Abstract
In this study, we present a modified quantum theory, denoted as QT*, which introduces mass-dependent decoherence effects. These effects are derived by averaging the influence of a proposed global quantum fluctuation in position and velocity. While QT* is initially conceived as a conceptual framework – a “toy theory” – to demonstrate the internal consistency of specific perspectives in the measurement process debate, it also exhibits physical features worthy of serious consideration. The introduced decoherence effects create a distinction between micro- and macrosystems, determined by a characteristic mass-dependent decoherence timescale, τ(m). For macrosystems, QT* can be approximated by classical statistical mechanics (CSM), while for microsystems, the conventional quantum theory QT remains applicable. The quantum measurement process is analyzed within the framework of QT*, where Galilean decoherence enables the transition from entangled states to proper mixtures. This transition supports an ignorance-based interpretation of measurement outcomes, aligning with the ensemble interpretation of quantum states. To illustrate the theory’s application, the Stern–Gerlach spin measurement is explored. This example demonstrates that internal consistency can be achieved despite the challenges of modeling interactions with macroscopic detectors.
1 Introduction
The foundations of quantum theory, an extremely successful theory for 100 years, continue to be the subject of controversy. A central aspect of this discussion is the question of the “semantic consistency” of quantum theory, a term coined by C. F. von Weizsäcker in [1], chapter 11.2. According to this author, “the semantic consistency of a physical theory should mean that its pre-understanding, with the help of which we physically interpret its mathematical structure, itself satisfies the laws of the theory” (p. 514, my translation). Applied to quantum theory, this raises the question of whether quantum mechanical measurement processes themselves can in turn be correctly described using the tools of quantum mechanics.
We will try to roughly classify the different positions on this “problem of the quantum mechanical measurement process”. The references to the position of individual physicists and their schools of thought are intended for illustrative purposes only and not as a serious contribution to the history of physics. One possible position, which we would like to call “dualism”, would be the requirement to describe the measuring apparatus classically in principle, whereby the cut between the measuring apparatus and the microsystem to be investigated can still be shifted. This position could be associated with one of the variants of the so-called “Copenhagen interpretation”. For the strict dualist, the measurement problem does not arise. It can only be formulated if one attempts to analyze the measuring apparatus itself as a quantum mechanical system.
Historically, this attempt goes back to J. von Neumann [2]. A strong argument in favor of such an approach is atomism, i.e., the insight that macroscopic bodies (e.g., measuring apparatuses) are made up of microsystems (e.g., atoms or molecules). But even an atomist can doubt whether macroscopic systems can be described by quantum theory in the same way as microsystems. For example, in his early textbook [3], G. Ludwig discussed the problem of the macroscopic arrow of time and relates this to the irreversible act of measurement. One can imagine a more general theory that is responsible for micro- and macrosystems and contains both the quantum mechanics of microsystems and, for example, the classical mechanics of macrosystems as a limiting case, see for example [4], §2.2. This comprehensive theory should then also describe the quantum mechanical measurement process in a semantically consistent way. We will refer to the two non-dualistic positions that result from this as “Q(uantum)-monism” and as “G(eneralized)-monism”.
For the Q-monist, the measurement problem presents itself in the following form: After the interaction between the microsystem and the measuring apparatus has been completed, the total system is in an entangled state, i.e., in a superposition of product states. On the other hand, it appears that exactly one term of this superposition is selected by reading the measurement result. This transition from the superposition to a term is called “reduction (or collapse) of the wave packet”. In a corresponding formulation of quantum theory, there are therefore two different types of time evolution: the unitary, deterministic, continuous evolution based on the dynamics of the quantum system, and the non-unitary, non-deterministic, discontinuous evolution due to measurement and the associated collapse of the wave packet. Because the latter cannot be reduced to the former, quantum theory appears to be semantically inconsistent.
There are various attempts to solve the measurement problem within Q-monism. One attempt, going back to von Neumannn [2], London, Bauer and Langevin [5], combines the reduction of the wave packet with the act of consciousness of reading the measurement result. Building on this, von Weizsäcker proposes to interpret the wave function ψ as the quintessence of the knowledge a physicist can have about a microsystem S. Further measurements on S then change this knowledge in a comprehensible way, and von Weizsäcker considers quantum theory to be semantically consistent with this interpretation, see [1].
Other approaches intended to solve the measurement problem are the “many worlds interpretation” of H. Everett III [6] and B. DeWitt [7], Bohm’s theory of hidden variables [8], the “consistent history interpretation” [9], the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber theory of the collapse of the wave function [10] and theories of decoherence [11]. Furthermore, R. Penrose’s idea that the collapse of the wave packet is triggered by gravitational effects [12] should be mentioned here, although this is not elaborated further.
An alternative to these solutions would be to unmask the measurement problem as a pseudo-problem. Although we are more concerned with the possible positions than with the people who hold them, it should be mentioned here that this position can be found quite clearly in the work of L. E. Ballentine [13], [14]. To this end, he brings the interpretation of (pure or mixed) quantum mechanical states into play. In the “individual system interpretation”, a pure state provides a complete and exhaustive description of an individual system, whereas in the “ensemble interpretation” a (pure or mixed) state provides a description of certain statistical properties of an ensemble of similarly prepared systems, [13], p. 360. Therefore, according to Ballentine, the paradoxical character of the superposition of product states after the interaction between microsystem S and measuring apparatus A disappears in the ensemble interpretation. It no longer refers to a fictitious state of the individual system S + A but to an ensemble of such individual systems.
It goes without saying that this is not the place to discuss the various proposed solutions in detail. However, we would like to take a closer look at Ballentine’s position outlined above. To do so, we will, after some general remarks in Section 2.1, sketch the elaboration of the ensemble interpretation by Ludwig [15] in Section 2.2. Then we will argue, against Ballentine, that the measurement problem also poses a difficulty in Q-monism with ensemble interpretation, see Section 2.3.
This leaves the supporters of the ensemble interpretation with G-monism. However, one weakness of G-monism is that it is based on a theory that is supposed to unite the micro and macro worlds, but which does not yet exist. Is such a theory even possible? What effects could play a role that only occur in a gradual transition from micro to macro systems? Motivated by such questions, we propose in the main part of the paper, starting with Section 3.1, as a toy theory a modified quantum theory QT* that has the desired properties. It uses elements from the decoherence theories, but differs from them by assuming a global fluctuation in position and velocity (“Galilei fluctuation”). On states that are understood in terms of the statistical interpretation these fluctuations act as averaged Galilean transformations and thus lead to a mass-dependent decoherence, see the Sections 3.2 and 3.3. Similarly as in the well-known work on decoherence, this explains why certain superpositions of states of heavy particles are not possible, see Sections 3.1 and 3.5. The description of quantum measurement processes in the modified theory QT* is given in Section 4, but under a restrictive condition, see Assumption 1. In Section 5 we apply the theory QT* to the example of a spin measurement by a Stern–Gerlach experiment. To ensure that the interaction between the microsystem (spin) and the measuring apparatus remains calculable, we simplify the detection of the silver atom by the elastic collision with a macroscopic particle whose location can be read off directly, see Section 5.1. Despite this drastic simplification, the description of the Stern–Gerlach experiment can be carried out consistently, as shown by the choice of concrete numbers for the relevant physical quantities in Section 5.2.
Finally, our results are summarized and discussed in Section 6. In particular, we discuss whether the theory QT* outlined here has physically plausible features beyond its toy character.
2 Ensemble interpretation of quantum states
We will focus on the contributions to the ensemble interpretation of Ballentine [13], [14] and Ludwig [4], [15]. For a broader overview see [16].
2.1 General remarks
We begin with a few remarks that somewhat soften the supposed contrast between “individual system interpretation” and “ensemble interpretation” of quantum states. In doing so, we emphasize the differences to classical theories, for which we consider classical statistical mechanics (CSM) as a generic example. Thereby we ignore mathematical subtleties that are irrelevant to this discussion. For example, pure states in CSM would be represented mathematically by points in phase space, whereas in any physical application finite uncertainty arises. Realistically, pure states are not realized by delta functions on phase space but approximated by functions with a finite width.
First, we consider pure states in quantum theory that are represented by projectors P = |ψ⟩⟨ψ| in a Hilbert space
Next, we consider genuinely mixed states, which are represented mathematically by statistical operators W in the Hilbert space
In the case of improper mixtures, it is not possible to distinguish such a decomposition of the ensemble depending on the closer circumstances. Below we will give an example where an assignment of pure states to individual systems of the ensemble can even be ruled out. In CSM the case of improper mixtures does not occur since the decomposition of a mixed state into pure states is always unique.
The announced example consists of the EPR-experiment, where a pair of particles is prepared in an entangled, rotationally invariant spin state
If Bob has made a spin measurement of the observable B = b ⋅ σ then it would be legitimate to call the mixed state W of the particle sent to Alice “proper” and the corresponding decomposition W = ∑ i p i P i is given by the two eigenprojectors P↑, P↓ of B, with p↑ = p↓ = 1/2. According to the above it would be permissible to assume that each particle arriving at Alice “has” either spin up or spin down w.r.t. the direction b chosen by Bob and corresponding to the perfect anti-correlation of spin measurement results of Alice and Bob.
The situation is different in the case where Bob has not made any spin measurement. Although the particles sent to Alice are characterized by the same mixed state
We conclude that the “individual system interpretation” of quantum states is possible in some cases, namely for pure states and proper mixtures, but for the general case, including improper mixtures, the “ensemble interpretation” is indispensable. In this respect, our argument goes beyond Ballentine [13], who sees in the “individual system interpretation” a conceivable but superfluous supplement to the “ensemble interpretation”, against which, among other things, Ockham’s razor argument speaks.
2.2 Preparation and registration procedures
We have seen in the preceding subsection that the distinction between “proper” and “improper” mixtures cannot be made at the level of statistical operators W but depends on the “closer circumstances” of the experiments. This can be taken as a motivation for introducing a refined vocabulary: A state described by W is not represented by a single ensemble of identically prepared systems but by a class of ensembles corresponding to different “preparation procedures”. Such a refined theory has been elaborated by Ludwig [15] and need not be reproduced here in all details. We will focus on the aspects relevant to this paper.
The attempt to interpret a quantum mechanical state as a single ensemble E of quantum systems leads to another problem: Every conceivable measurement of an observable (Hermitian operator) A, which has a complete system of eigenprojectors, leads to a corresponding partition of E consisting of subsets of E where the observable A has a definite value. For arbitrary finite sets of non-commuting observables and a dimension of the Hilbert space
A characteristic feature of Ludwig’s approach is the extension to preparation and registration procedures. Both types of procedures contain the description or construction manual of macroscopic devices in a classical language and can be realized by concrete processes as often as required. A single experiment consists of a combination of a realization of a preparation procedure and of a registration procedure and can be in turn be repeated as often as you want. The problem arises that there are obviously different combinations that differ in the relative spatio-temporal position of their parts. Ludwig solves this problem by demanding that the construction manuals refer to an abstract coordinate frame, which is replaced by a concrete coordinate frame for each realization. If you combine a preparation procedure and a registration procedure, you only need to identify the abstract coordinate frames. Another advantage of the introduction of abstract coordinate frames is that it enables a natural definition of time-translations or, more general Galilei transformations, operating on the coordinate frames of preparation procedures (Schrödinger picture) or, alternatively, of registration procedures (Heisenberg picture).
The purpose of an experiment is to obtain results. Ludwig’s formalism takes this aspect into account by assigning a probability λ(a, b0, b) to the triple of a preparation procedure a, a registration procedure b0 and an event b that can occur during the measurement. This leads to a function
where K denotes the set of states and L the set of effects. Coexistent effect processes generate “coexistent effects”. In his work [15] Ludwig further provides physical axioms for the structure (K, L, μ) such that K can be represented as the set of statistical operators W on a Hilbert space
The description of a particular experiment with the terms developed by Ludwig can sometimes be done in different ways, which is reminiscent of the shiftability of the cut in the Copenhagen interpretation. Consider, for example, the EPR experiment mentioned in the Section 2.1 of two measurements of Alice and Bob, resp., on a pair of particles. On the one hand, these measurements can be understood as coexistent effects measured for a pure state given by the projector onto
2.3 Ensemble interpretation and the measurement problem
To fix the notation we will assume that, after the interaction between the microsystem and the measurement apparatus, the total system assumes the pure state
where the states |Ψ α ⟩ refer to the microsystem and the states |ψ α ⟩ to the various outcomes which can be read off the measurement apparatus. Ballentine has argued [13] that this only then contradicts the experience that the measuring apparatus shows an unambiguous result if one assumes the individual system interpretation for the pure state Φ. There is supposedly no such problem with the ensemble interpretation for Φ.
We will discuss this position using Ludwig’s elaboration of the ensemble interpretation outlined in the last subsection. Then the state Φ is realized by a preparation procedure a. One could of course object that the preparation of a pure initial state for the measuring apparatus, which leads to (2) after time t, is extremely unrealistic. But this would be an argument against Q-monism. The discussion we analyze here, however, takes place within the framework of Q-monism, and is thus based on the premise that such a preparation procedure a is conceivable.
In Ludwig’s language, the states ψ α of the measuring apparatus can be interpreted as mutually exclusive coexistent effect processes, which enable a disjoint decomposition of the preparation procedure a of the form a = ⋃ α a α , similar to the EPR example from the Section 2.2. But this would result in a mixed state Φ, in contradiction to the assumption that Φ is a pure state.
We therefore come to the conclusion that the measurement problem persists, regardless of the interpretation of the state Φ according to the individual system interpretation or the ensemble interpetation.
3 Modified quantum theory QT*
3.1 Definitions
We consider non-relativistic quantum theory based on Galilean space-time
The connection to quantum theory is given by a projective, unitary, irreducible representation (“irrep”)
such that
see, for example, [19], [20]. Here
For the following we neglect the rotational degrees of freedom and thus set s = 0. Time translations are not considered since they correspond to a free time evolution and we will instead consider a more general unitary, Galilei invariant time evolution U(t). Moreover, for the purposes of this paper it will be convenient to pass from the momentum representation to the velocity representation of wave functions and hence to consider the Hilbert space
Then (5) will be reduced to
where
Explicitly, the transformation from
Then we obtain the positional representation of the reduced Galilean irrep analogous to (7) (denoted by the same letter)
where
3.2 Postulates and first results
So far, we have only sketched the well-known form of non-relativistic quantum theory. We will modify this theory by postulating that the “pure” time evolution described by a unitary family U(t) that commutes with the reduced Galilean irrep (10) is superimposed by a global quantum fluctuation:
Postulate 1
(Preliminary form)
Between the points in time t and t + δt, the total time evolution, in addition to the pure time evolution U(δt), is given by random, independent spatial translations a and Galilean boosts u. δt > 0 is a fixed time difference that is very small compared to the typical duration Δt of measurements.
The distribution of the two random variables a and u is left open, except that it is identical for all intervals (t, t + δt) and will be later restricted by certain assumptions on its statistical parameters. The order of space translations and boosts is irrelevant since, according to Weyl’s commutation relation, the commutator of their irreps is a constant phase factor that cancels if calculating probabilities.
We will discuss the consequences of Postulate 1 for the statistical interpretation of quantum theory, as outlined in Section 2.2. We will concentrate on the influence of random translations and boosts on the ensemble W, since the pure time evolution commutes with their representation. For two different time intervals (t1, t1 + δt) and (t2, t2 + δt) the values of the random variables a and u and their irreps
Postulate 1
(Final form)
Between the points in time t and t + Δt, the total time evolution, in addition to the pure time evolution U(Δt), is given by random, independent spatial translations a and Galilean boosts u which are normally distributed with zero mean values ⟨a⟩ = 0 and ⟨u⟩ = 0 and variances
In the language of stochastic processes we thus assume that a t and u t are independent 3-dimensional Brownian motions with variances σ2(a t − a s ) = α (t − s) and σ2(u t − u s ) = β (t − s) for s < t, resp., see, e.g., Def. 2.1 in [21]. In other words, the components of a t and u t are Lévy processes with vanishing jump term in the Lévy-Khintchine formula, cf. theorem (42.6) in [21].
In order to calculate the effect
Note that the transformation
It will be convenient to introduce new velocity coordinates by
and to rewrite (14) in the form
Analogously, we calculate the effect
Also this result will be rewritten by introducing new position coordinates
and assumes the form
Due to the similar structure also the transformation
Differentiating (18) w.r.t. the time parameter Δt gives the term
For later purposes we will prove the following
Lemma 1.
1. If the integral kernel W(x, y) of W in the positional representation is uniformly bounded in absolute value,
2. The analogous statement holds for the integral kernel W(v, w) of W in the velocity representation.
Proof.
It will suffice to prove the first statement concerning the positional representation of the integral kernel of W. For the effect of boost fluctuations it is clear that
□
3.3 Illustration of decoherence effects
It is plausible that the damping of the “off-diagonal” regions of the integral kernels W(v, w) and W′(x, y) by the transformations (14) and (18) possibly leads to decoherence effects. Nevertheless, it will be instructive to study these effects by means of an example.
We consider only one spatial dimension x and a statistical operator W′ with integral kernel W′(x, y) given by the projector onto a wave function representing a superposition of two wave functions sharply localized at x = A and x = B, resp., such that A < B. It follows that W′(x, y) almost vanishes everywhere except for four small regions located around the points (x = A, y = A), (x = A, y = B), (x = B, y = A) and (x = B, y = B), see Figure 1. Through the transformation W′ ↦ W″, see (18), the integral kernel W′(x, y) is multiplied by the “damping” Gaussian
in the η-direction orthogonal to the diagonal x = y.

Illustration of decoherence effects. The integral kernel W′(x, y) (dark yellow surface) corresponds to a wave function that is strongly concentrated at the points x = A and x = B. By multiplication with a Gaussian damping function that fulfills the condition Δη ≪ |A − B| (blue surface), where Δη is the width of the Gaussian in the direction orthogonal to the diagonal x = y, defined in (23), the off-diagonal peaks of W′(x, y) are suppressed. In contrast, multiplication with a Gaussian damping function that satisfies Δη ≫ |A − B| (green surface) leaves W′(x, y) practically unchanged.
The effect of this multiplication depends on the size of Δη relative to |A − B|: If Δη ≫ |A − B| the integral kernel W′(x, y) remains practically unchanged. The converse case Δη ≪ |A − B| leads to a complete suppression of the off-diagonal peaks of W′(x, y) at (x = A, y = B) and (x = B, y = A), see Figure 1. The resulting integral kernel W″(x, y) no longer represents a pure ensemble but a statistical mixture of two pure ensembles corresponding to localized wave functions at x = A or x = B. In the regime between these two extremal cases W″(x, y) is a mixture of ensembles corresponding to localized wave functions or superpositions where the statistical weight of the superpositions is gradually diminished for decreasing width Δη of the Gaussian.
Before returning to the general case, we note that a simulation of the transformation W′ ↦ W″ as a single process, starting from a superposition ϕ(x) of localized wave functions and performing a sequence of random boosts, would not change the double-peaked structure of |ϕ(x)|2. There is no “collapse of the wave packet” that accompanies the decoherence process W′ ↦ W″ for the case of Δη ≪ |A − B|. However, we would not see this as a disadvantage of the decoherence approach but rather as an argument against the interpretation of the wave function as the state of an individual system, see the discussion in Section 6.
3.4 Effect of Galilean fluctuations on composite systems
Due to the present approach, the fluctuation of translations and boosts affects the quantum system via the representation of the Galilean transformations. These representations influence the constituents of a quantum system and can thus be captured by reducing the product representation to irreducible representations (irreps). It is therefore not necessary to recalculate the composite effect of the fluctuations (possibly a further difference to GRW).
The reduction of a product of two representations results in a direct integral over irreps of the form ψ(R, …) with R as the center of mass coordinate, and the sum M = m1 + m2 of the individual masses as a parameter of the irrep, see [19]. This can be generalized directly to the product of N representations, where R is again the center of mass coordinate of the N constituents. If all constituents have the same mass, R is symmetric under permutations, and thus the irrep lies in the Bose sector. A problem arises here because the constituents of matter are fermions, mainly quarks and electrons. To a good approximation, however, one can restrict oneself to atomic nuclei as constituents (this is sufficient to obtain macroscopic masses). Atomic nuclei with an even mass number are co-bosons and can therefore be treated as bosons as long as their density is as low as that of normal matter. For atoms with odd mass numbers, pairs of atomic nuclei can in turn be regarded as constituents. The approximate description of co-bosons by bosons, which is also important in the context of Bose–Einstein condensation of ultracold atoms, has been discussed in various places, see e.g., [23], Ch. 6, [24], and [25].
3.5 The classical world
In the example of the preceding subsection we have only considered the effect of random boosts that lead to the multiplication of the integral kernel W′(x, y) of a statistical operator with a Gaussian damping function
In a similar way as sketched in Section 3.3 this transformation could possibly destroy superpositions of pure ensembles with different velocities, depending on the size of Δμ and the integral kernel W(v, w).
It seems at first sight that decoherence effects will be arbitrarily strong for increasing Δt. However, there is a time threshold τ, so that the decoherence reaches its maximum for Δt ∼ τ and does not increase further when Δt ≳ τ. τ can be obtained by the condition that the two widths Δη and Δμ satisfy the Heisenberg uncertainty relation:
For Δt ∼ τ, the attenuation of W′(x, y) near the diagonal causes a broadening of W′(v, w) due to the uncertainty principle, and vice versa, which brings the decoherence process to a standstill. τ may be called the “maximal decoherence time” due to Galilean decoherence. It is the simplest quantity with the dimension of time that can be formed from the parameters of the quantum system and Galilean fluctuation. In general, typical decoherence times will be shorter than τ, depending of the initial ensemble W.
Generalizing the example discussed in Section 3.3 we expect that Galilei decoherence will lead to a statistical operator W which is approximately “classical”, i.e., a mixture of pure states sharply localized in phase space (or, in this paper, position-velocity space). An example of such pure states is provided by the projectors onto (squeezed) coherent states |Ω⟩, see, e.g., [26]. These coherent states initially will have general variances
which entails
In the A we will present some calculations which confirm the expectation that Galilean decoherence leads to an approximately classical state if the following condition for decoherence is satisfied:
Here
Note that for Δt = τ this parameter assumes the value
There is an extensive literature on the problem of whether quantum mechanics contains classical mechanics as a limiting case, see [27], Chapter X, and in which sense decoherence plays a role in this, see [28] for a recent account. We can only address a few aspects of this debate here, in particular the controversy between Ballentine and Schlosshauer on the latter question [29], [30], [31], insofar as it indirectly affects issues of our paper.
First, it should be noted that in the so-called “Ehrenfest regime” there are approximate correspondences between classical trajectories and certain solutions of the Schrödinger equation, independent of any decoherence effects. The conditions for this are that the initial states are products of wave packets that are sharply localized with respect to position and momentum, and that the potential energy function is practically constant within the widths of the wave functions. Furthermore, this approximate correspondence is only valid for limited times, which can be relatively short for chaotic movements. For example, the trajectory of a billiard ball after 11 collisions is no longer uniquely determined even macroscopically due to Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle for the initial conditions, see [32].
In this respect, Ballentine has a point here, even if his research relates less to the Ehrenfest regime than to the so-called “Liouville regime” [33]. On the other hand, representatives of decoherence theories emphasize the aspect that an approximate reduction of classical mechanics to quantum mechanics must also explain why certain superpositions of macroscopic states (such as states of living and dead cats) cannot be prepared. A representative of Ballentine’s position could reply to this that such a superposition can indeed be prepared, but in the sense of the ensemble interpretation and not in the sense of individual systems in a superposition. We have already criticized this view in the Section 2.3 and would therefore recognize the need to explain the limited preparability of states in the CSM, but would point out that our variant of decoherence also provides the desired explanation.
In the case of the chaotic dynamics mentioned above, the theory QT* leads to a transformation of the relatively rapidly spreading pure state into a “proper” mixture. It thus also contains the limiting case of stochastic classical mechanics, which, as far as I can see, is not possible in the usual decoherence theories.
4 Quantum measurement
A quantum measurement consists of coupling a microsystem to a macrosystem (“measuring apparatus”) such that the time evolution of the total system leads to final states that can be classically distinguished. The problem is that, using only the pure time evolution, the final state will be an entangled superposition of different product states. In this section we will examine the extent to which the picture changes when Galilean fluctuations are taken into account.
We assume, for the sake of simplicity, that the Hilbert space
where
The total Hilbert space is hence
and the pure time evolution between t and t + Δt is given by a unitary operator
Assumption 1.
Using the preceding notation we assume:
This assumption on the state after the pure time evolution U(Δt) resembles the bi-orthogonal Schmidt decomposition of a twofold product state, see [17], Chapter 5.3, but note that in general there does not exist a Schmidt decomposition of triple product states. Physically, the Assumption 1 means that, besides the fundamental entanglement between the microsystem and the measuring apparatus which is represented in the superposition (33), the further entanglement between the pointer and the remaining degrees of freedom of the measuring apparatus can be neglected. We will not specify the form of the unitary representation of the Galilei group in the Hilbert space
The projector onto the state vector Φ(Δt) is hence of the form
The effect of the Galilei fluctuations will only be calculated for the last factor |Ω μ ⟩⟨Ω ν | of (35). This already shows that after the time Δt the pure state decays into a mixture of macroscopically distinguishable pointer states. It seems highly plausible that additional decoherence effects cannot affect this result.
We set
Here we have set
By assumption, for μ ≠ ν the pointer states Ω
μ
, Ω
ν
will be macroscopically distinguishable. This means that x
μ
, x
ν
or v
μ
, v
ν
will be macroscopically distinguishable. The latter can be translated into the condition
First, the factor
We collect the Gaussian terms in (37) which depend on x or y and transform the argument of the exponential them according to
where we have used (19) and the analogous definitions
Analogously as above, the first term in (??) will lead to a fapp vanishing of
Summarizing, the decoherence effects due to Galilean fluctuations will lead to fapp vanishing
After the time Δt the pure state W(Δt) decays into a statistical mixture of product states that correspond to definite pointer states Ω μ , μ = 1, …, r.
5 Example: Stern–Gerlach experiment
5.1 Simplified model
As an example to illustrate our previous considerations, we choose a simplified theoretical description, adapted to our definitions, of the historical Stern–Gerlach experiment (1922), in which the quantization of the electron spin was demonstrated (at least in retrospect).
A beam of silver atoms is sent through an inhomogeneous magnetic field and split into two partial beams due to the interaction of the magnetic moment of the outer 5s electron with the magnetic field, see Figure 2. In the simplified representation, we consider the spin of the 5s electron as a microsystem with 2-dimensional Hilbert space

Schematic representation of the Stern–Gerlach experiment.
After this part of the measurement the silver atom in turn interacts with a macrosystem (“detector”) and is finally detected in a rudimentary position measurement. We model this last part of the measurement by an elastic collision of the silver atom with another macroscopic particle P (the “pointer”) with Hilbert space
For future reference, we recall that a Gaussian wave packet satisfying the 1-dimensional free Schrödinger equation can be written in the form
with initial value
Here r i is one coordinate of the position vector r, m denotes the mass of the particle, v i a velocity parameter such that mv i will be the expectation value of r i -momentum and d will be the standard deviation of the r i -position observable at t = 0. Generally we have
which describes the well-known spreading of the wave packet with increasing time. This spreading can be neglected for short times, more precisely, for
A general element of the product space
where we have set
The next part of the measurement is the free time evolution of the silver atom described by ψ↑(r1, t) until it collides with the macroscopic particle P at x1 = A. At time t = t2 = 0 the macroscopic particle with mass m2 will be represented by the Gaussian wave packet written in product form
where we have set
As noted above, we will simplify the treatment of the collision by considering only the horizontal coordinates x1 of the silver atom and x2 of the pointer. Then the collision dynamics is most conveniently calculated by passing to center of mass and relative coordinates
since the motion w.r.t. X will be free if the interaction only depends on x. The inverse transformation is given by
Here we encounter the following problem: If we insert (48) into Ψ↑(x1, t)ψ↑(x2, t) the result can, in general, not be factored into a wave function depending on X and another one depending on x. This would call our Assumption 1 into question. Fortunately, we can achieve the factorization
for all t by the special choice
as can be shown by a short computation. This condition can be reformulated equivalently by saying that the “dissipation time”
The Schrödinger equation describing the collision between the silver atom and the pointer can then be decoupled into two equations of the form
Here M and μ are the total and the reduced mass, resp., defined in the usual way by
and V(x) is the interaction potential. Equation (51) describes a free time evolution for the center of mass wave function Φ↑(X, t). For the interaction potential we choose a repulsive delta function of the form
which entails that the transmission probability can be neglected and the silver atom will be reflected by the pointer with probability
We conclude that at time t ≥ t3 the collision is practically finished and that the total wave function will be of the form
where we have again invoked the condition (50) in order to factorize the result in the specified way.
In order to confirm the Assumption 1 it has to be shown that, for t ≥ t3, the final pointer state
The details of the calculation will be given in B.
So far we have only considered the first component of the spinor
It remains to confirm that, for some time t > t3 the two pointer states
The consistency of the various assumptions will be examined in the following subsection.
5.2 Choice of concrete values
It is the aim of this subsection to show, by choosing concrete values for the physical quantities of the simplified Stern–Gerlach experiment and for the free parameters α and β of the theory QT*, that the various assumptions we made in the previous subsection are consistent and also in agreement with the general theory of Galilean decoherence that we have developed.
Thus let us assume that a silver atom with mass m1 = 1.79 × 10−25 kg moves with a horizontal velocity of
After leaving the magnet, the silver atom moves horizontally for the time
Next we choose the mass of the macroscopic particle P as m2 = 108 m1 = 1.79 × 10−17 kg, approximately corresponding to the mass of a 18 corona viruses. Further let
which, by virtue of (25), (50) and (26), implies
Using these values we will check the consistency of our assumptions. First we estimate the vertical distance Δz = 2C between the two partial beams when they hit the screen as
It can therefore actually be ruled out that the silver atom deflected downwards interacts with the particle P, which is initially located at
Next we assume that the duration Δt of the total measuring process will be Δt = 102 τ = 0.5235 s. The times |t1| and t3 for the first parts of the measurement can therefore be neglected in comparison with Δt. During the time Δt, the pointer moves by the horizontal distance
This means that the two coherent states Ω↑ and Ω↓ can indeed be considered as macroscopically distinct and in this sense the condition (57) can be regarded as fulfilled.
The condition θ ≪ 1 which guarantees that the wave packet of the pointer practically will not spread during the measurement process is satisfied in the sense that
With the shorter collision time t3 = 6.667 × 10−4 s the wave packet of the silver atom will not spread either due to (50).
Finally, we consider the decoherence process after the time τ. The width Δη in the Gaussian function (20) assumes the value
Hence the superposition of the two pointer states Ω↑ and Ω↓ is damped by a factor which is fapp zero. In contrast, the analogous width Δη1 for the damping factor of the silver atom, calculated for the whole duration Δt of the measurement, assumes the value
which means that Galilean decoherence of the state of the silver atom can be safely neglected.
To summarize, we can say that a consistent choice of physical quantities is possible for the Stern–Gerlach experiment, which confirms our theory of decoherence by Galilean fluctuations.
6 Discussion and summary
There are numerous versions of the measurement problem in quantum mechanics in terms of its formulation and possible solutions. What justifies the publication of yet another version? On the one hand, it is the impression that the actual debate is too one-sidedly based on an “individual system interpretation” of quantum states. Furthermore, the discussion mostly seems to assume that macrosystems can also be described by quantum mechanics without further modifications, a position that we referred to in the Introduction as “Q-monism”.
We have therefore presented and discussed the ensemble interpretation in relative detail in the Section 2, following Ludwig’s approach. However, in our opinion, the thesis of Ballentine, another representative of the ensemble interpretation, that the measurement problem is a pseudo-problem, is not tenable, see Section 2.3.
There is a connection between the two points, ensemble interpretation and Q-monism. If, following Ludwig’s approach, one formulates an axiomatic basis of quantum mechanics with the basic concepts of “preparation” and “registration procedures”, there are obvious problems in applying these basic concepts to the preparation and measurement of all macroscopic quantum states. In this case, Ludwig therefore speaks of an “extrapolation” of quantum mechanics [4]. However, one does not necessarily have to follow this “skeptical semantics”, since there are other examples of physical theories with successful extrapolation: Nobody will doubt that the diameter of the sun is 1,392,700 km only because terrestrial scales would evaporate inside the sun.
The focus of our work is on the sketch of a modified quantum theory QT*, in which the measurement problem can be solved if the ensemble interpretation is adopted. The modification consists in the postulate of a global quantum fluctuation with respect to the position and velocity of quantum systems, which is effective in addition to the pure time evolution, whereby an arrow of time is distinguished. The average effect of these fluctuations leads to decoherence effects dependent on the mass m of the system with a (maximal) decoherence time τ(m). This does not allow an absolute distinction between micro- and macrosystems, but a distinction that depends on whether τ(m) ≫ Δt or τ(m) ≪ Δt applies with a time Δt typical for the duration of experiments. The restriction of QT* to macrosystems leads to a classical statistical mechanics (CSM) with a phase space with Cartesian (p, q)-coordinates. This is at least highly plausible, even if we have not worked out the details. The approximate reduction QT* → CSM is not surprising, but essentially a consequence of the postulate of phase space fluctuations, analogous to the identification of a “pointer basis” by the form of the interaction in decoherence theories. In our case, the role of the pointer basis is taken over by the overcomplete basis of coherent phase space states |Ω⟩. The analogous restriction to microsystems leads to the usual quantum theory QT, since Galilean decoherence can be neglected for microsystems and times Δt ≪ τ(m). As the time evolution of QT* differs from that of QT, these theories will not be empirically equivalent. Especially for systems at the boundary between micro and macro decoherence effects should be measurable and provide estimates for the parameters α and β.
The quantum mechanical measurement process was treated in the theory QT* under the restrictive condition that the entangled total state after the pure measurement interaction has the form of a superposition of triple product states. This can be heuristically justified by the fact that the transition to a mixture of macroscopically distinguishable pure states by virtue of Galilean decoherence is then particularly easy to handle. To show the consistency of the various assumptions with each other and with the choice of the free parameters in QT*, we have considered the spin measurement in a Stern–Gerlach magnet as an example. The tricky point here is the interaction of the deflected silver atom with a macroscopic detector, which we have roughly modeled as an elastic collision with a macroscopic particle.
We should emphasize that the theory QT* in no way describes the occurrence of a concrete measurement result in a single experiment. This would not be expected simply because of the underlying ensemble interpretation of quantum states. Rather, the Galilean decoherence transforms the entangled state into a “proper” mixture, which allows an ignorance interpretation. This ignorance is eliminated by reading the measurement result.
It is an interesting question whether the dissipative modification of the unitary time evolution we consider can be described by a dynamical semigroup. For reasons of time and space, we were unable to pursue this question further in our work. Preliminary calculations indicate that this is indeed the case, but that the dynamical semigroup has unbounded generators. Thus, it is not covered by the characterization of covariant norm-continuous semigroups found by Holevo [34], see also the related papers [35], [36] which consider Galilean covariant dynamical semigroups.
Finally, we would like to discuss the role of the QT* theory. It is initially intended as a toy theory that can be used to demonstrate the fundamental possibility of a theory comprising QM and CSM. On the other hand, there are also physical arguments that make a modified quantum theory along the lines of QT* does not appear to be completely arbitrary. We recall that in Ludwig’s statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics, the effect of Galilean transformations on states (or, alternatively, on effects) was indirectly defined by the effect of these transformations on (classical) coordinate frames. The construction manuals for preparation apparatus refer to these coordinate frames. In this respect, the arbitrary accuracy with which a Galilean transformation and its representation is specified is an extrapolation of a classical inaccuracy. However, this accuracy can be questioned in terms of semantic consistency (this time in a different context than mentioned in the Introduction): The devices, scales, clocks and optical measuring instruments, for the numerical determination of a Galilean transformation are again quantum objects. They therefore exhibit typical uncertainties and fluctuations that stand in the way of an arbitrarily precise determination of a Galilean transformation.
We mention as an additional source of uncertainty the classical description of (non-relativistic) gravity by a Newton–Cartan geometry with a curved connection [37], which is reminiscent of Penrose’s idea. This replaces the definition of Galilean transformations in the classical sense with path-dependent parallel transport of Galilean frames.
However, a mathematical formulation of this fundamental uncertainty of Galilean transformations is completely open. The requirement of Galilean fluctuations between two points in time t and t + δt can be seen as a first attempt at such a formulation. One can therefore speculate whether other formulations lead to similar decoherence effects and thus explain the emergence of a classical world for times larger than τ(m).
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Thomas Bröcker for numerous discussions on the topics covered in this paper and for his encouragement in writing it.
-
Research ethics: Not applicable.
-
Informed consent: Not applicable.
-
Author contributions: The author has accepted responsibility for the entire content of this manuscript and approved its submission.
-
Use of Large Language Models, AI and Machine Learning Tools: None declared.
-
Conflict of interest: The author states no conflict of interest.
-
Research funding: None declared.
-
Data availability: Not applicable.
Appendix A: Decay into a mixture of coherent states
We consider the (squeezed) coherent states
This definition is in accordance with [26] except that we consider the position-velocity space instead of phase space. Due to the completeness relation
we may represent any statistical operator W in the form
The corresponding mixture of coherent states has the form
which is formally obtained from (A3) by setting
Hence an ensemble W is approximately a mixture of coherent states,
The following calculations will show that this is the case for the statistical operator W″ resulting after the two transformations
First we consider
Here we have, additionally to (19) and (15), defined
and
Using
we collect all terms of (A8) arising in the η-integral:
According to our assumptions and Lemma 1 there exists a least upper bound
In the next step we insert this result into the remaining ξ-integration and obtain
If Δt assumes the maximal decoherence time τ we have
The remaining task is to show that ⟨Ω′|W″|Ω⟩ is sharply concentrated at
μ
0 = 0. Here we can argue quite analogously to the previous discussion by using the velocity representation instead of the position representation and the fact that the order of action of
Summarizing, ⟨Ω′|W″|Ω⟩ is sharply peaked about the diagonal Ω′ = Ω and due to the Galilean fluctuations the statistical operator can be approximated by a mixture of classical states. We have shown that this happens for Δt = τ but for concrete examples the effective decoherence time may be much smaller than the maximal decoherence time τ,
Appendix B: Approximation by coherent states in the Stern–Gerlach example
We explicitly calculate the pointer state
where f(t) is a complex function used for normalization (except for a time-dependent phase factor) and R(x2, t) and I(x2, t) are real functions of the following form:
where θ was the dimensionless parameter defined in (56). Moreover,
where
and
We conclude that, if all terms of linear or higher order in θ are neglected, the wave packet
It has to be checked that the standard deviation σ x = d2 of this coherent state is in accordance with the other data of the Stern–Gerlach example and the general theory outlined in this paper, see Section 5.2.
References
[1] C. F. von Weizsäcker, Aufbau der Physik, München, Wien, Carl Hanser, 1985.Suche in Google Scholar
[2] J. von Neumann, Matnematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Berlin, Springer, 1932, (English translation: “Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics”, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1955).Suche in Google Scholar
[3] G. Ludwig, Die Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik, Berlin, Springer, 1954.10.1007/978-3-662-37993-6Suche in Google Scholar
[4] G. Ludwig, An Axiomatic Basis for Quantum Mechanics, Volume 2, Quantum Mechanics and Macrosystems, New York, Springer, 1987.10.1007/978-3-642-71897-7Suche in Google Scholar
[5] F. London, E. Bauer, and P. Langevin, La théorie de 1’observation en mécanique quantique, Paris, Hermann, 1939.Suche in Google Scholar
[6] H. EverettIII, ““Relative state” formulation of quantum mechanics,” Rev. Mod. Phys., vol. 29, no. 3, pp. 454–462, 1957. https://doi.org/10.1103/revmodphys.29.454.Suche in Google Scholar
[7] B. S. deWitt, “The Everett-Wheeler interpretation of quantum mechanics,” in Battelle Rencontres, 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics, C. M. deWitt and J. A. Wheeler, Eds., New York, Benjamin, 1968, pp. 318–332.Suche in Google Scholar
[8] D. Bohm and J. Bub, “A proposed solution of the measurement problem in quantum mechanics by a hidden variable theory,” Rev. Mod. Phys., vol. 38, no. 3, pp. 453–469, 1966. https://doi.org/10.1103/revmodphys.38.453.Suche in Google Scholar
[9] R. B. Griffiths, “Consistent histories and the interpretation of quantum mechanics,” J. Stat. Phys., vol. 36, nos. 1–2, pp. 219–272, 1984. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf01015734.Suche in Google Scholar
[10] G. C. Ghirardi, A. Rimini, and T. Weber, “Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems,” Phys. Rev. D, vol. 34, no. 2, pp. 470–491, 1986. https://doi.org/10.1103/physrevd.34.470.Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
[11] D. Giulini, E. Joos, C. Kiefer, J. Kupsch, I.-O. Stamatescu, and H. D. Zeh, Eds. Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, Springer, 1996.10.1007/978-3-662-03263-3Suche in Google Scholar
[12] R. Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds and The Laws of Physics, Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 1989.10.1093/oso/9780198519737.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar
[13] L. E. Ballentine, “The statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics,” Rev. Mod. Phys., vol. 42, no. 4, pp. 358–381, 1970. https://doi.org/10.1103/revmodphys.42.358.Suche in Google Scholar
[14] L. E. Ballentine, Quantum Mechanics: A Modern Development, 2nd ed. Singapore, World Scientific, 2015.Suche in Google Scholar
[15] G. Ludwig, An Axiomatic Basis for Quantum Mechanics, Volume 1, Derivation of the Hilbert Space Structure, New York, Springer, 1985.10.1007/978-3-642-70029-3_1Suche in Google Scholar
[16] D. Home and M. A. B. Whitaker, “Ensemble interpretations of quantum mechanics. A modern perspective,” Phys. Rep., vol. 210, no. 4, pp. 223–317, 1992. https://doi.org/10.1016/0370-1573(92)90088-h.Suche in Google Scholar
[17] A. Peres, Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1993.Suche in Google Scholar
[18] S. Kochen and E. P. Specker, “The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics,” J. Math. Mech., vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 59–87, 1967. https://doi.org/10.1512/iumj.1968.17.17004.Suche in Google Scholar
[19] J.-M. Lévy-Leblond, “Galilei group and nonrelativistic quantum mechanics,” J. Math. Phys., vol. 4, no. 6, pp. 776–788, 1963. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.1724319.Suche in Google Scholar
[20] J.-M. Lévy-Leblond, “Nonrelativistic particles and wave equations,” Commun. Math. Phys., vol. 6, pp. 286–311, 1967, https://doi.org/10.1007/bf01646020.Suche in Google Scholar
[21] R. F. Bass, Stochastic Processes, Cambridge Series in Statistical and Probabilistic Mathematis, vol. 33, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2011.Suche in Google Scholar
[22] K. Kraus, States, Effects, and Operations Fundamental Notions of Quantum Theory, Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 190, Berlin, Springer, 1983.10.1007/3-540-12732-1Suche in Google Scholar
[23] H. J. Lipkin, Quantum Mechanics: New Approaches to Selected Topics, North-Holland, New York, 1973, reprinted by: Courier Corporation, 2014.Suche in Google Scholar
[24] S. Avancini, J. R. Marinelli, and G. Krein, “Compositeness effects in the Bose-Einstein condensation,” J. Phys. A: Math. Gen., vol. 36, no. 34, pp. 9045–9052, 2003. https://doi.org/10.1088/0305-4470/36/34/307.Suche in Google Scholar
[25] P. Céspedes, E. Rufeil-Fiori, P. A. Bouvrie, A. P. Majtey, and C. Cormick, “Description of composite bosons in discrete models,” Phys. Rev. A, vol. 100, no. 1, p. 012309, 2019. https://doi.org/10.1103/physreva.100.012309.Suche in Google Scholar
[26] J. R. Klauder and B. S. Skagerstam, Coherent States: Applications in Physics and Mathematical Physics, Singapore, World Scientific, 1985.10.1142/0096Suche in Google Scholar
[27] E. Scheibe, Die Reduktion physikalischer Theorien, Teil II: Inkommensurabilität und Grenzfallreduktion, Berlin, Springer, 1999.10.1007/978-3-642-59286-7Suche in Google Scholar
[28] P. Strasberg, “Classicality with(out) decoherence: concepts, relation to Markovianity, and a random matrix theory approach,” SciPost Phys., vol. 15, no. 1, p. 024, 2023. https://doi.org/10.21468/scipostphys.15.1.024.Suche in Google Scholar
[29] N. Wiebe and L. E. Ballentine, “Quantum mechanics of hyperion,” Phys. Rev. A, vol. 72, no. 2, p. 022109, 2005. https://doi.org/10.1103/physreva.72.022109.Suche in Google Scholar
[30] M. Schlosshauer, “Classicality, the ensemble interpretation, and decoherence: resolving the hyperion dispute,” Found. Phys., vol. 38, pp. 796–803, 2008, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-008-9237-x.Suche in Google Scholar
[31] L. E. Ballentine, “Classicality without decoherence: a reply to Schlosshauer,” Found. Phys., vol. 38, pp. 916–922, 2008, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-008-9242-0.Suche in Google Scholar
[32] D. J. Raymond, “How determinate is the “billiard ball universe”,” Am. J. Phys., vol. 35, no. 2, pp. 102–103, 1967. https://doi.org/10.1119/1.1973895.Suche in Google Scholar
[33] L. E. Ballentine, “Quantum-to-classical limit in a Hamiltonian system,” Phys. Rev. A, vol. 70, no. 3, p. 032111, 2004. https://doi.org/10.1103/physreva.70.032111.Suche in Google Scholar
[34] A. S. Holevo, “A note on covariant dynamical semigroups,” Rep. Math. Phys., vol. 32, no. 2, pp. 211–216, 1993. https://doi.org/10.1016/0034-4877(93)90014-6.Suche in Google Scholar
[35] S. Nimmrichter and K. Hornberger, “Macroscopicity of mechanical quantum superposition states,” Phys. Rev. Lett., vol. 110, no. 16, p. 160403, 2013. https://doi.org/10.1103/physrevlett.110.160403.Suche in Google Scholar
[36] B. Schrinski, S. Nimmrichter, B. A. Stickler, and K. Hornberger, “Macroscopicity of quantum mechanical superposition tests via hypothesis falsification,” Phys. Rev. A, vol. 100, no. 3, p. 032111, 2019. https://doi.org/10.1103/physreva.100.032111.Suche in Google Scholar
[37] P. Havas, “Four-dimensional formulations of Newtonian mechanics and their relation to the special and general theory of relativity,” Rev. Mod. Phys., vol. 36, no. 4, pp. 938–965, 1964. https://doi.org/10.1103/revmodphys.36.938.Suche in Google Scholar
[38] C. Brislawn, “Kernels of trace class operators,” Proc. Am. Math. Soc., vol. 104, no. 4, pp. 1181–1190, 1988. https://doi.org/10.2307/2047610.Suche in Google Scholar
© 2025 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Frontmatter
- Dynamical Systems & Nonlinear Phenomena
- Controlling the convective heat transfer of shear thinning and shear thickening fluids in parallel plates with magnetic force
- Multistability, chaos and hyperchaos in a novel 3D discrete memristive system: microcontroller implementation and cryptography
- Comparative study of thermally intense cilia and non-cilia generated motion of Ellis’s fluid by using MATHEMATICA 14.1
- Fundamental Concepts of Physical Science
- Nonlinear electrodynamics and its possible connection to relativistic superconductivity: instance of a time-dependent system
- Galilean decoherence and quantum measurement
- Solid State Physics & Materials Science
- A dynamically tunable polarization-insensitive broadband vanadium dioxide-assisted absorber for terahertz applications
- Thermodynamics & Statistical Physics
- Heat transfer analysis for the Cattaneo–Cristov heat flux model using integral transform technique with isothermal and isoflux wall conditions
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Frontmatter
- Dynamical Systems & Nonlinear Phenomena
- Controlling the convective heat transfer of shear thinning and shear thickening fluids in parallel plates with magnetic force
- Multistability, chaos and hyperchaos in a novel 3D discrete memristive system: microcontroller implementation and cryptography
- Comparative study of thermally intense cilia and non-cilia generated motion of Ellis’s fluid by using MATHEMATICA 14.1
- Fundamental Concepts of Physical Science
- Nonlinear electrodynamics and its possible connection to relativistic superconductivity: instance of a time-dependent system
- Galilean decoherence and quantum measurement
- Solid State Physics & Materials Science
- A dynamically tunable polarization-insensitive broadband vanadium dioxide-assisted absorber for terahertz applications
- Thermodynamics & Statistical Physics
- Heat transfer analysis for the Cattaneo–Cristov heat flux model using integral transform technique with isothermal and isoflux wall conditions