Self-limitation as the basis of environmentally sustainable care of the self
-
Richard Sťahel
Abstract
When we abandon the neoliberal fiction that one is independent on the grounds that it is a-historic and antisocial, we realize that everyone is dependent and interdependent. In a media-driven society the self-identity of the individual is formed within the framework of the culture-ideology of consumerism from early childhood. As a result, both the environmental and social destruction have intensified. In the global era, or in the era of the global environmental crisis, self-identity as a precondition for environmentally sustainable care of the self should be based on the culture-ideology of human rights and responsibilities, and on conscious self-limitation which realizes that one’s prosperity and security cannot come at the expense of others. Care of the self is about ensuring the habitability of the global environment as the primary interest of each individual.
Introduction
Globalization and industrialism are leading to the devastation of nature and the social environment, and these are intensified by the application of neoliberal ideology to almost all areas of life. The beginning of the neoliberal ideological campaign against the traditional social standards that place limits on willfulness in individual and social relations and hence on the social preconditions of care of the self can be dated back to 1976, the year Milton Friedman was awarded the Nobel Prize. This award was in fact taken as legitimization of the claim that the only responsibility of business and indeed any human activity is the maximization of profit regardless of the social and environmental consequences. Therefore, this maximization of private profit is by neoliberal narrative interpreted as obvious and natural care of the self. In the overconsuming society of global industrial civilization[2], which, inter alia, applies the growth principle to all areas of organized society, care of the self is understood, in considerably reduced form, to mean increased personal consumption—the consumption of water, energy, milk, meat, and so on, per person. However, as J. Patočka demonstrated in his work, care of the self was originally understood in a considerably different sense: that it played a constitutive role in understanding the self, philosophy, and society. As care of the self is currently understood to mean the maximization of consumption, paradoxically it makes it increasingly difficult for a growing circle of people to fulfill their most basic needs for social and environmental reasons.
In the end, this continuous effort to increase production and consumption leads to such devastation of the environment that soon the present form of life of the individual and society will become impossible[3]. In other words, despite having the scientific knowledge society is not able to see that the organization of its social life is in fact the mass suicide of civilization. This irrational action of global society can also be referred to as a social pathology. Critical theory can help us reflect upon and analyze the phenomenon, because as Axel Honneth emphasizes, “(…) critical theorists all claim that it is a lack of social rationality which causes the pathology of capitalist society” (Honneth, 2004, p. 340)[4]. We can then ask whether our environmental irresponsibility is not a pathology of reason. To understand the root of this social pathology or pathology of reason[5] we have to look at the image of humans based on current public policies and business activities.
Homo economicus vs homo politicus
The neoliberal ideal[6] of humans attempting to maximize personal profit (homo economicus) permeated public policies and norms of public and non-public institutions in the 1990s. Personal profit is not just the maximization of profit from any activity, but also the maximization of consumption. This notion of self-identity is formed through consumption from an early age. Mass media turn our children into competent, never satisfied consumers even before they learn to read and write in school. They are flooded with consumptive stimuli and items from the moment they are able to perceive them. Through mass media products preschool children are exposed to the never-ending attack of advertisements urging them to consume more.[7] Even in the state school system the addiction to commercial products (tablets, software, applications, etc.) is systematically built in. It is in this environment that children form their self-identity. It is this environment which shapes the anti-social homo economicus focused on personal profit and effectivity, a never satisfied consumer of products, services, and experiences. Global mass media networks and marketing campaigns ensure this identity prevails over most national, ethnic, and religious identities. Leslie Sklair has very fittingly labelled this phenomenon the culture-ideology of consumerism and argues that it is globalization driven (Sklair, 2009) and that it both shapes and is dependent upon today’s homo economicus.
Pursuing his own personal interest, homo economicus, comes into conflict with homo politicus who pursues the public interest and accepts responsibility for the wider community. The institutions of constitutional democracy were originally built on the notion of the active citizen taking an interest in society. As J. Patočka points out, care of the self was conceived in Ancient Greek philosophy as care of the soul, willingness and the need to know how to reason, and most of all, seek it out. In this sense care of the self is care of the public’s welfare, care of the community, care for the polis (Patočka, 1996b). It is one of the main reasons for philosophy’s existence[8]. As such it is conscious self-limitation. In small communities where only a small circle of relationships, interests, and possible conflicts need controlling, regulation exists in the form of ethical norms[9]. In bigger communities and complex societies ethical norms are internalized, for example by self-regulation, and are also enforced by social institutions, later by laws. In other words: “Not all desires could be fulfilled. Not everything could be said or enacted. The capacity to limit oneself was the essence of one’s freedom and the freedom of all” (Mbembe, 2016). However, neoliberalism considers all these forms of regulations to be limitations threatening freedom. It demands deregulation in the name of freedom, that is, it tries to eliminate all forms of regulation. It calls for naturalness or spontaneous order (Hayek, 1998, pp. 45-52; pp. 233-244) as the only guarantee of freedom. However, as it turns out, such freedom is reached at the expense of others through what it is becoming a privilege[10].
However, much of modern European thinking directly or indirectly relates to other views of freedom in which freedom and privilege exclude one another. In the mid-eighteenth century J.-J. Rousseau came to realize that inequality in society, frequently in the form of slavery, wouldoccur more spontaneously than equality and freedom. Moreover, often:
There are some unfortunate circumstances where one’s liberty can be preserved only at the expense of someone else’s, and where the citizen can be perfectly free only if the slave is completely enslaved (Rousseau, 2011, p. 220).
According to Rousseau true freedom is the result of conscious and purposeful limitations legitimized through the social contract. Here the social order is based on a contract rather than on nature or spontaneity[11]. Rousseau pointed out that people were mutually dependent and hence there was a need to find a model of society in which freedom was not realized at the expense of others[12].
The concepts of homo economicus and homo politicus are mutually exclusive normativities. This contradiction is reflective of the inner conflict in society as well as the legitimization crisis of the current economic and political system. This conflict considerably limits society’s ability to adequately react to the threats it faces. Society is atomized, paralyzed by inner conflict and deepening social inequality, while much energy is spent on conflicts arising from mutually exclusive private interests. But public interest should globalize so it is able to face global environmental threats and risks, because for society to survive in its current form requires the ability to take responsibility not only on the economic and political levels, but also on the environmental one.[13]
Care of the self has become the central motivation for almost all human activity with radical individualism, indifference, and skeptical relativism on the increase. This is not the care of the self Patočka identified in early Greek philosophy, but a care of the self, based on the idea that the individual is independent of everybody and everything. However, it has been shown that the more complex a society becomes, the denser the network of dependencies surrounding each individual. Individuals too often deceive themselves into thinking they are independent of everything and everyone—besides their own abilities[14]—in keeping with the mainstream narrative. Paradoxically, this idea is found in highly complex societies in which the individual is (mutually) dependent on far more relations and systems—social, technical, and natural—than ever before in human history. At the same time many of these relations, systems, and risks (energy, transport, communication, financial, environmental, etc.) cannot be controlled because they are global in nature[15]. However, the average individual seems to have a limited ability to understand that these forms of dependence are relatively limited. This is not simply because individuals are primarily interested in their immediate surroundings and personal relationships, but also because of this neoliberal narrative dominating public discourse. It tells people they are free and independent and have access to the unlimited consumption of products and services. As L. Hohoš notes,
(…) individual freedom came to mean individualized consumption in a consumer society, and consumer freedom within the framework of the market mechanism became a means of self-realization and individual independence (Hohoš, 2007, p. 42).
Therefore the fact that a society based on individualism, consumerism, and profit regardless of how they are achieved is not sustainable passes unnoticed amid the offers for a new car, TV, or exotic holiday.
Since the 1970s the neoliberal contra-revolution has been destroying the normative order of constitutional democracy by weakening the assumption that it is based on inclusive policies that attempt to reduce social differences. By emphasizing increases in production and consumption it has significantly hastened the devastation of the environment. The intensified industrialization, increase in the global population, and consumer demand over the last 50 years have led to such environmental devastation at the planetary level that humanity is no longer in the Holocene epoch with its mild and stable geology and climate that favorably influenced the development of civilization. Humanity as a geologic and climate force now faces the growing instability and unpredictability of the geological and climate epoch of Anthropocene[16], in which the most visible signs of ecosphere collapse are climate change and the sixth mass extinction of plant and animal species (Steffen et al., 2011). Natural science findings clearly point to the catastrophic consequences of this which, if it continues, will lead to the collapse of Earth’s life-support systems. K. E. Boulding’s 1960s metaphor of Earth as a spaceship has come to fruition[17]. It is remarkable that knowledge of this has not changed most everyday human activity[18]. Most people still act like cowboys on the prairie, taking what they want and leaving lots of trash behind and destroying nature rather than astronauts in a spaceship who have to recycle everything and anxiously observe all the environmental parameters enabling them to survive (the composition of the air they breathe, its temperature, humidity, pressure, etc.). Instead “we continue to plan for the future as if climate scientists don’t exist” (Hamilton, 2017). Real existential threats go unheeded by the public and by most of academia.
Culture-ideology of consumerism or culture-ideology of human rights
If there is any chance of reversing this progression (which is leading to a state in which the global ecosphere will not support the existence of the current civilization) we have to act fast. The nature of the risk also means that the entire normative system of the global civilization will have to change along with our understanding of self-identity and care of the self. The current variant influenced by the culture-ideology of consumerism will have to be abandoned. New norms that limit the ruthless production and consumption of all products and services will have to be set, and this will affect waste production and environmental destruction. In philosophy the global environmental crisis raises the issues of how norms that restrict the freedom of unlimited production and consumption can be justified[19], and of what we understand care of the self to mean. Growth in production and consumption is perceived to be the norm, and is even the goal of public policies[20], regardless of the devastating consequences for the biosphere and civilization. Permanent growth goes against the basic imperative of life, which is sustainability[21], and it also goes against basic physical limits, that is, the finiteness of resources.
In the global era, which is also the era of the global environmental crisis and especially the climate crisis, the problem of care of the self has to be looked at from the perspective of environmental sustainability. This calls for a reassessment of consumer freedom, which is almost impossible in this culture-ideology of consumerism. This is because the current form of consumer freedom is available only to a small section of the global population that has access to the unlimited consumption of products and services, mainly at the expense of the majority of the world’s population. The latter do not have freedom of consumption; people frequently do not have freedom of movement or the basic preconditions for life such as sufficient water, nourishment, and housing. J.-J. Rousseau’s idea that there were some unfortunate circumstances in which a person’s liberty could be preserved only at the expense of someone else’s is therefore still valid. We can agree with L. Sklair’s notion that it is necessary to distinguish between
(…) the culture-ideology of consumerism and rights to adequate consumption. The human right to adequate consumption (we can define this as the basic minimum level that even averagely well-off people would settle for), properly conceived, entails the social responsibility of those who are democratically elected to make such decisions to ensure that is available to all (Sklair, 2009, p. 87).
In other words, environmentally sustainable care of the self should be founded on the culture-ideology of human rights and responsibilities, on conscious self-limitation, knowing that one’s welfare and security cannot be secured at the expense of others. Environmentally sustainable care of the self-consciously works with the belief that human rights have to be respected and secured not just for the privileged population of the rich global North, but for all people on this planet. This means that the right to life, as the basic human right, implies at least the right to water, nourishment, housing, and breathable air[22]. Care of the self is about ensuring that the inhabitability of the global environment is the primary interest of each individual[23]. Earth’s life-support systems can be preserved through self-limitation in the demand for and expectation of consumption, for example self-limitation in travel[24], number of children born, and total consumption. However, as Hans Jonas suggests, it is hard to imagine under capitalism “that people would voluntarily do away with the hedonistic life in wealth they adopted in childhood” (Jonas, 1997, p. 219). The increase in consumption is seen as a means of self-realization and individual independence. The consequence of it is the exact opposite: the deepening and multiplication of dependencies and interdependencies. This means that environmentally sustainable care of the self is conditional on a change in the content, form, and goals of education as well as on a change to the basic imperatives of the economic and political system[25].
On the individual level care of the self should be based on the knowledge that with the current state of the development of global civilization, self-limitation of consumption is the sine qua non of the self-preservation of the individual and the human species. The goal, or ideal, that environmentally sustainable care of the self should seek is a lifestyle that does not limit the possibilities and preconditions of other people, not only within a territorial state but also on the global level, now and in the future. By seeking to preserve the potential life of others in society, across the world, and for future generations[26], the circle of care of the self widens, as Patočka mentions, to the community. This is defined not just territorially or ethnically, but so as to include all humanity[27]. It does not simply concern the current population, but also unborn children, and members of future generations. In this sense environmentally sustainable care of the self not only updates, but also radicalizes, secular humanism. In this sense humanism is humankind’s chance to survive[28].
Conclusion
To summarize, all this also applies to the climate agreement signed on 12 December 2015 in Paris, which, once ratified, will replace the Kyoto Protocol in 2020. The importance of this agreement lies in the fact that 196 countries, or their political representatives, have acknowledged that the phenomenon of anthropogenic climate change exists and that it constitutes a threat, and that they have agreed to deal with the threat. The aims the individual countries set for themselves are voluntary commitments to self-limitation at the state level[29],[30]. It is this voluntary commitment that is considered the main weakness of the agreement, because there is no mechanism to enforce the obligation to reduce greenhouse gas emissions. All that is required to fulfill the agreement is an efficient mechanism that would enforce these obligations at the political level, but also persuade the global population that environmentally sustainable care of the self is essential to the self-limitation of demand for and expectation of consumption.
References
Angus, I. (2016). Facing the Anthropocene: Fossil capitalism and the crisis of earth system. New York: Monthly Review Press.Suche in Google Scholar
Beck, U. (2010). Climate for change, or how to create a green modernity? Theory, Culture & Society, 27 (2-3), 254-266.10.1177/0263276409358729Suche in Google Scholar
Beck, U., & Sznaider, N. (2011). Self-limitation of modernity? The theory of reflexive taboos. Theory and Society, 40(4), 417-436. 10.1007/s11186-011-9145-5.Suche in Google Scholar
Boulding, K. E. (1966). The economics of the coming spaceship earth. In H. Jarrett (Ed.), Environmental Quality in a Growing Economy (pp. 3-14). Baltimore, MD: Resources for the Future/Johns Hopkins University Press.Suche in Google Scholar
Cílek, V. (2012). Suroviny a konec světa – od kolapsu k regeneraci. [Raw materials and the end of the world – from collapse to regeneration]. In M. Bárta, M. Kovář a kol., Kolaps a regenerace: Cesty civilizací a kultur. Minulost, současnost a budoucnost komplexních společností. [Collapse and regeneration: Paths of civilizations and cultures. Past, present and future of complex societies] (pp. 767-786). Praha: Academia.Suche in Google Scholar
D’Alisa, G., Demaria, F., & Kallis, G. (2015). (Eds.). Degrowth: A vocabulary for a new era. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9780203796146Suche in Google Scholar
Davies, J. (2016). The birth of the Anthropocene. Oakland, California: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520964334Suche in Google Scholar
Dunaj, Ľ. (2010). Reflections on justice under the condition of globalisation. Human Affairs, 20, 124-134.10.2478/v10023-010-0014-zSuche in Google Scholar
Dunaj, Ľ. (2014). To deficits of democratic thinking in Slovakia. In A. Javorská, K. Mitterpach, & R. Sťahel (Eds.), Philosophica 14: Rendering change in philosophy and society (pp. 7-20). Nitra: UKF.Suche in Google Scholar
Dunaj, Ľ. (2015). The pragmatist approach to sociocultural transformation as an alternative to neoliberal radicalism. Philosophica Critica, 1(2), 19-31.10.17846/PC.2019.1.2.19-31Suche in Google Scholar
Fromm, E. (2001). Humanizmus ako šanca prežiť (Moderný človek a jeho budúcnosť). [Humanism as a chance to survive (Modern man and his future)]. Filozofia, 56(2), 109-116.Suche in Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1980). Legitimation crisis. (3rd ed.). London: Heinemann. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/environment/2017/may/05/the-great-climate-silence-we-are-on-the-edge-of-the-abyss-but-we-ignore-it?CMP=share_btn_fbSuche in Google Scholar
Hamilton, C. (2017, May 5). The great climate silence: We are on the edge of the abyss but we ignore it. The Guardian.Suche in Google Scholar
Hansen, J. et al. (2015). Ice melt, sea level rise and superstorms: Evidence from paleoclimate data, climate modeling, and modern observations that 2 °C global warming is highly dangerous. Atmospheric Chemistry and Physics, 15, 20059–20179. Retrieved from http://www.atmos-chemphys-discuss.net/15/20059/2015/acpd-15-20059-2015.pdf10.5194/acpd-15-20059-2015Suche in Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A. (1998). Právo, zákonodarství a sloboda. Nový výklad liberálních principů spravedlnosti a politické ekonomie. [Law, legislation and liberty: A new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy]. Praha: Academia.Suche in Google Scholar
Hohoš, L. (2007). Globalization and a normative framework of freedom. Human Affairs, 17, 42-53.10.2478/v10023-007-0005-xSuche in Google Scholar
Hohoš, L. (2016). A tentative scenario of “Sustainable Degrowth Society”. Philosophica Critica, 2 (1), 59-64. Retrieved from http://philosophicacritica.ukf.sk/uploads/1/3/9/8/13980582/hohos_a_tententive_scenario__1_.pdf10.17846/PC.2019.2.1.59-64Suche in Google Scholar
Honneth, A. (1996). Patologie sociálního. Tradice a aktuálnost sociální filosofie [Pathologies of the social: The past and present of social philosophy.] In A. Honneth Sociální filosofie a postmoderní etika [Social philosophy and post-modern ethics] (pp. 27-86). Praha: Filosofia.Suche in Google Scholar
Honneth, A. (2004). A social pathology of reason: On the intellectual legacy of critical theory. In F. Ruch, (Ed.), The Cambridge companion on critical theory (pp. 336-360). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CCOL0521816602.014Suche in Google Scholar
Hrubec, M. (2008). On conditions of participation: The deficits of public reason. Human Affairs, 18, 81-91.10.2478/v10023-008-0007-3Suche in Google Scholar
Jonas, H. (1973). Technology and responsibility: Reflections on the new tasks of ethics. Social Research, (40)1, (Spring 1973), 31-54.Suche in Google Scholar
Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Suche in Google Scholar
Jonas, H. (1997). Princip odpovědnosti. Pokus o etiku pro technologickou civilizaci [The imperative of responsibility: In search of ethics for the technological age]. Praha: OIKOYMENH.Suche in Google Scholar
Mbembe, A. (2016, December 22). The age of humanism is ending. Mail & Guardian Online.Suche in Google Scholar
Patočka, J. (1996a). Nadcivilizacie a její vnitřní konflikt [Over-civilization and its internal conflict]. In J. Patočka Péče o duši I. Sebrané spisy. Svazek 1 [Care for the soul I: Collected works. Volume 1] (pp. 243-302). Praha: OIKOYMENH.Suche in Google Scholar
Patočka, J. (1996b). Evropa a doba poevropská [Europe and the post-European age]. In J. Patočka, Péče o duši II. Sebrané spisy. Svazek 2 [Care for the Soul II: Collected works. Volume 2] (pp. 80-148). Praha: OIKOYMENH.Suche in Google Scholar
Patočka, J. (1996c). Heretical essays in the philosophy of history. Edited by James Dodd. Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: OPEN COURT.Suche in Google Scholar
Rousseau, J.-J. (2011). On the social contract, or principles of political right. In J.-J. Rousseau The basic political writings. (2nd ed.) (pp. 153-252). Indianopolis: Hacket Publishing Company.Suche in Google Scholar
Sklair, L. (2009). The globalization of human rights. Journal of Global Ethics, 5(2), 81-96.10.1080/17449620903110235Suche in Google Scholar
Sklair, L. (2016). Half-Baked. Philosophica Critica, 2(2), 103-116.10.17846/PC.2019.2.2.103-116Suche in Google Scholar
Steffen, W., Grinevald, J., Crutzen, P., & McNeill, J. (2011). The Anthropocene: Conceptual and historical perspectives. In Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society A: Mathematical Physical and Engineering Sciences, 369(1938), 842-867. 10.1098/rsta.2010.0327Suche in Google Scholar
Steffen, W., Broadgate, W., Deutsch, L., Gaffney, O., & Ludwig, C. (2015). The trajectory of the Anthropocene: The great acceleration. The Anthropocene Review, 2(1), 81-98.10.1177/2053019614564785Suche in Google Scholar
Sťahel, R. (2015a). Človek, jeho sloboda a vlastníctvo v myslení Jeana-Jacquesa Rousseaua [Man, his freedom and ownership in the thinking of Jean-Jacques Rousseau]. In V. Manda, R. Sťahel, & T. Pružinec, Človek, sloboda a vlastníctvo vo filozofii raného novoveku [Man, freedom and ownership in early modern philosophy] (pp. 105-169). Bratislava: IRIS.Suche in Google Scholar
Sťahel, R. (2015b). Environmentálna zodpovednosť a environmentálna bezpečnosť [Environmental responsibility and environmental security]. Filozofia, 70(1), 1-12.Suche in Google Scholar
Sťahel, R. (2016a). Environmental limits of personal freedom. Philosophica Critica, 2(1), 3-21.10.17846/PC.2019.2.1.3-21Suche in Google Scholar
Sťahel, R. (2016b). Environmental crisis and political revolutions. In J. P. Arnason & M. Hrubec (Eds.), Social transformations and revolutions: Reflections and analyses (pp. 99-120). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.10.1515/9781474415354-006Suche in Google Scholar
Sťahel, R. (2016c). Climate change and social conflicts. Perspectives on Global Development and Technology, 15(5), 480-496. 10.1163/15691497-12341403.Suche in Google Scholar
Višňovský, E. (2013). Pragmatizmus je environmentalizmus [Pragmatism is environmentalism]. Filosofický časopis, 61(6), 845-860.Suche in Google Scholar
Tokar, B. (2014). Toward climate justice: Perspectives on the climate crisis and social change. Porsgrunn: New Compass Press.Suche in Google Scholar
UN (2015). Framework Convention on Climate Change (Adoption of the Paris Agreement). Retrieved from https://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2015/cop21/eng/l09r01.pdfSuche in Google Scholar
© 2017 Institute for Research in Social Communication, Slovak Academy of Sciences
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Care of the self in the Global Era
- Reflexivity and globalization: Conditions and capabilities for a dialogical cosmopolitanism
- Aesthetic cultivation and creative ascesis: Transcultural reflections on the late Foucault
- Careful becomings: Foucault, Deleuze, and Bergson
- Self-appropriation vs. self-constitution: Social philosophical reflections on the self-relation
- Care of the S: Dynamics of the mind between social conflicts and the dialogicality of the self
- Self-limitation as the basis of environmentally sustainable care of the self
- The deficits of critical thinking in the postmodern era
- The inner conflict of modernity, the moderateness of Confucianism and critical theory
- Sensibility in applied ethics
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Care of the self in the Global Era
- Reflexivity and globalization: Conditions and capabilities for a dialogical cosmopolitanism
- Aesthetic cultivation and creative ascesis: Transcultural reflections on the late Foucault
- Careful becomings: Foucault, Deleuze, and Bergson
- Self-appropriation vs. self-constitution: Social philosophical reflections on the self-relation
- Care of the S: Dynamics of the mind between social conflicts and the dialogicality of the self
- Self-limitation as the basis of environmentally sustainable care of the self
- The deficits of critical thinking in the postmodern era
- The inner conflict of modernity, the moderateness of Confucianism and critical theory
- Sensibility in applied ethics