proof.

To define a partition, we consider indifference conditions for each type of S (S’s ICs) and R’s best responses (R’s BRs) for the game under two-dimensional state-uncertainty.

Suppose ai and ai+1 are induced in the i-th and (i+1)-th intervals, respectively, by type 1. At the boundary point s = xi, type 1’s ICs require:

ai+1+ai=(1+p+L(1p))xi+2b.(S's ICs (t = 1))

Similarly, suppose ai and ai+1 are induced in the i-th and (i+1)-th intervals, respectively, by type 2. At the boundary point s = yi, type 2’s ICs require:

ai+1+ai=(L(1+p)+1p)yi+2b.(S's ICs (t = 2))

Thus, if ai and ai + 1 are induced by both types of S, then xi=L(1+p)+1p1+p+L(1p)yi. Type 1’s ideal action given signal s = xi is equivalent to type 2’s ideal action given signal s = yi for i{1,2,...,N11} (because type 1’s ideal action given s is a=1+p+L(1p)2s+b while type 2’ ideal action given s is a=L(1+p)+1p2s+b).

R’s BRs require that given m = mi for any i{1,2,...,N1} (i. e. both types use mi):

ai=Pr[m=mi|t=1]E[θ|mi,t=1]+Pr[m=mi|t=2]E[θ|mi,t=2]Pr[m=mi|t=1]+Pr[m=mi|t=2](R's BRs)

given m = mi for i{N1+1,...,N2} (i. e. only type 2 use mi) is

ai=E[θ|mi,t=2],(R's BRs)

where E[θ|mi,t=1]=(1+p+L(1p))(xi1+xi)4 and E[θ|mi,t=2]=(L(1+p)+1p)(yi1+yi)4. S’s ICs imply E[θ|mi,t=1]=E[θ|mi,t=2] for i{1,...,N11} while E[θ|mN1,t=1]E[θ|mN1,t=2]. Thus, ai is well defined as claimed.   □

Lemma 6.

Fix p(0,1) and b(0,). Consider mt in a partition equilibrium with N1N2 intervals, where t{1,2,...,N11}. Information provided by type 2 second order stochastically dominates (SOSD) information provided by type 1.

Proof.

Type 1 uses mi given s(xi1,xi) while type 2 uses mi given signal s(yi1,yi). The two conditional distributions have the same mean

(L(1+p)+1p)(yi1+yi)4=(1+p+L(1p))(xi1+xi)4,

but different supports; and the former has larger variances than the latter as follows.

Table 1:
Type Support Variances
t=1 ( x i 1 , x i ) ( L x i 1 , L x i ) ( 1 + p + L 2 ( 1 p ) ) ( x i 1 2 + x i 1 x i + x i 2 ) 6 ( 1 + p + L ( 1 p ) ) ( x i 1 + x i ) 2 4 2
t=2 ( y i 1 , y i ) ( L y i 1 , L y i ) ( L 2 ( 1 + p ) + 1 p ) ( y i 1 2 + y i 1 y i + y i 2 ) 6 ( L ( 1 + p ) + 1 p ) 2 ( y i 1 + y i ) 2 4 2
  1. This table compares two conditional distributions: one for information which type 1 transmits when sending message mi (see the second row) and another for information which type 2 transmits when sending mi (see the third row).

   □

A.3 Proofs for Section 5.1 (Discrete Model)

A.3.1 Proof for Remark 2

We find sufficient conditions which satisfy the next three claims.

Claim 1. Under two-dimensional uncertainty, there exists an equilibrium in which every type uses different messages for different signals, as shown in Figure 3.

Claim 2. Under two-dimensional uncertainty, there is no equilibrium in which different types use different messages for s = 1. (Language is vague).

Claim 3. Under one-dimensional uncertainty, there only exists a babbling equilibrium given type 1 while there is a separation equilibrium given type 2, as shown in Figure 4.

Claim 1 holds if b<1+L4 as follows. Under two-dimensional uncertainty, in the supposed equilibrium, each type induces a = 0 given s = 0 and a=1+L2 given s = 1. Thus, this equilibrium exists if both types prefer a = 0 to a = 1 given s = 0.

Claim 2 holds if b>p(L1)2 as follows. Under two-dimensional uncertainty, if different types use different messages for s = 1, type 1 induces a = 0 given s = 0 and a=1+p+(1p)L2 given s = 1 while type 2 induces a = 0 given s = 0 and a=(1+p)L+1p2 given s = 1. However, if b>p(L1)2, type 1’s most preferred action is not a=1+p+(1p)L2 given s = 1 among all inducible actions.

Claim 3 holds if b(12,L2] as follows. Under one-dimensional uncertainty, each type of S knows the state (because s = θ) and induces a = θ by sending m = s in a separating equilibrium if it exists. We can show that a separating equilibrium exists for a type if this type wants to induce low action a = 0 for θ = 0. The condition is b12 for type 1 and bL2 for type 2.

Therefore, if 1 < L < 2, b(12,1+L4) suffices to satisfy the three claims.

Then, fix b(12,1+L4). We look at the most informative equilibrium. Under two-dimensional state-uncertainty, both types send m = Null given s = 0 and m = Large given s = 1, as shown in Figure 3. R’s ex-ante expected payoff is:

12((1L)28)F=F1+12((1L)28)F=F2=(1L)28,

where:

{12((00)2)θ=0+12((11+L2)2)θ=1=(1L)28if F=F1,12((00)2)θ=0+12((L1+L2)2)θ=L=(1L)28if F=F2.

Under one-dimensional uncertainty, we consider a babbling equilibrium given type 1 and a separation equilibrium given type 2, as shown in Figure 4. R’s ex-ante expected payoff is:

12(14)F=F1+12(0)F=F2=18,

where:

{12((012)2)θ=0+12((112)2)θ=1=14if F=F1,12((00)2)θ=0+12((LL)2)θ=L=0if F=F2.

Hence, R is better-off under two-dimensional state-uncertainty.

Fix b<12. Under one-dimensional state-uncertainty, there is a separation equilibrium given each type. R’s ex-ante expected payoff is:

12(0)F=F1+12(0)F=F2=0.

Hence, R is worse-off under two-dimensional state-uncertainty.

Fix b>1+L4. Under two-dimensional state-uncertainty, there only exists a babbling equilibrium in which only a=1+L4 is induced by both types. R’s ex-ante expected payoff is:

12(L22L+516)F=F1+12(5L22L+116)F=F2=3L22L+38(<L22L+316).

Under one-dimensional state-uncertainty, there only exists a babbling equilibrium in which only a=12 (a=L2) is induced given type 1 (type 2). R’s ex-ante expected payoff is:

12(14)F=F1+12((1L)28)F=F2=L22L+316.

Hence, R is worse-off under two-dimensional state-uncertainty.

A.3.2 Proof for Remark 3

Let a0 = 0, a1=1+p+(1p)L2 and a2=(1+p)L+1p2 (i. e. a0<a1<a2). If the type is revealed in the first stage, type 1 can induce a0 and a1 while type 2 can induce a0 and a2, respectively, in the second stage. But type 1 knows he will prefer a2 to a1 given s = 1. Hence, type 1 pretends to be type 2.

A.4 Proofs for Section 5.2 (Different Prior Beliefs)

A.4.1 Proof for Remark 4

The proof and the outcome are similar to those for a model in Section 4. We only show differences in equilibrium outcome from the basic model.

Type 2’s partition y(N2) satisfies:

Δyi={Δyi1+4(qRqS)(1p)2qR(1p)yifor i{2,...,N2}{N1,N1+1},Δyi1+4(qRqS)(1p)2qR(1p)yi+2Gb,p(N1)(1+(1p)(1qR)+p)for i{N1,N1+1}.

The relationship between partitions of both types is:

xi={1+(1p)(1qS)+p1+(1p)(1qS)yifor i{N1,N1+1},1(1+(1p)(1qS)+p1+(1p)(1qS)yN1)for i=N1.

R selects a = ai given m = mi such that:

ai={(1+(1p)(1qR)+p)(yi1+yi)2for i{1,...,N2}{N1},(1+(1p)(1qR)+p)(yi1+yi)2Gb,p(N1)for i=N1.

Due to the difference in prior beliefs |qRqS|, any type of S cannot credibly separate messages for signals. Then, as in the basic model, the communication should have a partitional form. The players use a smaller number of messages as |qRqS| increases. Moreover, in a partition equilibrium with N1N2 intervals, both types of S commonly use messages m1,m2,...,mN1. Type 1’s ideal action given signal s = xi is equivalent to type 2’s ideal action given s = yi, which is a=(1+(1p)(1qS)+p)yi + b, for i{1,...,N11}.

A.4.2 Proof for Remark 5

In a partition equilibrium with N intervals, the partition satisfies:

Δxi=Δxi1+42qRb+4(qRqS)2qRxifori{2,...,N}.

S send m = migiven s(xi1,xi) for i{1,...,N} so that mimi for any ii. Then, R selects a = ai given m = misuch that ai=(2qR)(xi1+xi)4 for i{1,...,N}.

Therefore, we observe non-monotonic relationships unless qR=qS (common prior belief). For example, by fixing qR=14 and qS=34, a larger |b| can result in a smaller or larger NDP(b,qR,qS):

NDP(b,qR,qS)={4forb(33758416,223544),3forb(1748,225464)(33758416,223544),2forb(1116,1516)(1748,225464),1otherwise.

For another example, by fixing b=38 and qR=12, a larger |qRqS| can result in a smaller or larger NDP(b,qR,qS):

NDP(b,qR,qS)={4for qS(2932116,4+(476121545])1/3+(476+121545])1/316),3for qS(78,1)(2932116,4+(476121545])1/3+(476+121545])1/316),2for b(12,78),1for b(0,12).

References

Arrow, Kenneth J. 1974. The Limits of Organization. New York, NY: W. W. North & Co.Search in Google Scholar

Aumann, Robert J. 1976. “Agreeing to Disagree.” The Annals of Statistics 4 (6): 1236–39.10.1007/978-3-319-20451-2_40Search in Google Scholar

Blume, Andreas, Oliver Board, and Kohei Kawamura. 2007. “Noisy Talk,” Theoretical Economics 2: 395–440.Search in Google Scholar

Blume, Andreas, and Oliver Board. 2013. “Language Barriers.” Econometrica 81 (2): 781–812.10.3982/ECTA9183Search in Google Scholar

Blume, Andreas, and Oliver Board. 2014. “Intentional Vagueness,” Erkenntnis 79 (S4): 855–99.10.1007/s10670-013-9468-xSearch in Google Scholar

Che, Yeon-Koo, and Navin Kartik. 2009. “Opinions as Incentives,” Journal of Political Economy 117 (5): 815–60.10.1086/648432Search in Google Scholar

Chiba, Saori. 2014. Extensions and Vagueness of Language under Two-Dimensional State Uncertainty. Department of Management, Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia WP No.20/2014.10.2139/ssrn.2511319Search in Google Scholar

Chiba, Saori, and Kaiwen Leong. 2013. “Cheap Talk with Outside Options.” Department of Management, Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia WP No.16/2013.10.2139/ssrn.2332689Search in Google Scholar

Crawford, Vincent P., and Joel Sobel. 1982. “Strategic Information Transmission.” Econometrica 50 (6): 1431–51.10.2307/1913390Search in Google Scholar

Crémer, Jacques, Luis Garicano, and Andrea Prat. 2007. “Language and the Theory of the Firm.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 122 (1): 373–407.10.1162/qjec.122.1.373Search in Google Scholar

De Jaegher, Kris. 2003. “A Game-Theoretic Rationale for Vagueness,” Linguistics and Philosophy 26: 637–59.10.1023/A:1025853728992Search in Google Scholar

De Jaegher, Kris, and Robert van Rooij. 2011. “Strategic Vagueness, and Appropriate Context,” In Language, Games, and Evolution: Trends in Current Research on Language and Game Theory, 13, edited by Anton Benz, Christian Ebert, Gerhard Jäger, Robert van Rooij, 40–59. Berlin, Germany: Springer.10.1007/978-3-642-18006-4_3Search in Google Scholar

Fine, Kit. 1975. “Vagueness, Truth and Logic.” Synthese 30: 265–300.10.7551/mitpress/7064.003.0011Search in Google Scholar

Franke, Michael, Gerhard Jäger, & Robert van Rooij. 2011. “Vagueness, Signaling and Bounded Rationality.” New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 6797: 45–59.10.1007/978-3-642-25655-4_5Search in Google Scholar

Kawamura, Kohei. 2013. “Eliciting information from a large population,” Journal of Public Economics 103: 44–54.10.1016/j.jpubeco.2013.04.002Search in Google Scholar

Keefe, Rosanna, and Peter Smith. 1997. Vagueness: A Reader. Cambridge: MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Knight, Frank. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Kissimmee, FL: Signalman Publishing.Search in Google Scholar

Lambie-Hanson, Timothy, and Giri Parameswaran. 2015. “A Model of Vague Communication.” mimeo.Search in Google Scholar

Lewis, David. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Lim, Wooyoung, and Qinggong Wu. 2018. “Vague Language and Context Dependence.” mimeo.Search in Google Scholar

Lipman, Barton. 2002. “Language and Economics.” mimeo.Search in Google Scholar

Lipman, Barton. 2009 “Why is Language Vague?” mimeo.Search in Google Scholar

March, James G., and Herbert A. Simon. 1958. Organizations. New York, NY: John Wiley.Search in Google Scholar

Morgan, John, and Phillip C. Stocken. 2008. “Information Aggregation in Polls.” American Economic Review 98 (3): 864–96.10.1257/aer.98.3.864Search in Google Scholar

Myerson, Roger B. 1991. Game Theory: Analysis of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

O’Connor, Cailin. 2014. “The Evolution of Vagueness.” Erkenntnis 79 (4): 707–27.10.1007/s10670-013-9463-2Search in Google Scholar

Parameswaran, Giri, and Timothy Lambie-Hanson. 2016. “Imperfect Perception and Vagueness.” mimeo.Search in Google Scholar

Peirce, Charles S. 1902. “Vague.” In Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, editd by J. M. Baldwin, 748. New York, NY: MacMillan.Search in Google Scholar

Rubinstein, Ariel. 2000. Economics and Language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511492358Search in Google Scholar

Sides, John, Daron R. Shaw, Matt Grossmann, and Keena Lipsitz. 2015. Campaigns and Elections. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.Search in Google Scholar

Snook, Scott A. 2000. The Accidental Shootdown of U.S. Black Hawks over Northern Iraq. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Sorensen, Roy A. 2001. Vagueness and Contradiction. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780199241309.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1974. “Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases.” Science 185: 1124–31.10.21236/AD0767426Search in Google Scholar

Van den Steen, Eric. 2010. “Interpersonal Authority in a Theory of the Firm.” American Economic Review 100 (1): 466–90.10.1257/aer.100.1.466Search in Google Scholar

Warglien, Massimo. 2013. “Language and Organizations.” In Handbook of Economic Organization: Integrating Economic and Organization Theory, edited by Anna Grandori, 137–56. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.10.4337/9781849803984.00016Search in Google Scholar

Williamson, Timothy. 1994. Vagueness. New York, NY: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Williamson, Timothy. 2003. “Vagueness in Reality.” In The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, editd by Michael J. Loux, and Dean W. Zimmerman, 690–716. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Zadeh, Lotfi. 1975. “Fuzzy Logic and Approximate Reasoning.” Synthese 30: 407–28.10.1142/9789814261302_0016Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2019-10-22

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Articles in the same Issue

  1. Research Articles
  2. Optimal Forestry Contract with Interdependent Costs
  3. Bi and Branching Strict Nash Networks in Two-way Flow Models: A Generalized Sufficient Condition
  4. Pay-What-You-Want in Competition
  5. Two Rationales for Insufficient Entry
  6. Students’ Social Origins and Targeted Grading
  7. Pricing, Signalling, and Sorting with Frictions
  8. On the Economic Value of Signals
  9. The Core in Bertrand Oligopoly TU-Games with Transferable Technologies
  10. Reasoning About ‘When’ Instead of ‘What’: Collusive Equilibria with Stochastic Timing in Repeated Oligopoly
  11. Timing Games with Irrational Types: Leverage-Driven Bubbles and Crash-Contingent Claims
  12. Costly Rewards and Punishments
  13. Blocking Coalitions and Fairness in Asset Markets and Asymmetric Information Economies
  14. Strategic Activism in an Uncertain World
  15. On Equilibrium Existence in a Finite-Agent, Multi-Asset Noisy Rational Expectations Economy
  16. Optimal Incentives Under Gift Exchange
  17. Public Good Indices for Games with Several Levels of Approval
  18. Vagueness of Language: Indeterminacy under Two-Dimensional State-Uncertainty
  19. Winners and Losers of Universal Health Insurance: A Macroeconomic Analysis
  20. Behavioral Theory of Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma: Generous Tit-For-Tat Strategy
  21. Flourishing as Productive Tension: Theory and Model
  22. Notes
  23. A Note on Reference-Dependent Choice with Threshold Representation
  24. Regular Equilibria and Negative Welfare Implications in Delegation Games
  25. Unbundling Production with Decreasing Average Costs
  26. A Simple and Procedurally Fair Game Form for Nash Implementation of the No-Envy Solution
  27. Decision Making and Games with Vector Outcomes
  28. Capital Concentration and Wage Inequality
  29. Annuity Markets and Capital Accumulation
Downloaded on 22.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2018-0093/html
Scroll to top button