Abstract
This article develops an equilibrium sorting model with utility maximizing agents (researchers) on one side of the market, and on the other side institutions (universities) and an outside sector. Researchers are assumed to care about peer effects, their relative status within universities, and salary compensation. They differ in their concern for salary compensation as well as in their ability. We derive the unique stable equilibrium allocation of researchers and investigate the effects on the academic sector of changes in the outside option as well as the interaction between the outside option and the researchers’ concern for relative status. In any equilibrium, the right-hand side of the ability distribution is allocated to the academic sector, while the left-hand side of the ability distribution is allocated to the outside sector, with possible overlap between sectors and within the academic sector. The universities’ qualities are determined endogenously, and we show that an increase in the value of the outside option decreases the difference in quality between the higher and lower ranked universities. Furthermore, differences in average salaries between the institutions arise endogenously.
Acknowledgments
We thank Dan Bernhardt, Odilon Camara, Lorne Carmichael, Steve Coate, Allen Head, Justin Johnson, George Mailath, Frank Milne, Larry Samuelson, Jan Zabojnik, seminar participants at Aarhus University and Queen’s University, two anonymous referees, and the editor for comments. The Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) provided financial support for this research.
Appendix
A AProof of Theorem 1
Since ,
, is defined as the closure of the set of types at which
is strictly increasing,
and
. We first prove that if
,
, and
, then
and
. Suppose to the contrary that
. Then, there exists
such that
and
. Since
, agents of ability type
strictly prefer A. This is a contradiction, since ability type
is higher than the lowest ability type working for A and thus has the option of moving to A. Suppose now, to reach another contradiction, that
. Then, there exists
such that
and
. Since
, agents of ability type
strictly prefer A. This is again a contradiction, since type
is higher than the lowest ability type working for A and thus has the option of moving to A.
We now show that if and
, then
and
. To see this, note that
implies that
. Also, note that for
, we have that
, so
.
Suppose now, in order to reach a contradiction, that . The support set
is defined as the closure of the set of types at which
is strictly increasing, so
must be a limit point of some neighborhood that belongs to
, and this neighborhood must necessarily be to the right of the minimum. Then, for
, we have that
![[2]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq4.png)
Since researchers always have the possibility of switching to the outside sector, it must hold that
![[3]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq5.png)
because otherwise some type with
close to
would move to the outside sector. Inequality [3] implies that
![[4]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq6.png)
Since for all
and
, it must be the case that
![[5]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq7.png)
But inequalities [2], [4], and [5] imply that , which is equivalent to
. Hence, a researcher in
close to
would be better off switching to B, which contradicts that
. Thus,
.
Suppose instead, to reach another contradiction, that . Then, it must hold that
![[6]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq8.png)
since researchers of ability type have the option of moving to B, but are choosing C over B. Inequality [6] is equivalent to
![[7]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq9.png)
Since is non-increasing in
, and
, it must be the case that
![[8]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq10.png)
for all . Also,
for all
. This, together with inequalities [7] and [8] implies that
![[9]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq11.png)
for all and for all
. Because researchers can always switch to the outside sector, this implies that
. Hence, assuming that
has led to a contradiction, because it was assumed that
. Thus,
. An analogous argument shows that if
and
, then
and
.
We next show that ,
, and
are intervals. To see this, suppose that
is non-empty and not an interval. Then, there exist types
and
, with
such that all ability types on
choose B or C, while
and
. Thus, it must be that
and either
and/or
. Furthermore, since
is the closure of the set of types for which
is strictly increasing, types in small neighborhoods below
and above
are in the support set of A.
If then, since types
and
have the option of switching between A and B, both ability types must be indifferent between A and B:
![[10]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq12.png)
and
![[11]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq13.png)
Since , eqs [10] and [11] imply that
, which contradicts that
.
If instead then, since all ability types
have the option of switching between A and C, it must be the case that
![[12]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq14.png)
for all and for all
. Since
, ability types
in a small neighborhood below
are also in
. For these
,
because
is non-increasing in
, and
. This together with inequality [12] implies that
for all
, so these ability types would prefer to switch to the outside sector, which contradicts that they belong to the support set of A.
Hence, assuming that there exist types and
, with
such that all types on
choose B or C, while
and
has lead to a contradiction. It follows that
is an interval. A similar argument proves that
is an interval.
Suppose finally that is non-empty and not an interval. Then, there exist ability types
and
, with
such that all ability types on
choose A or B, while
and
. Suppose, without loss of generality, that
.
Since ability types have the option of switching between B and
it must be the case that
![[13]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq15.png)
which gives
![[14]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq16.png)
For in neighborhood above
,
, because
is non-increasing in
, and
. With inequality [14], this implies that
![[15]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq17.png)
This contradicts that so
must be an interval.
Next, we establish that if and
, then
for heterogenous
s and
for a homogenous
. A similar argument applies to show these inequalities with
replacing
when
,
, and
.
Since researchers always have the option of switching to the outside sector, we must have that
![[16]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq18.png)
This implies that for some
If some researchers of ability type prefer the outside sector to university B, that is,
for some
, then
. Suppose instead, for a contradiction, that
. Since researchers always have the option of switching to the outside sector, we must have that
for all
, which implies
for all
. This contradicts that
for some
. Therefore,
if
for some
.
If , then inequality [16] holds for all
and
. To see this, suppose that
. Then, we have
. Under the supposition, we must have
for some
, which implies
![[17]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq19.png)
Since is non-decreasing in
and
, we havethat
This contradicts inequality [17], because
and
Therefore, if
, then
. Finally, by definition an equilibrium allocation is a feasible allocation and, thus, has
for all
, that is, in any equilibrium every researcher works in either A, B, or C. Therefore, and because
,
, and
are intervals,
. Then, again by feasibility of the equilibrium, it must also be the case that
.
To establish that with homogenous
, suppose that
. A researcher of ability type
is the lowest ability researcher who works for B and, therefore, has rank
. Since it is already established that
, it must, hence, be that
![[18]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq20.png)
Researchers with must be indifferent between B and the outside option. Furthermore,
for
, since
for all
. We, thus, have that for
,

using the result in inequality [18]. This implies that , a contradiction with
. Therefore,
, which establishes that
. Following the same argument as the case with heterogenous
s,
and
. Hence, we have established that there exists
such that
, while
work in the academic sector. ■
B Complete characterization for, and proof of, Theorem 2
Complete characterization for Theorem 2: Under Assumptions 1 and 2, there exists a unique stable sorting equilibrium.
Defining the following constants:
,
and the following functions:
,
the equilibrium is
UFS if
, and
CFS if
,
, and
USU if
,
, and
UPO if
, and
CPO if
,
,
, and
UFO if
, and
CFO if
,
, and
CSU if
, and
CFO or CSU if
, and
EAS if
Proof of Theorem 2
To prove Theorem 2, we first solve for the cut-offs v, z, y, and x, as well as for the slopes of the non-normalized type-distributions ,
, and
across
-space. We can, then, solve for the regions of
-space in which the different equilibria exist, for the universities’ qualities, and for the influence of the outside option on the size of the academic sector in the constrained equilibria. We proceed to show that the equilibria described in Theorem 2 are stable and that there is a unique stable equilibrium across
-space. Finally, we prove the comparative statics results.
Recall that according to Assumption 1, . Also, note that eq. [1] gives that

A researcher of type z is the highest ability researcher who works in the outside sector. Hence, is constant and equal to
on
. As established in Theorem 1,
and, thus,
, and it follows that
. Since
, it follows that
On
everyone works in the outside sector. We conclude that the non-normalized distribution of types in the outside sector is

Consider first full segregation. With full segregation, . The non-normalized distributions of types,
,
, and
, under full segregation are illustrated in Figure 2. By Theorem 1, it is the top end of the ability distribution that will choose to work in academia. With full segregation, all of the highest ability researchers choose to work for the better university A, while the best of the remaining researchers choose to work for B. Only a researcher with
is indifferent between A and B. It follows easily, in addition to the values for
found above, that under full segregation

and

In particular, we have that and
.
The peer effect at university A is then given by

while the peer effect at university B is given by

The full segregation equilibrium is unconstrained as long as , that is, as long as the peer effect in B when both universities’ demands are satisfied is as least as high as the wage difference between the outside and academic sectors for the threshold type
. When this is satisfied, the lowest ranked researcher in B has higher utility from working at B than from working in the outside sector. Therefore, the boundary between UFS and CFS is given by

Full segregation also requires that the difference in peer effect is large enough that no researcher wishes to move from A to B. Under UFS, this condition is given by
![[19]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq29.png)
As long as inequality [19] is satisfied, the lowest ranked researcher at A has at least as high utility from staying at A as from moving to B. Thus, the North boundary of UFS is given by

When instead , the full segregation equilibrium is constrained and the size of the academic sector is determined by the equation
![[20]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq31.png)
That is, the size of the academic sector is pinned down by such that the lowest ranked researcher in B gets exactly the same utility from working at B as he would from working in the outside sector.
The lowest ranked researcher at B, , strictly prefers A to B in CFS, since his ranking is zero at either university and
in CFS. Suppose, in order to reach a contradiction, that
. Since
, condition (ii) of Definition 2 implies that
, which contradicts that
strictly prefers A to B. We therefore have that
in CFS. This together with eq. [20] implies that under CFS the size of university B,
, is determined implicitly by the equation
![[21]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq32.png)
In CFS, university B hires some researchers, . Setting
in eq. [21] gives the CFS/USU boundary:
![[22]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq33.png)
At the CFS/CPO boundary, the lowest type at university A is indifferent between university A and university B: . Rearranging, we have
. Therefore, we need
for
Substituting into eq. [21] gives the CFS/CPO boundary:
![[23]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq34.png)
Totally differentiating eq. [23] gives that on the CFS/CPO boundary,

so the CFS/CPO boundary is downward sloping.
Consider now partial overlap. With partial overlap, . The non-normalized distributions of types,
,
, and
, under partial overlap are illustrated in Figure 3. Again, by Theorem 1, it is the top end of the ability distribution that will choose to work in academia. When there is overlap, all researchers with ability
in the interval
are indifferent between the two universities, thus both
and
are increasing on
as illustrated in Figure 3.
To find the non-normalized type-distributions and
under partial overlap, we first find their values at the critical points z, y, and x. With
, we see that
, since researchers in
are allocated exclusively to B. A researcher of type x is the highest ability researcher who works for B, hence
and
is constant thereafter. Since y is the lowest type who works for A,
. Finally, researchers in
are allocated exclusively to A, hence
.
Since a researcher of type y is indifferent between A and B, we must have that
![[24]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq36.png)
Since a researcher of type x is also indifferent between A and B, we have that
![[25]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq37.png)
![[26]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq38.png)
Furthermore, researchers with are also indifferent between A and B. Hence, for
,
![[27]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq39.png)
It follows from eq. [27] and the fact that on this interval , that
and
must be linear on
, and if
then
is flatter than
, and vice versa.
We can find the slopes of and
on
from the critical points above and conclude that under partial overlap the non-normalized distribution of types at university A is

while the non-normalized distribution of types at university B is

The peer effect at university B is then given by
![[28]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq42.png)
while the peer effect at university A is
![[29]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq43.png)
Using eqs [28] and [29], the difference in peer effect between A and B is given by

This and eq. [26] imply that

which together with eq. [25] can be used to find that
![[30]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq46.png)
Plugging this back into [26] then gives that
![[31]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq47.png)
Using eqs [28]–[31], we now have that
![[32]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq48.png)
and
![[33]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq49.png)
From eqs [30] and [31] it follows that is equivalent to
![[34]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq50.png)
which is consistent with the North boundaries of UFS and CFS. From eq. [30] it also follows that if and only if
![[35]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq51.png)
and if and only if inequality [35] holds with equality. When the latter is true it is also the case that
, cf eq. [31], and the overlap is full rather than partial.
The partial overlap equilibrium is unconstrained, as long as the peer effect at university B, which is given in eq. [33], calculated with the universities actual demands and
is at least as high as the wage difference between the outside and academic sectors. That is, the equilibrium is UPO as long as
![[36]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq52.png)
Equality in inequality [36] defines a curve in -space, which is the boundary between UPO and CPO. Solving for
in this equality, the boundary is givenby
![[37]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq53.png)
It follows from inequalities [34] and [35] that the South boundary of UPO is given by
![[38]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq54.png)
and the North boundary of UPO is given by

Totally differentiating eq. [37] gives that the UPO/CPO boundary is upward sloping,

because from eq. [38] in UPO.
When inequality [36] does not hold, the partial overlap equilibrium is constrained and the size of the academic sector is determined by the equation
![[39]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq57.png)
That is, the size of the academic sector is pinned down by such that the lowest ranked researcher in B gets exactly the same utility from working at B as he would from working in the outside sector.
The lowest ranked researcher at B, , strictly prefers A to B in CPO, since his ranking is zero at either university and
in CPO. Suppose, in order to reach a contradiction, that
. Since
, condition (ii) of Definition 2 implies that
, which contradicts that
strictly prefers A to B. We therefore have that
in CPO. Thus, the size of university B in CPO is determined implicitly by the equation
![[40]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq58.png)
We need in CPO. Setting
in eq. [40] gives the CPO/USU boundary:
![[41]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq59.png)
Totally differentiating eq. [41] gives that the boundary between CPO and USU is upward sloping,

because with and
inequality [34] gives that
At the CPO/CFO boundary, university B hires researchers of the highest type, . Setting
and
in eq. [30] gives
. Thus,
if and only if
at the CPO/CFO boundary. Substituting
into eq. [40] gives CPO/CFO boundary:
![[42]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq61.png)
Totally differentiating eq. [42] gives that the CPO/CFO boundary is downward sloping:

Consider now full overlap. With full overlap, and
. In this case, A and B share all types in academia, that is, all types in academia are indifferent between A and B. Then
![[43]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq63.png)
This scenario is illustrated in Figure 4.
The full overlap equilibrium is unconstrained as long as
![[44]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq64.png)
If inequality [44] is not satisfied, the full overlap equilibrium is constrained, that is, CFO. Then the size of the academic sector is determined by
![[45]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq65.png)
In CFO, all types in academia are indifferent between A and B. Thus, the size of each university is undetermined. However, the relative university sizes are irrelevant for the researchers’ utilities.
Setting in eq. [45] gives that the CFO/EAS boundary is
![[46]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq66.png)
Setting and
in eq. [45] gives that for
the CFO equilibrium may in fact be a CSU equilibrium.
As we show later, CFO is only stable if . Plugging
into eq. [45] gives that the South CFO boundary is
![[47]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq67.png)
Consider finally single university. The non-normalized distributions of types, ,
, and
, under single university are illustrated in Figure 5. By Theorem 1, the top end of the distribution will choose to work for the better university A, and the remaining researchers will work for the outside sector. It follow that under single university


and

In particular, we have that .
The peer effect at university A is then given by

and the peer effect at university B is .
Single university requires that no researcher would like to move from university A to university B. Under Assumption 2, a researcher will have a rank of zero if he moves to an empty university. The lowest type in A weakly prefers university A to university B if and only if . Under Assumption 2, this condition becomes
. This condition always holds because
, and the peer effect at university B is
because there are no peers at the empty university B. Note that all other types in A also prefer to stay in A, since for those types
.
The lowest type in A weakly prefers university A to the outside sector as long as . The size of university A is unconstrained if
That is, if the peer effect in A is at least as high as the wage difference between the outside and academic sectors for the lowest type in A,
. Therefore, the USU/CSU boundary is given by

If instead then the single university equilibrium is constrained and the size of university A is implicitly determined by
![[48]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq73.png)
Setting gives the CSU/EAS boundary,
![[49]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq74.png)
When this is satisfied, the highest type is indifferent between university A and the outside sector.
Note, for and
, both CFO and CSU equilibria are possible.
In full overlap equilibria, since all types in academia are indifferent between A and B, eq. [10] is satisfied for all types in academia. Therefore, full overlap equilibria are in principle possible across -space. However, as we will show next, they are only stable when
, resulting in the unique stable equilibrium being as depicted in Figures 6 and 7.

Sorting equilibrium with affine salary functions for
We show stability by applying Theorem 6.5 in Stokey and Lucas (1989). Let denote the mean type in academia. That is,

Note that
![[50]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq76.png)
Let t denote the difference in average types between the universities, that is,

Under full overlap, , while under full segregation,
. Under partial overlap,

Define also

By eq. [50],
![[51]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq80.png)
A stationary point has . By Theorem 6.5 in Stokey and Lucas (1989), a stationary point is stable if the derivative
is less than one in absolute value.
Taking the derivative of in eq. [51] gives
![[52]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq81.png)
Taking the derivative w.r.t. t in eq. [29] yields
![[53]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq82.png)
By eq. [24],

which gives that
![[54]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq84.png)
Similarly, by eq. [25],

yielding that
![[55]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq86.png)
Combining eqs [52]–[55], we now have that
![[56]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq87.png)
Now, consider first full overlap allocations. For these, and
. Hence,
, so full overlap allocations are stationary points. Plugging
and
into eq. [56] gives that

Thus, if and only if
. This implies that UFO allocations are stable for
. Under CFO on the other hand,
only North-East of the CPO/CFO boundary given by eq. [42]. Therefore, CFO allocations are stable for
![[57]](/document/doi/10.1515/bejte-2013-0071/asset/graphic/bejte-2013-0071_eq89.png)
For EAS, and
from eq. [52]. It follows that
. Therefore,
is a stationary point. The EAS equilibrium is stable, because
for all t.
Consider next full segregation allocations. For these and
. By inserting this and the expression for
into eq. [51], it followsthat
. Therefore,
is a stationary point. Under full segregations
. Plugging this into eq. [56] shows that
for all t. It follows that the full segregation equilibria are stable.
Next consider partial overlap allocations. By eqs [32] and [33], . Inserting eq. [29] and the expression for
into eq. [51], it follows that
. Therefore,
is a stationary point. By eq. [24],
, while by eq. [25],
. Plugging these expressions into eq. [56] shows that
. It follows that

Thus,

if and only if .
This implies that UPO allocations are stable for . Under CPO, on the other hand,
only South-West of the CPO/CFO boundary given by eq. [42]. Therefore, CPO allocations are stable for

Finally, in SU equilibria, the peer effect at university B, , is zero. Therefore,
does not depend on
or the mean type in academia,
. Also, by Assumption 2 the rank at B of any researcher who moves to the empty university B is zero. Therefore, any researcher in university A or the outside sector will prefer their location to university B.
Proof of base salary comparative statics:
(i) That is decreasing in
for CFS and CPO equilibria followsfromtaking the total derivative in eqs [21] and [40] and solving for
. In CFS,
. In CPO,
because
. That
is decreasing in
for CFO follows from taking the total derivative of eq. [45] and finding
.
Totally differentiating eq. [48] gives
.
(iv)In CFS,
, and it follows that
since
.
In CPO, . Taking the derivative gives that
, which is negative since
.
The result for CPO and CFS follows from (iv). For CFO, the quality difference is zero and does not change with
. In the unconstrained equilibria, the academic sector is unaffected by changes in the outside option, and in particular the universities’ qualities do not depend on
.
Proof of salary progression comparative statics:
Following the proof of the base salary comparative statics,
in CFS and CPO since
.
The result for CPO and CFS follows from (iii). For CFO, the quality difference is zero and does not change with
. In the unconstrained equilibria, the academic sector is unaffected by changes in the outside option, and in particular the universities’ qualities do not depend on
.
References
Besley, T., and M.Ghatak. 2005. “Competition and Incentives with Motivated Agents.” American Economic Review95:616–36.10.1257/0002828054201413Suche in Google Scholar
Carayol, N.2008. “An Economic Theory of Academic Competition: Dynamic Incentives and Endogenous Cumulative Advantages.” Conferences on New Political Economy25:179–203.10.1628/186183408785112340Suche in Google Scholar
Carmichael, L.1988. “Incentives in Academics: Why Is There Tenure?” Journal of Political Economy96:453–72.10.1086/261547Suche in Google Scholar
Cawley, J.2009. “A Guide (and Advice) for Economists on the U. S. Junior Academic Job Market.” Working paper, Cornell University.Suche in Google Scholar
Chade, H., G.Lewis, and L.Smith. 2013. Student Portfolios and the College Admissions Problem. Working paper, SSRN.Suche in Google Scholar
Damiano, E., H.Li, and W.Suen. 2010. “First in Village or Second in Rome?” International Economic Review51:263–88.10.1111/j.1468-2354.2009.00579.xSuche in Google Scholar
Damiano, E., H.Li, and W.Suen. 2012. “Competing for Talents.” Journal of Economic Theory147:2190–219.10.1016/j.jet.2012.09.002Suche in Google Scholar
Del Rey, E.2001. “Teaching Versus Research: A Model of State University Competition.” Journal of Urban Economics49:356–73.10.1006/juec.2000.2193Suche in Google Scholar
Epple, D., and R. E.Romano. 1998. “Competition between Private and Public Schools, Vouchers, and Peer-Group Effects.” American Economic Review88:33–62.Suche in Google Scholar
Epple, D., R. E.Romano, and H.Sieg. 2006. “Admission, Tuition, and Financial Aid Policies in the Market for Higher Education.” Econometrica74:885–928.10.1111/j.1468-0262.2006.00690.xSuche in Google Scholar
Gale, D., and L. S.Shapley. 1962. “College Admissions and the Stability of Marriage.” American Mathematical Monthly69:9–15.10.1080/00029890.1962.11989827Suche in Google Scholar
Hansmann, H.1986. “A Theory of Status Organizations.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization2:119–30.Suche in Google Scholar
Hartwick, J. M., and Y.Kanemoto. 1984. Formation of Convoys, Tennis Ladders, Colleges and Related Groups. Economics Department Discussion Paper 589, Queen’s University.Suche in Google Scholar
Lach, S., and M.Schankerman. 2009. “Incentives and Invention in Universities.” RAND Journal of Economics39:403–33.10.1111/j.0741-6261.2008.00020.xSuche in Google Scholar
Lazear, E. P.1997. “Incentives in Basic Research.” Journal of Labor Economics15:S167–97.10.1086/209860Suche in Google Scholar
Lazear, E. P.2001. “Educational Production.” Quarterly Journal of Economics116:777–803.10.1162/00335530152466232Suche in Google Scholar
Ortmann, A., and R.Squire. 2000. “A Game-Theoretic Explanation of the Administrative Latticein Institutions of Higher Learning.” Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization43:377–91.10.1016/S0167-2681(00)00121-9Suche in Google Scholar
Postlewaite, A.1998. “The Social Basis of Interdependent Preferences.” European Economic Review42:779–800.10.1016/S0014-2921(97)00144-XSuche in Google Scholar
Prüfer, J., and U.Walz. 2011. “Academic Faculty Governance and Recruitment Decisions.” Public Choice153:507–29.10.2139/ssrn.1419911Suche in Google Scholar
Sacerdote, B.2001. “Peer Effects with Random Assignment: Results for Dartmouth Roommates.” Quarterly Journal of Economics116:681–704.10.1162/00335530151144131Suche in Google Scholar
Sarpca, S.2010. “Multidimensional Skills, Specialization, and Oligopolistic Competition in Higher Education.” Journal of Public Economics94:800–11.10.1016/j.jpubeco.2010.06.012Suche in Google Scholar
Stokey, N. L., and R. E.Lucas. 1989. Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.10.2307/j.ctvjnrt76Suche in Google Scholar
- 1
These comparisons between fields assume that the concern for ranking is equivalent across fields.
- 2
In a broader interpretation of the model, ranking can be interpreted as a proxy for job security in general, or, with the country club interpretation, higher ranked patrons may enjoy special benefits if the country club recognizes the positive externality they generate.
- 3
Note that constant salary is a special case.
- 4
Constant salary is again a special case.
- 5
We thank a referee for the suggestion to include condition (ii) in the sorting equilibrium definition.
- 6
We thank a referee for suggesting the connection between heterogeneity in
and the overlap between the academic and outside sectors.
- 7
When the weight researchers assign to pecuniary compensation relative to peer effect is homogenous, then researchers only differ in their ability, so we, henceforth, use the term “type” to refer to ability type.
- 8
Because the relative size of the universities is undetermined in CFO equilibria, there is a set of parameter values for which the size of university B in the CFO equilibrium may in fact be zero, in which case the equilibrium is CSU. This indeterminacy does not affect welfare.
- 9
When
exceeds a threshold, at least one university may be inactive for all values of
.
- 10
We have written the difference in salary progression as that for the academic sector minus that for the outside sector (opposite to how we wrote the difference in base salary) in order for it to be positive and for “decreasing” meaning decreasing in absolute value. A decrease, thus, implies a better outside option.
- 11
Figure 6 illustrates the sorting equilibrium for the case of university A having a greater demand for researchers than university B. Figure 7 illustrates this for the case of university B having a greater demand for researchers than university A and is presented in Appendix B.
©2013 by Walter de Gruyter Berlin / Boston
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Masthead
- Masthead
- Advances
- Dependence and Uniqueness in Bayesian Games
- Monopolistic Signal Provision†
- Multi-task Research and Research Joint Ventures
- Transparent Restrictions on Beliefs and Forward-Induction Reasoning in Games with Asymmetric Information
- A Simple Bargaining Procedure for the Myerson Value
- On the Difference between Social and Private Goods
- Optimal Use of Rewards as Commitment Device When Bidding Is Costly
- Labor Market and Search through Personal Contacts
- Contributions
- Learning, Words and Actions: Experimental Evidence on Coordination-Improving Information
- Are Trust and Reciprocity Related within Individuals?
- Optimal Contracting Model in a Social Environment and Trust-Related Psychological Costs
- Contract Bargaining with a Risk-Averse Agent
- Academia or the Private Sector? Sorting of Agents into Institutions and an Outside Sector
- Topics
- Poverty Orderings with Asymmetric Attributes
- Dictatorial Mechanisms in Constrained Combinatorial Auctions
- When Should a Monopolist Improve Quality in a Network Industry?
- On Partially Honest Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies with Restricted Domains: A Sufficient Condition
- Revenue Comparison in Asymmetric Auctions with Discrete Valuations
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Masthead
- Masthead
- Advances
- Dependence and Uniqueness in Bayesian Games
- Monopolistic Signal Provision†
- Multi-task Research and Research Joint Ventures
- Transparent Restrictions on Beliefs and Forward-Induction Reasoning in Games with Asymmetric Information
- A Simple Bargaining Procedure for the Myerson Value
- On the Difference between Social and Private Goods
- Optimal Use of Rewards as Commitment Device When Bidding Is Costly
- Labor Market and Search through Personal Contacts
- Contributions
- Learning, Words and Actions: Experimental Evidence on Coordination-Improving Information
- Are Trust and Reciprocity Related within Individuals?
- Optimal Contracting Model in a Social Environment and Trust-Related Psychological Costs
- Contract Bargaining with a Risk-Averse Agent
- Academia or the Private Sector? Sorting of Agents into Institutions and an Outside Sector
- Topics
- Poverty Orderings with Asymmetric Attributes
- Dictatorial Mechanisms in Constrained Combinatorial Auctions
- When Should a Monopolist Improve Quality in a Network Industry?
- On Partially Honest Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies with Restricted Domains: A Sufficient Condition
- Revenue Comparison in Asymmetric Auctions with Discrete Valuations