Startseite Primate origins of discourse-managing gestures: the case of hand fling
Artikel Open Access

Primate origins of discourse-managing gestures: the case of hand fling

  • Pritty Patel-Grosz ORCID logo EMAIL logo , Matthew Henderson ORCID logo , Patrick Georg Grosz ORCID logo , Kirsty Graham ORCID logo und Catherine Hobaiter ORCID logo
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 3. Januar 2023

Abstract

The last decades have seen major advances in the study of gestures both in humans and non-human primates. In this paper, we seriously examine the idea that there may be gestural form types that are shared across great ape species, including humans, which may underlie gestural universals, both in form and meaning. We focus on one case study, the hand fling gesture common to chimpanzees and humans, and provide a semantic analysis of this gesture.

1 Introduction

One of the perennial questions in linguistic description and analysis is whether there are universals of an explanatory sort. This question has recently gained new prominence in research on human gestures, as discussed in Cooperrider et al. (2018) and Cooperrider (2019). Relatedly, research on gestures in non-human primates has focused on the question of whether there are gestural form types or even gestural meanings that are shared across great ape species (Graham et al. 2018; Kersken et al. 2019). Finally, when it comes to the issue of meaning more broadly, as studied in natural language semantics, the question of abstract semantic universals that may be shared by all humans has been raised repeatedly, as in May (1991: 353), Partee (1992: 124–125) and von Fintel and Matthewson (2008). We propose a combined approach, which investigates universals in human gestures, great ape gestures, and semantics.

We build on the recent work on great ape gestures in Byrne et al. (2017) and Byrne and Cochet (2017), among others (e.g. Hewes 1973), who use comparative evidence across ape species. For instance, non-human great apes (chimpanzees [Pan troglodytes], bonobos [Pan paniscus], gorillas [Gorilla], and orangutans [Pongo]) appear to share more gestural form types (e.g., Arm Raise, Reach Palm, etc.) than would be expected by chance, suggesting a shared origin of gesture in apes. Qualities of this inherited system may have facilitated the emergence of language. Moreover, Graham et al. (2018) show that chimpanzees and bonobos also share the meanings of their gestures at a level above chance, indicating that such meanings may either be innate as well, or may arise across species based on shared cognitive needs and capacities.[1] Humans share common ancestors with non-human great apes, and are in fact a closer relative to chimpanzees and bonobos than the gorillas and other great apes with whom chimpanzees share a large proportion of their repertoire (Byrne et al. 2017). As a result, these findings give rise to the expectation that the form types and meanings of shared great ape gestures are also present (and potentially innate) in humans. Kersken et al. (2019) demonstrate that the gestural form types shared by non-human apes are also found in the spontaneous gestures of 1-to-2 year old human toddlers. These findings give rise to the following two questions: Are the shared gestural form types also found in adults? If so, what are their meanings, and do they overlap with the meanings found in non-human great apes? We experimentally investigated these questions in Henderson et al. (2022). Henderson et al. (2022) is an experimental study that tests the extent to which core aspects of ape gesture meanings are retained and recognised when they are reproduced in human interactions. It did so by allowing participants to watch videos of these gestures reproduced in a naturalistic human interaction, and then select from among four potential meanings. However, Henderson et al. (2022) does not explore the linguistic implications at length; the purpose of this article is to go beyond Henderson et al. (2022), taking matters one step further. We lay out a conceptual framework for linking shared ape gestures to discourse-managing meanings in humans, proposing a concrete formalization of how gestures follow a complete transition from the communication of non-human primates, via correspondingly concrete gestures of humans, to the abstract discourse-managing gestures of humans. To do so, we proceed as follows.

We focus on the hand fling form type; hand fling is shared between humans and all of the non-human great ape species (chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas, and orangutans), and may thus be a candidate for a gestural universal. In terms of its meaning, humans attribute the same physical “Move away” interpretation to this hand fling gesture that is present in other great apes, but also a more abstract discourse-managing meaning along the lines of “Forget it”. We briefly summarize the findings of Henderson et al. (2022) in Section 2, and then analyse a naturalistic use of hand fling as a discourse-managing gesture in Section 3. We argue that both interpretations share an abstract core meaning (Section 4); this overlap may derive from a shared abstract semantic building block, which in turn is a candidate for an abstract semantic universal in humans (Section 5), since gestures predate language even within the human lineage (see, e.g., McNeill 2012).

This paper systematically builds on the extensive literature on how abstract gestures are based in gestures with concrete meanings (e.g., Abner et al. 2015; Bavelas et al. 1992; Bressem and Müller 2017; McNeill 1992; Müller 2004), and on the rapidly growing literature on great ape gestures (e.g., Byrne et al. 2017; Graham et al. 2018; Kersken et al. 2019). Owing to both research traditions, it aims to make a contribution to both of them and to the connection between them, by adding formal semantic methodology with a focus on the form-meaning pairings associated with the hand fling gesture. Formal semantic approaches to animal communication constitute a new field of research (see, e.g., Schlenker et al. 2016), and this paper aims to expand the scope of this field to the comparison of great ape gestures and human gestures.

2 From chimpanzees to humans

In their research on chimpanzee gestures, Hobaiter and Byrne (2011: 749) define gesture as “discrete, mechanically ineffective physical movements of the body observed during periods of intentional communication” (compare, e.g., Kendon 2004: 7, Abner et al. 2015: 437–439, among many others, for definitions of gesture in humans). There is a general question of how to determine the meaning of a given gesture, both in humans and in other species; a human who gestures will often be hard-pressed to describe the meaning of a gesture in words (see, for example, the abstract gestural meanings in Bressem and Müller 2017, which amount to different types of ‘negative assessment’). This issue is amplified in the study of non-human primates, since human researchers cannot access intuitions about gestural meanings – they can only observe in which contexts the gestures seem to be appropriate. In their study of wild chimpanzees, Hobaiter and Byrne (2014) catalogue 39 uses of a hand fling gesture observed in five individuals, for which they assign the primary meaning “Move away” (73% of observations) and a secondary meaning “Stop that” (27% of observations).[2] These researchers defined meaning here using a gesture’s apparently satisfactory outcome, which is established as follows. In non-human apes, we observe that a gestural signaller (defined as the individual gesturing) produces, and may repeat, a gesture until the recipient (for whom the gesture is intended) responds in a way that appears to satisfy the signaller. The behaviour that made the signaller stop gesturing is classified as the gesture’s apparently satisfactory outcome (Cartmill and Byrne 2007; Genty et al. 2009).

The hand(s) fling form is defined as a “Rapid movement of hand(s) or arm(s) from the signaller towards the recipient” in Byrne et al. (2017: 759), while the “Move away” meaning is defined as a prompt for the recipient to move away from the signaller (Hobaiter and Byrne 2014: 1598). Hand fling is present in all non-human great ape species (chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas, and orangutans).[3] Building on Kersken et al.’s (2019) finding that humans and other great apes overlap extensively in their gestural repertoire, our first question is whether the same hand fling can also be used as a human gesture with comparable meaning. Since the “Move away” meaning is strongly associated with hand fling in chimpanzees, we ask if humans make the same connection, i.e. would a human onlooker also associate a hand fling gesture performed by another human with a “Move away” meaning. (While a “Stop that” meaning has also been attested for hand fling, the fact that “Move away” is attested in more than 70% of occurrences is taken to indicate that hand fling is a ‘tight’ gesture strongly associated with the “Move away” meaning, Hobaiter and Byrne 2014: 1597.) Notably, since the gestures of non-human great apes are much more constrained in creativity than the gestures of humans, the optimal test scenario is one in which a human signaller performs the chimpanzee gesture as if it were a human gesture.

Figure 1 is an illustration from a study presented in Henderson et al. (2022), that aimed to do this very thing; here, chimpanzee specialist Dr Catherine Hobaiter is depicted performing a hand fling gesture that adheres to its definition in chimpanzees but is performed as if it were a human gesture. Hobaiter aimed to reproduce ape-typical components of the gesture, e.g., the finger flexion and wrist position typical for chimpanzee hands, to ensure the gesture is faithful to what is found in chimpanzees, rather than anthropomorphised, to maximise similarity. Note that while human and chimpanzee vocal anatomy is markedly different (Nishimura et al. 2022), the physiology of human and chimpanzees in the limbs required for gesture production is not. So while the authentic reproduction of vocal signals would not be possible across species, it is possible to recreate ape gesture actions. By reproducing the chimpanzee hand fling gesture as if it were a human gesture, it is possible to test whether human onlookers draw the same meaning inference that is found in chimpanzees, namely a prompt for the recipient to “Move away”. This was indeed confirmed by our first experimental study (reported in Henderson et al. 2022), where 77% of 300 study participants chose “Move away” as the meaning of hand fling in a forced-choice task with four answer options. For the purposes of our study of human gestures that are isomorphic to chimpanzee gestures, this finding suggests that adult humans draw similar inferences from seeing such a gesture as is found in chimpanzees.

Figure 1: 
Three stills to illustrate the hand fling gesture.
Figure 1:

Three stills to illustrate the hand fling gesture.

Naturally, the source of the “Move away” inference is unclear, i.e., whether the form-meaning association is innate, or simply acquired systematically due to shared cognitive mechanisms, which may also involve iconicity in the form of resemblance between the gesture and an actual activity of shooing away a person or animal. Either way, we expect the form-meaning association to be a candidate for a gestural universal – though possibly at an abstract level, which we discuss in Section 5. Moreover, the question of whether iconicity plays a role in the gestural form-meaning association is independent from Kersken et al.’s (2019) finding that the form of the hand fling gesture is found in 1-to-2 year old human infants; these infants will plausibly not have access to the same iconic resources as human adults.

In a next step, we observe the following: while gestures of the type in Figure 1 appear to be used exclusively to communicate about the external physical world by non-human great apes (i.e., “Remove yourself physically”), humans may assign additional meanings to such a gesture in addition to that physical meaning. We propose that an abstract discursive counterpart of “Remove yourself” may amount to “Remove the undesirable information that you have proffered”, or more casually, “Forget it”, or even “Nah”. In a second experimental study, we used the same forced-choice design with four answer options, but tested abstract discourse-managing meanings instead of the concrete chimpanzee meanings; we found that human participants can indeed infer a “Forget it” meaning from the same gesture in Figure 1. (“Forget it” was chosen by 95% of 300 study participants.)

While bearing in mind that Figure 1 is the controlled recreation of a chimpanzee gesture by a human signaller (rather than a spontaneous gesture performed as part of a realistic conversation), an inspection of the literature on gestures in humans reveals similarities to the ‘brushing away’ and ‘holding away’ gestures that Bressem and Müller (2014, 2017 discuss as part of their family of Away gestures (building on Kendon 2004: 248–264, Calbris 2011; see also Harrison 2010); they describe ‘brushing away’ as a gesture that resembles “Rapidly brushing away small, annoying objects” while ‘holding away’ resembles “Holding or pushing away an object” (Bressem and Müller 2017: 3). This is an important connection, as it substantiates the intuition that hand fling constitutes a universal gesture type in that such Away gestures have been found in a range of different languages and cultures. Note that in chimpanzees, the flinging motion of hand fling, an outward hand movement away from the body, is more important to the gesture’s definition than the final position of the hand; Bressem and Müller (2014: 1596) discuss such a movement, which they take to define their family of Away gestures, and connect it to “rejection, refusal, negative assessment, and negation”.

We will now outline the discourse-managing potential of hand fling in Section 3, and then return to a potential abstract core meaning in Section 4. At this point, it is worth noting that there seems to be cross-cultural variation in the perception of hand fling; native speakers of British, Canadian and American English report that hand fling as a discourse-managing gesture is quite rude, whereas native speakers of German find the gesture quite natural without a similar sense of rudeness; our discussion glosses over such differences.

3 Charting the discourse effects of hand fling

If we start by turning to the established formal semantics literature on discourse management, one concept that connects to the “Forget it” meaning of a hand fling gesture is the notion of common ground management in Krifka (2008: 246) (see also Repp 2013; Krifka 2017). The core idea is that we not only communicate to establish shared knowledge about a world/situation (see, e.g., Karttunen 1974; Lewis 1979; Stalnaker 1974), but we also communicate about how the discourse situation between us should evolve. To apply this notion to our hand fling gesture in its discourse-managing “Forget it” use, hand fling may communicate the signaller’s attitude on how a piece of information φ that has already been proffered by the recipient should be handled: φ should be rejected rather than being added to the common ground. This is in line with a treatment of hand fling as similar to Bressem and Müller’s (2014, 2017 ‘holding away’ gestures, which are characterized as “refusing and rejecting” information. Note that this discourse-managing information itself will, of course, be added to the common ground, e.g., in the shape of the proposition the signaller wants the recipient to withdraw the information that the recipient had proffered.

The hand fling with a “Forget it” meaning thus has a similar discursive effect to the expression of denial of a salient proposition (see, e.g., Repp 2013; van der Sandt 1991), thus preventing the targeted proposition φ from being added to the common ground. We can embed this in a discourse model as given in (1), using a notation from Repp (2013) for the sake of concreteness. (Compare Farkas and Bruce’s 2010 Table for a discourse model that would also permit a formal rendering of the contribution that hand fling makes to a discourse situation; see also Romero and Han 2004 for related research.) Example (1) incorporates the idea that a proposition (and thus a piece of information) φ is introduced as part of the statement in (1-i), the removal of which the signaller prompts in (1-ii). Compare Bressem et al.’s (2017: 176) description of the ‘holding away’ gestures as a means to “reject topics of talk, to stop arguments, beliefs, or ideas from intruding into the realm of shared conversation”.

(1)
Discourse conditions for utterance un containing HAND-FLING:
(i) a preceding utterance un-1 of the recipientc has communicated that the proposition φ should be added to the common ground
(ii) the signallerc (who utters un) prompts the recipientc to remove φ from the discourse between the recipientc and signallerc

We can now illustrate hand fling at work in a concrete example, (2)/(3) (inspired by a naturalistic example found in The Fifth Child [1988] by Doris Lessing [p. 40], and its official German translation by Eva Schönfeld). Here, hand fling occurs as a speech-accompanying gesture, rather than as a stand-alone gesture. We propose the following analysis: Robin’s utterance in (2a) triggers an inference (presumably at the level of conversational implicature) to φ = we cannot manage. Alex’s use of the hand fling gesture targets that inference (hand fling anaphorically takes φ as its propositional argument) and thereby rejects φ, in line with (1-ii). This strengthens Alex’s own assertion of p = we can manage.

(2)
a. Robin: Our visitors are arriving tomorrow and the house is a mess!
b. Alex: We can manage HAND-FLING

Such an analysis of (2) is corroborated by analogous facts from German. Consider the German translation in (3). In German, it is natural to add the discourse particle schon (see e.g. Egg 2012; Zimmermann 2018).

(3)
a.
Robin: Our visitors are arriving tomorrow and the house is a mess!
b.
Alex: Das schaffen wir schon HAND-FLING
that manage we PRT
‘We will [schon] manage that.’

Egg (2012: 298) discusses an example similar to (3) (though not containing a gesture) and argues for an analysis that can be rendered as in (4): Robin’s utterance in (3a) communicates (simplified) q = the house is a mess, (4b). In (3b), Alex asserts the proposition p = we will manage, (4c), and adds the particle schon, which contributes the meaning inference in (4a), as applied to (4b–c) in (4d). (See Grosz 2021 for recent discussion of whether the non-at-issue contribution of German discourse particles, [4a]/[4d] is best modelled as a presupposition or designated use-conditional meaning.) Importantly, Alex’s retort to Robin’s statement serves to cancel a defeasible entailment (i.e. an entailment that arises in ‘normal’ circumstances), and schon (with the semantics in [4a]) highlights this cancellation, as spelled out in (4d). It is this defeasibly entailed proposition (φ = ¬p) that hand fling targets in (2b) and (3b).

(4)
a.
schon⟧(p)(q) ⤳ both p and q hold, and, according to the common ground, q
defeasibly entails ¬p (simplified from Egg 2012: 312)
b.
q = the house is a mess (asserted by Robin)
c.
p = we will manage (asserted by Alex)
d.
schon⟧(p)(q) the house is a mess (q) defeasibly entails we can not manage (¬p),
but both p (we will manage) and q (the house is a mess) hold;
therefore, the defeasible entailment (q>¬p) is cancelled.

It is worth noting that the hand fling gesture and the particle schon seem to reinforce one another in (3), as both of them serve to reject the salient inference φ = ¬p = we cannot manage. This behaviour is expected, given that both contributions may qualify as use-conditional in nature (Gutzmann 2013: 10–14), and it is a hallmark property of use-conditional meanings that they can be reinforced by repetition (cf. Potts’ 2007: 182–183 repeatability property of expressive content).[4] Having seen examples of the hand fling in its discourse-managing “Forget it” reading, (2b) and (3b), we now return to the question of how this may relate to the great ape meaning “Move away”, in Section 4.

4 Spelling out a semantic core of hand fling

The gestures of non-human great apes that have been described in the literature as of now (as in Hobaiter and Byrne 2014) are universally directive in the spirit of Searle (1975: 355), i.e., communicative acts by which the signaller prompts the recipient to perform some action or other. We can thus apply an established formalism for imperatives in human language to flesh out the meaning of hand fling in its “Move away” reading; for concreteness’ sake, we use Portner’s (2007: 358) formalism in (5). (See Kaufmann 2012, among many others, for alternative approaches to imperatives.) For a reader unfamiliar with formal semantic notation, (5) expresses that the meaning of hand fling in its “Move away” reading corresponds to the description of a property that holds of an individual x (by virtue of the lambda notation, λx). Specifically, this is a property of x removing physical closeness from x and the signaller in the context c in a situation w (as encoded in the text that follows the full stop in the second line of [5]). The part between colon and full stop (‘x = recipientc’) is a presupposition that is only met if the denoted property holds of the recipient in context c; this encodes the recipient-orientation of directives (such as imperatives). In Portner’s system, a directive of the type in (5) is communicated by a signaller with the intention to add the denoted property to the recipient’s To-Do List, a contextually given set of properties which the recipient is committed to realize of themselves. In the concrete case at hand, (5) amounts to a prompt for reducing physical closeness between the recipient and the signaller, thus increasing distance between them. (Bold type is added to facilitate comparison between [5] and [6].)

(5)
hand fling Move-awayc,g,w
= [λx : x = recipientc . x removes physical closeness from x and signallerc in w]

At first encounter, (5) may seem like a round-about way of expressing “Move away”, but our aim is to see how this meaning could be mapped transparently onto a discourse-managing meaning such as “Forget it”. This mapping can be done by switching physical closeness with information, as shown in (6). The change from manipulating something physical in (5) to abstract information in (6) is reminiscent of the conduit metaphor that was applied to human gestures by McNeill (1992), based on Reddy (1979), which argues that the gestural manipulation of virtual objects can be transferred to an analogous manipulation of abstract information (see also Müller 2004; Abner et al. 2015: 439; Bressem and Müller 2017: 2–3 and Cooperrider et al. 2018: 14).

(6)
hand fling Forget-itc,g,w
= [λx : x = recipientc . x removes information from x and signallerc in w]

We can make the parallels between (5) and (6) even more explicit by abstracting over the theme argument and specifying its ontological type (physical closeness vs. information) in the denotation of the gesture. Such a restatement of (5) and (6) is given in (7) and (8), respectively; here, the gesture combines with a variable i, which amounts to a contextually salient object that either classifies as physical closeness (7), or as a piece of information (8). In the formal semantics, the value of i (i.e., the contextually salient object for which it stands in) is provided by a contextual assignment function g, in line with standard procedure.[5]

(7)
hand fling Move-away ic,g,w
= [λx : x = recipientcphysical-closeness(g(i)) . x removes g(i) from x and signallerc in w]
(8)
hand fling Forget-it ic,g,w
= [λx : x = recipientcinformation(g(i)) . x removes g(i) from x and signallerc in w]

With regards to the universals debate as outlined in Section 1, we can now reason as follows: First, we proposed that humans may share a set of universal gestures with chimpanzees (and other great apes); this has previously been shown for 1- to 2-year old human infants by Kersken et al. (2019); our experiments in Henderson et al. (2022) extend this inquiry to adult humans. Second, we have argued that abstract discourse-managing gesture meanings, in (6)/(8), are transparently derived from physical gesture meanings that communicate about the external world, given in (5)/(7), based on a shared semantic core meaning (here: x removes g(i) from x and signaller c ). As a consequence, the mapping from shared great ape gestures to corresponding discourse-managing meanings should arise independently across different cultures, which would provide a new piece to solving the puzzle of where gestural universals come from (Cooperrider et al. 2018; Cooperrider 2019).

5 Broader consequences

On a big picture level, we propose that the meanings of shared great ape gestures may more broadly constitute primary building blocks of gestural meaning in humans. While these building blocks may be understood in a physical sense (“Remove yourself”, “Move away”), we proposed in Section 4 that they can ‘trickle down’ into the discourse-managing gestures of adult humans by virtue of a semi-predictable mapping (where “Remove yourself” becomes “Remove the undesirable information that you have proffered”, i.e., “Forget it”). If supported, this hypothesis would allow us to identify the origin of a subset of discourse-managing human gestures in shared great ape gestures. Returning to Hobaiter and Byrne (2014) with this goal in mind, Table 1 illustrates attested ape meanings (quoted from Hobaiter and Byrne’s 2014 supplemental materials).

Table 1:

Excerpt of chimpanzee meanings from Hobaiter and Byrne (2014).

Meaning Definition
“Acquire object” recipient gives signaller object (e.g. food, leaf sponge, etc.)
“Attend to specific location” recipient adjusts their behaviour to focus attention on the location indicated in the signaller’s gestural communication, usually in grooming
“Move away” recipient moves away from signaller
“Move closer” recipient moves closer to signaller
“Stop that” the recipient either ceases behaviour previously directed towards the signaller or changes their behaviour to direct it towards another individual

If we take the meanings in Table 1 to form the basis of universal meanings in humans, we observe that some of them are negative/discouraging (such as the meaning “Move away”, which is associated with the hand fling gesture), while others are positive/encouraging (such as the meaning “Move closer”). Such notions of discouragement and encouragement may thus form the basis of universal gestural meanings. In the first instance, the universal meanings shared between humans and great apes will be physical; subsequently, discourse-managing uses will derive from some of these physical gesture uses (though not necessarily all of them).

To put this conjecture to the test, we can look at the beckon gesture (Hobaiter and Byrne 2014: 1598), which in chimpanzees is strongly associated with a “Move closer” meaning. In the same way in which “Move away” may map to rejection of information, we would expect that “Move closer” maps to acceptance/solicitation of information. In the second experimental study discussed in Section 2, we also presented human participants with a forced-choice task involving four answer options for possible meanings of the beckon gesture as performed in Figure 2. The majority of participants chose the answer option “Tell me more” (47%) or “Tell me about it” (35%),[6] with only 18% of participants choosing one of the two distractors, thus offering support for the suggestion that beckon may qualify as a positive counterpart of hand fling in discourse management as well.

Figure 2: 
Three video stills to illustrate the beckon gesture.
Figure 2:

Three video stills to illustrate the beckon gesture.

6 Summary and conclusion

In this paper, we examined the idea that humans may share certain gestures with other great apes, such as chimpanzees, including the gestural form hand fling with an abstract gestural meaning that amounts to “Move away” (Section 2). As humans are not restricted to communicating about the physical external world, we proposed that the abstract gestural meaning of hand fling can be mapped onto the management of information in the discourse, by virtue of a simple change in the meaning of the gesture (Section 4). As proof of concept, we fleshed out a concrete application of this analysis to discourse situations in humans (Section 3). We concluded with a brief exploration of the broader consequences (Section 5). The central hypothesis generated in this paper amounts to the idea that parts of the meanings of shared great ape gestures (such as “Move away”) may be contained in those of the discourse-managing gestures of adult humans (such as “Forget it”); we consider this hypothesis to form the basis for future hypothesis testing in line with Henderson et al. (2022).


Corresponding author: Pritty Patel-Grosz, Super Linguistics Research Group, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway, E-mail:

Award Identifier / Grant number: 802719

Funding source: Universitetet i Oslo

Award Identifier / Grant number: Career development grant

Acknowledgments

The authors are very grateful for useful feedback and input from Philippe Schlenker, the audiences at the LINGUAE seminar (Institut Jean Nicod, École Normale Supérieure), the Linguistics Circle at the University of Edinburgh, and the LALP Lab seminar at NTNU. This research was partially supported by funding from the Faculty of Humanities career development grant at the University of Oslo [PI: Patel-Grosz]; Matthew Henderson, Kirsty Graham and Catherine Hobaiter received research funding from the European Union’s 8th Framework Programme, Horizon 2020, under grant agreement no 802719 [PI: Hobaiter].

References

Abner, Natasha, Kensy Cooperrider & Susan Goldin-Meadow. 2015. Gesture for linguists: A handy primer. Language and Linguistics Compass 9. 437–449. https://doi.org/10.1111/lnc3.12168.Suche in Google Scholar

Asher, Nicholas. 2011. Lexical meaning in context: A web of words. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511793936Suche in Google Scholar

Bavelas, Janet B., Nicole Chovil, Douglas A. Lawrie & Allan Wade. 1992. Interactive gestures. Discourse Processes 15. 469–489. https://doi.org/10.1080/01638539209544823.Suche in Google Scholar

Bressem, Jana & Cornelia Müller. 2014. The family of Away gestures: Negation, refusal, and negative assessment. In Cornelia Müller, Alan Cienki, Ellen Fricke, Silva H. Ladewig, David McNeill & Bressem Jana (eds.), Body – Language – Communication. An international handbook on multimodality in human interaction (HSK 38.2), 1592–1604. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.10.1515/9783110302028.1592Suche in Google Scholar

Bressem, Jana & Cornelia Müller. 2017. The “Negative-Assessment-Construction” – a multimodal pattern based on a recurrent gesture? Linguistic Vanguard 3. 20160053. https://doi.org/10.1515/lingvan-2016-0053.Suche in Google Scholar

Bressem, Jana, Nicole Stein & Claudia Wegener. 2017. Multimodal language use in Savosavo. Refusing, excluding and negating with speech and gesture. Pragmatics 27. 173–206. https://doi.org/10.1075/prag.27.2.01bre.Suche in Google Scholar

Byrne, Richard W., Erica Cartmill, Emilie Genty, Kirsty E. Graham, Catherine Hobaiter & Joanne E. Tanner. 2017. Great ape gestures. Simple intentional communication with a rich set of innate signals. Animal Cognition 20. 755–769. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-017-1096-4.Suche in Google Scholar

Byrne, Richard W. & Hélène Cochet. 2017. Where have all the (ape) gestures gone? Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 24. 68–71. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-016-1071-0.Suche in Google Scholar

Calbris, Geneviève. 2011. Elements of meaning in gesture. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/gs.5Suche in Google Scholar

Cartmill, Erica A. & Richard W. Byrne. 2007. Orangutans modify their gestural signaling according to their audience’s comprehension. Current Biology 17. 1345–1348. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2007.06.069.Suche in Google Scholar

Cooperrider, Kensy, Natasha Abner & Susan Goldin-Meadow. 2018. The palm-up puzzle: Meanings and origins of a widespread form in gesture and sign. Frontiers in Communication 3. 23. https://doi.org/10.3389/fcomm.2018.00023.Suche in Google Scholar

Cooperrider, Kensy. 2019. Universals and diversity in gesture. Research past, present, and future. Gesture 18. 209–238. https://doi.org/10.1075/gest.19011.coo.10.1075/gest.19011.cooSuche in Google Scholar

Egg, Markus. 2012. Discourse particles at the semantics-pragmatics interface. In Werner Abraham & Elisabeth Leiss (eds.), Modality and theory of mind elements across languages, 297–333. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110271072.297Suche in Google Scholar

Farkas, Donka & Kim Bruce. 2010. On reacting to assertions and polar questions. Journal of Semantics 27. 81–118. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffp010.Suche in Google Scholar

von Fintel, Kai & Lisa Matthewson. 2008. Universals in semantics. The Linguistic Review 25. 139–201. https://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.2008.004.Suche in Google Scholar

Genty, Emilie & Klaus Zuberbühler. 2015. Iconic gesturing in bonobos. Communicative & Integrative Biology 8. e992742. https://doi.org/10.4161%2F19420889.2014.992742.10.4161/19420889.2014.992742Suche in Google Scholar

Genty, Emilie, Thomas Breuer, Catherine Hobaiter & Richard W. Byrne. 2009. Gestural communication of the gorilla (Gorilla gorilla): Repertoire, intentionality and possible origins. Animal Cognition 12. 527–546. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-009-0213-4.Suche in Google Scholar

Graham, Kirsty E., Catherine Hobaiter, James Ounsley, Takeshi Furuichi & Richard W. Byrne. 2018. Bonobo and chimpanzee gestures overlap extensively in meaning. PLoS Biology 16. e2004825. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.2004825.Suche in Google Scholar

Grosz, Patrick G. 2021. Discourse particles. In Daniel Gutzmann, Lisa Matthewson, Cécile Meier, Hotze Rullmann & Thomas Ede Zimmermann (eds.), The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics. Oxford: John Wiley & Sons.Suche in Google Scholar

Gutzmann, Daniel. 2013. Expressives and beyond: An introduction to varieties of use-conditional meaning. In Daniel Gutzmann & Hans-Martin Gärtner (eds.), Beyond expressives: Explorations in use-conditional meaning, 1–58. Leiden: Brill.10.1163/9789004183988_002Suche in Google Scholar

Harrison, Simon. 2010. Evidence for node and scope of negation in coverbal gesture. Gesture 10. 29–51. https://doi.org/10.1075/gest.10.1.03har.Suche in Google Scholar

Henderson, Matthew, Patrick G. Grosz, Kirsty E. Graham, Catherine Hobaiter & Pritty Patel-Grosz. 2022. Shared semantics: Exploring the interface between human and chimpanzee gestural communication. Manuscript, University of St Andrews/University of Oslo.Suche in Google Scholar

Hewes, Gordon W. 1973. Primate communication and the gestural origin of language. Current Anthropology 14. 5–24. https://doi.org/10.1086/204019.Suche in Google Scholar

Hobaiter, Catherine & Richard W. Byrne. 2011. The gestural repertoire of the wild chimpanzee. Animal Cognition 14. 745–767. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-011-0409-2.Suche in Google Scholar

Hobaiter, Catherine & Richard W. Byrne. 2014. The meanings of chimpanzee gestures. Current Biology 24. 1596–1600. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2014.05.066.Suche in Google Scholar

Karttunen, Lauri. 1974. Presuppositions and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics 1. 181–194. https://doi.org/10.1515/thli.1974.1.1-3.181.Suche in Google Scholar

Kaufmann, Magdalena. 2012. Interpreting imperatives. Dordrecht: Springer.10.1007/978-94-007-2269-9Suche in Google Scholar

Kendon, Adam. 2004. Gesture: Visible action as utterance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511807572Suche in Google Scholar

Kersken, Verena, Juan-Carlos Gómez, Ulf Liszkowski, Adrian Soldati & Catherine Hobaiter. 2019. A gestural repertoire of 1- to 2-year-old human children: In search of the ape gestures. Animal Cognition 22. 577–595. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-018-1213-z.Suche in Google Scholar

Krifka, Manfred. 2008. Basic notions of information structure. Acta Linguistica Hungarica 55. 243–276. https://doi.org/10.1556/aling.55.2008.3-4.2.Suche in Google Scholar

Krifka, Manfred. 2017. Negated polarity questions as denegations of assertions. In Chungmin Lee, Ferenc Kiefer & Manfred Krifka (eds.), Contrastiveness in information structure, alternatives and scalar implicatures, 359–398. Dordrecht: Springer.10.1007/978-3-319-10106-4_18Suche in Google Scholar

Lewis, David. 1979. Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8. 339–359. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00258436.Suche in Google Scholar

May, Robert. 1991. Syntax, semantics, and logical form. In Asa Kasher (ed.), The Chomskyan turn, 334–359. Oxford: Blackwell.Suche in Google Scholar

McNeill, David. 1992. Hand and mind: What gestures reveal about thought. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Suche in Google Scholar

McNeill, David. 2012. How language began, gesture and speech in human evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139108669Suche in Google Scholar

Moore, Richard. 2014. Ape gestures: Interpreting chimpanzee and bonobo minds. Current Biology 24. R645–R647. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2014.05.072.Suche in Google Scholar

Müller, Cornelia. 2004. Forms and uses of the Palm up open hand: A case of a gesture family. In Cornelia Müller & Roland Posner (eds.), The semantics and pragmatics of everyday gestures, 233–256. Berlin: Weidler.Suche in Google Scholar

Nishimura, Takeshi, Isao T. Tokuda, Shigehiro Miyachi, Jacob C. Dunn, Christian T. Herbst, Kazuyoshi Ishimura, Akihisa Kaneko, Yuki Kinoshita, Hiroki Koda, Jaap P. P. Saers, Hirohiko Imai, Tetsuya Matsuda, Ole Næsbye Larsen, Uwe Jürgens, Hideki Hirabayashi, Shozo Kojima & W. Tecumseh Fitch. 2022. Evolutionary loss of complexity in human vocal anatomy as an adaptation for speech. Science 377. 760–763. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.abm1574.Suche in Google Scholar

Partee, Barbara. 1992. Syntactic categories and semantic type. In Michael Rosner & Roderick Johnson (eds.), Computational linguistics and formal semantics, 97–126. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511611803.004Suche in Google Scholar

Pika, Simone & John Mitani. 2006. Referential gestural communication in wild chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Current Biology 16. R191–R192. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2006.02.037.Suche in Google Scholar

Portner, Paul. 2007. Imperatives and modals. Natural Language Semantics 15. 351–383. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-007-9022-y.Suche in Google Scholar

Potts, Christopher. 2007. The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics 33. 165–198. https://doi.org/10.1515/TL.2007.011.Suche in Google Scholar

Reddy, Michael J. 1979. The conduit metaphor: A case of frame conflict in our language about language. In Andrew Ortony (ed.), Metaphor and thought, 164–201. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139173865.012Suche in Google Scholar

Repp, Sophie. 2013. Common ground management: Modal particles, illocutionary negation and VERUM. In Daniel Gutzmann & Hans-Martin Gärtner (eds.), Beyond expressives, 231–274. Leiden: Brill.10.1163/9789004183988_008Suche in Google Scholar

Romero, Maribel & Chung-hye Han. 2004. On negative yes/No questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 27. 609–658. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:LING.0000033850.15705.94.10.1023/B:LING.0000033850.15705.94Suche in Google Scholar

Van der Sandt, Rob. 1991. Denial. Papers from the Chicago Linguistics Society 27. 331–344.Suche in Google Scholar

Schlenker, Philippe, Emmanuel Chemla, Anne M. Schel, James Fuller, Jean-Pierre Gautier, Jeremy Kuhn, Dunja Veselinović, Kate Arnold, Cristiane Cäsar, Sumir Keenan, Alban Lemasson, Karim Ouattara, Robin Ryder & Klaus Zuberbühler. 2016. Formal monkey linguistics. Theoretical Linguistics 42. 1–90. https://doi.org/10.1515/tl-2016-0001.Suche in Google Scholar

Searle, John R. 1975. A taxonomy of illocutionary acts. In Keith Gunderson (ed.), Language, mind, and knowledge, 344–369. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Avaliable at: https://hdl.handle.net/11299/185220.Suche in Google Scholar

Stalnaker, Robert. 1974. Pragmatic presuppositions. In Milton Munitz & Peter Unger (eds.), Semantics and philosophy, 197–213. New York: New York University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Tanner, Joanne E. & Richard W. Byrne. 1996. Representation of action through iconic gesture in a captive lowland gorilla. Current Anthropology 37. 162–173. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1086/204484.10.1086/204484Suche in Google Scholar

Tramacere, Antonella & Richard Moore. 2018. Reconsidering the role of manual imitation in language evolution. Topoi 37. 319–328. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9440-x.Suche in Google Scholar

Zimmermann, Malte. 2018. Wird schon stimmen! A degree operator analysis of schon. Journal of Semantics 35. 687–739. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffy010.Suche in Google Scholar

Received: 2022-01-15
Accepted: 2022-11-07
Published Online: 2023-01-03

© 2022 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Artikel in diesem Heft

  1. Frontmatter
  2. Editorial
  3. Editorial 2023
  4. Research Articles
  5. Tapped /r/ in RP: a corpus-based sociophonetic study across the twentieth century
  6. Revisiting English written VP-ellipsis and VP-substitution: a dependency-based analysis
  7. Agreeing objects in Zulu can be indefinite and non-specific
  8. On the semantics of (negated) approximative kaada in Classical Arabic: a case for embedded exhaustification
  9. Imperatives as persuasion strategies in political discourse
  10. Primate origins of discourse-managing gestures: the case of hand fling
  11. Basic word order typology revisited: a crosslinguistic quantitative study based on UD and WALS
  12. The effect of L2 German on grammatical gender access in L1 Polish: proficiency matters
  13. Validation of two measures for assessing English vocabulary knowledge on web-based testing platforms: brief assessments
  14. Validation of two measures for assessing English vocabulary knowledge on web-based testing platforms: long-form assessments
  15. Cerebral asymmetries in the processing of opaque compounds in L1 Polish and L2 English
  16. Are preschool children sensitive to the function of accessibility markers? A visual world study with German-speaking three- to four-year-olds
  17. Sensory experience ratings (SERs) for 1,130 Chinese words: relationships with other semantic and lexical psycholinguistic variables
  18. A corpus-based study of quoi in French native speech
  19. The overlooked effect of amplitude on within-speaker vowel variation
  20. Contextualized word senses: from attention to compositionality
  21. Words of scents: a linguistic analysis of online perfume reviews
  22. Constraction: a tool for the automatic extraction and interactive exploration of linguistic constructions
  23. The Red Hen Anonymizer and the Red Hen Protocol for de-identifying audiovisual recordings
  24. Novel metaphor and embodiment: comprehending novel synesthetic metaphors
Heruntergeladen am 7.9.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/lingvan-2022-0004/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen