Abstract
Roman-Catholic scholars tend to interpret Luther’s emphasis on the exteriority of salvation as a critique of the goodness of creation. Through an analysis of De servo arbitrio, this article shows this to be wrong. While emphasizing the unconditionality of God’s work in both creation and salvation, Luther still insists that humans are created in God’s image as his co-operators, thus repeating the divine lordship over creation. This is further emphasized in other works that go beyond De servo arbitrio in finding Christology to be a key to the relationship between God and humans. Luther thus has an integrated understanding of all aspects of human life as the area of divine creation and should not be seen as a forerunner of a modern, secularized worldview. This role rather belongs to Erasmus, who insists that God stands idly by while humans make up their minds about how to live their lives.
1 Introduction
In 2001, Margaret Daphne Hampson published a book, Christian Contradictions, where she documents and deplores the inability among Roman-Catholic scholars to understand Martin Luther and the Lutheran Reformation. In her view, this inability is related to the Lutheran emphasis on extrinsic or alien righteousness, which differs from the Roman-Catholic insistence on understanding salvation as a process of renewing the original human position of being created in the likeness of God. According to the accepted Roman-Catholic view, the Lutheran emphasis on the exteriority of salvation implies a rejection of the goodness of creation and of the human ability to cooperate with God. This emphasis may to some extent be excusable as a reaction against the one-sidedness of late medieval semi-Pelagianism.[1] A certain respect for Luther is therefore now acceptable even within a Roman-Catholic context.[2] Still, his emphasis on human sinfulness implies a deplorable rejection of the analogy between God and creation which, according to many of his critics, led to Luther, against his intentions, becoming an agent of secularisation.[3]
In Christian Contradictions, Hampson points to ideas in the works of Søren Kierkegaard as a possible bridge between the two traditions. Useful as Kierkegaard may be in this context, I think that is to go one step too far. In my view, what Roman-Catholics find lacking in Luther’s theology is there and has been there all the time; it is only a question of knowing where to look. Arguing from the two basic narratives of the Bible, the story of creation and the story of Christ, one has to present salvation as a renewal of the original human position as being created in the likeness of God.[4] This is something the mature Luther understood very well – it is a cornerstone in his theological thinking at least from 1519.[5]
To defend this statement is the main goal of this article, and my main source will be the book Luther himself considered his most profound theological and metaphysical inquiry, De servo arbitrio, written in 1525,[6] and the understanding of divine–human cooperation that is found in this book.[7] To set things in context, however, I will start by presenting what provoked Luther into writing De servo arbitrio, which was the alternative understanding of the relationship between God and the human found in Erasmus of Rotterdam’s book Diatribe de libero arbitrio, published in 1524.[8]
2 The Relation between God and the Human According to Erasmus’s De libero arbitrio
Erasmus considers the question de libero arbitrio (concerning free choice)[9] as one of the most complicated problems in biblical interpretation (Ia1). The reason is that the human ability to order one’s behaviour by means of an informed and conscious choice touches upon questions concerning the contingence of divine foreknowledge, whether our will contributes to our salvation or we are only acted upon by grace,[10] or whether everything happens by necessity or not (Ia8). These questions are in Erasmus’s view rather left unsolved; they belong to the innermost sanctuaries into which God does not want us to penetrate (Ia7). The reason is that the exploration of these issues side-tracks us from what Erasmus considers the essence of the via pietatis, which is to strive for improvement while trusting divine mercy, knowing that no injustice can be caused by God who is by nature just.[11] But even without solving these problems, Erasmus considers it essential to think that free choice has at least some power (Ia5).[12]
Erasmus does not go into any details why he finds this to be the only acceptable solution. But it seems to be related to Erasmus’s finding the implications of not holding this position to be unacceptable. If it is said that God causes both good and evil in us, this will according to Erasmus short-circuit the striving for improvement and lead to nothing but godlessness, as nobody can love a God who throws people into hell as punishment for the evil deeds he has caused (Ia10).[13] The outcome of the final judgement must therefore somehow be related to the quality of the human contribution. If this vis liberi arbitrii is totally rejected, the via pietatis is undermined. We therefore have to accept an understanding of free choice as the power of the human will whereby a person may connect oneself to or turn away from what leads to eternal salvation.[14]
The inconsistency of this argument is fairly obvious and was certainly not lost on an astute reader like Luther. Erasmus maintains that he wants to leave the questions concerning divine foreknowledge and power of grace unsolved but does in fact insist on a quite ambitious solution. If the power of free and unrestricted choice is real also in questions that are related to the divine–human relationship, then divine foreknowledge is necessarily contingent, and salvation is necessarily conceived as the outcome of cooperation between divine grace and human choice. Trying to the best of his ability not to be seen as a follower of Pelagius, Erasmus accepts as satis probabilis the position of those who contribute pene nihil (almost nothing) to free choice (IIa12). But as Luther repeatedly makes Erasmus aware, the question of the amount of the power of free choice is uninteresting; the interesting question is whether it is a part of the process or not.[15] And regarding that question, Erasmus does not leave anybody in the dark concerning his own position.
But the argument is not only inconsistent; it also fails to consider an essential part of the problem.[16] The one question Erasmus does not investigate, neither in the introduction nor in any other part of De libero arbitrio, is the question of what kind of relationship God and human have. Essential in the Bible and through most of the history of Christian thinking is the understanding that God is the Creator and that humans are created. The relationship is thus asymmetrical from the outset; the human is dependent on God in a way that cannot be turned the other way around. Irrespective of what humans do or do not do, they act from within the God relationship (Acts 17:28). At the same time, the divine way of dealing with the world is set as the ideal for humans to follow (Matt 5:48). God is thus not only the origin of human existence, but there is also an analogy between them. The dialectics of this analogous, though radically asymmetrical, relationship is something Erasmus fails to consider. As he tells the story, the human connects with or turns away from what leads to salvation while God is standing idly by; God thus abdicates as Creator while the human makes up his or her mind.[17] God and the human are competitors, and human freedom is therefore only conceivable as divine absence. They only cooperate in the sense that they contribute to different parts of the solution.[18]
There are two implications of this approach that are important for the present investigation. For one thing, the foundation of Erasmus’s understanding of God remains unclear. God’s existence and the necessity of coming to terms with God through a negotiated solution are taken for granted, but it is unclear which problem this is supposed to solve. Erasmus’s via pietatis is essentially a vision of morally acceptable behaviour, but it is not clear what God’s role is in establishing and realizing this goal. While still being mentioned as a source of mercy and justice, God has no role to play when humans are making up their minds about which course to follow in life. A God who does not make any difference is easily dispensed with. The real secularizing influence from this debate thus comes from Erasmus’s short-circuiting the God relationship in his understanding of human liberty.[19] This was well understood by Luther, who found the main problem with Erasmus’s approach in his understanding of God.[20]
The other implication is that Erasmus, in overlooking the foundational character of the God relationship, clearly differs from post-Tridentine Roman-Catholicism.[21] For all its failures in grasping the essence of the theology of the Reformers, its representatives still understand the significance of the relation to the Creator for the understanding of the created.[22] Luther’s critique of Erasmus should therefore not be seen as paradigmatic for the relation between Lutheranism and Roman-Catholicism; on the contrary, it rather anticipates the Roman-Catholic critique of secularized liberalism.
An interesting illustration of this second point is D.C. Schindler’s book Freedom from Reality from 2017.[23] Schindler is as uninformed and prejudiced concerning Luther’s thought as any of the authors considered by Margaret Hampson, thus confirming her main thesis on all accounts.[24] Still, large parts of his critique of the deficiency of the self-referential understanding of freedom found in modern, secularized understandings of human liberty, which for Schindler above all is prefigured in the work of John Locke, read as a reiteration of Luther’s critique of Erasmus.[25] No wonder, as Luther’s and Schindler’s starting points are virtually identical: If not informed by a thick description of the goodness of the created and its divine origin, any understanding of human liberty will move in the direction of formal definitions void of any content.[26]
Luther is clearly not satisfied with Erasmus’s approach, and it is not difficult to see why. What, then, are the main emphases of his own approach?
3 Divine–Human Cooperation According to De servo arbitrio
Luther’s main point of orientation is a strong theology of creation.[27] Not only is God the origin of all there is; his creative activity is at the core of all that happens. The expression from 1 Corinthians 12:6, “Deus operetur omnia in omnibus” (God works all in all), runs like a refrain through De servo arbitrio; it is quoted no less than seven times.[28] What humans experience when they open their senses and take in what happens in the world is therefore nothing but the activity of God.
As the eternal One, God does this in a way that is always unconditioned by the created.[29] Temporal change does not apply to God.[30] While this puts the divine essence beyond what can be grasped by human rationality,[31] the principle itself is in Luther’s understanding something that follows with logical necessity from the distinction between Creator and creation and is for that reason perfectly rational. It can therefore be grasped even by those who do not know the biblical revelation, and this is in Luther’s view also the case.[32]
This is the reason for Luther’s insistence that everything happens by necessity “as far as the will of God is concerned.”[33] The point Luther is trying to make is that God is not dependent on anything outside himself for his will to occur.[34] Luther may have been in doubt whether the idea of necessity is the ideal one in this context;[35] he might have been better off by staying with the idea of divine unconditionality.[36] But there is no doubt this was absolutely essential in his understanding of God.
As far as I can see, Luther is emphasizing two points here. First of all, he is convinced that an understanding of a God as conditioned by elements in the created world literally does not make sense. If even God suffers change, there is nothing beyond the flux of change. Then, everything is arbitrary, and truth does not exist. The idea of divine foreknowledge contingent upon the decisions of humans is therefore incoherent. Philosophically, this insistence on the unconditionality of the origin both of the intelligible and of the sensible is based on an ultimately Platonic intuition of the necessity of transcendence as the only possible warrant against the world disappearing in the quagmire of arbitrariness.[37] If what is experienced by humans has a given structure, then the source of this structure cannot itself be a part of it. In actualizing this perspective, Luther is but a link in a chain that goes all the way from Plato to MacIntyre and Schindler.[38] From a theological perspective, the notion of divine unconditionality is founded on the biblical emphasis on God’s eternity and unchangeability (Ps 90:2; Jam 1:17).
The other point Luther is making is that he connects divine infallibility to the trustworthiness of divine promises. As proclaimed by the New Testament authors, these promises are quite strong; they contain, among other things, a promise of eternal salvation.[39] If not backed by the trustworthiness of divine infallibility, they are necessarily reduced to a pious hope with no assurance of ever being fulfilled. For Luther, this is totally unacceptable. Statements backed by divine infallibility are as infallible as their source. They therefore generate absolute and unshakable trust, which Luther calls assertio. He does not let his readers remain in doubt about its significance but declares: “If you take away the assertions, you have taken away Christianity.”[40]
However, this is not interpreted by Luther as determinism in the sense that the acts of humans are predetermined in detail.[41] If this were the case, divine decisions would merely be repeated in the area of the created through a kind of copy-and-paste mechanism, and the distinction between Creator and creation would be lost. The idea Luther employs to avoid this misunderstanding is the idea of divine–human cooperation. In applying this idea, he explicitly rejects Erasmus’s model, according to which what God does is added to what humans do to the effect that they together complete the work.[42] This destroys the asymmetry of the relation, as I already have shown.[43] According to Luther, God does everything, but he does this in such a way that the human still has a complete task to fulfil. God is fully responsible for the preservation of the ship, and the sailor is fully responsible for guiding it.[44] The human thus has relative independence within the area of the created despite God’s foreknowledge not being contingent upon the contribution of the human. The human is involved as a self-determining entity; God does not work in us without us.[45]
Luther applies this model in two different contexts, between which he finds an exact parallel.[46] Humans can do nothing to be created or to maintain their status of being created; both happen only through the power and goodness of the omnipotence of God, who creates and conserves us without us being in any way involved in this process.[47] In a strictly parallel way, humans are recreated in the kingdom of the Spirit, and once recreated, they are kept within this kingdom without any contribution from their part; this is solely the work of the Holy Spirit.[48] For Luther, any concession in the direction of an Erasmian, semi-Pelagian understanding of cooperation destroys the principle of divine unconditionality. Both creation and recreation are, however, done for the purpose of humans cooperating with God either in the world through God’s general omnipotence or in his kingdom through the power of the Holy Spirit.[49] God wants to have us as co-operators who openly proclaim what he whispers in our hearts.[50]
Humans thus repeat within the realm of the created what God does as the Lord of the created.[51] Humans are created to be lords themselves; they are created in the image of God and have for that reason a certain independence within the realm God has given them to lord over.[52] When this plays out as intended, humans do what is good;[53] the goodness God made manifest when he let the created world come into being is then repeated within the realm of the created by humans created in God’s own image. Human goodness is a reality, and it is patterned after the model of God’s own manifestation of his goodness in creation and recreation.[54] God is under no external obligation to do what is good; his loving goodness flows from his nature. In the same way, the repetition of divine goodness in humans can never be forced, and Luther therefore reacts strongly against any idea that would take us in that direction. The kind of necessity he is exploring is what he calls a necessity of immutability,[55] and this is what occurs when humans cannot but let the divinely induced attitude resonate in their lives.[56]
The distinction employed by Scholastic theology to align the unconditionality of divine action with the relative independence of the human subject is the distinction between necessitas consequentiae (logical necessity) and necessitas consequentis (factual necessity), where the latter is supposed to give some latitude for the human capacity for self-determination.[57] Luther is aware both of the distinction and recognizes the significance of the problem it is supposed to solve, but he still considers it confusing and misleading.[58] The reason is that this distinction takes us in the wrong direction, involving us in complicated and unhelpful discussions. What keeps theology on track here is in Luther’s view the conviction that what God wants always happens combined with trust that through the work of the Spirit, this overflowing goodness of divine presence is made manifest in the lives of the believers. An analysis that tries to divide responsibility between God and humans, or between primary and secondary causes, is therefore misguided, and – whether he is correct or not – it is Luther’s conviction that this is what Scholasticism does.[59] What he aims at emphasizing is that God does everything, and when the human is successfully aligned with God’s active goodness through the work of the Spirit, the human spontaneously and unforced manifests the same goodness.[60]
There is thus not a single step in the direction of a separated, disenchanted, and purely secular understanding of the world in Luther’s thought; on the contrary, he is at pains to reject Erasmus’s anthropocentric and secularized understanding of goodness by replacing it by a firmly theocentric one. Humans are created for the purpose of realizing divine–human cooperation and will only realize the idea of what it is to be human by emulating God’s way of dealing with the world from within the realm of the created.[61]
For Luther, this approach to the quest for God is the only one that is rationally consistent. The alternative, a God that is conditioned by the created or, which for Luther basically is the same thing, no God at all, is for Luther a man-made, and for that reason an arbitrary and incoherent, replacement. It is equal to creating one’s own God in the image of the human. Luther’s approach implies that the human experience of oneself as a (within limits) self-determining entity is rooted in the reality of humans being created in the likeness of God; it is an experience of what really is the case.
This leaves us with several unsolved questions: Why is this person recreated and not that person? Why does not God’s loving omnipotence overcome all opposition? How can divine foreknowledge be infallible when humans have a relative liberty to make their own choices? These questions do not worry Luther. The problem is partly solved by referring to the difference between God and humans (Why should humans aspire to know everything about God?),[62] partly by the distinction between the lights of nature, grace, and glory. The light of grace solves questions unsolvable by reason alone. In a similar way, the light of glory will also expand our knowledge, though the difference between God and creation will for ever remain in place.[63]
The one event that opens our eyes to the light of grace is the resurrection of Christ.[64] It is thus, even for Luther, in the person of Christ we have the main example of divine–human cooperation. Important as this is in Luther’s thinking, it is not unfolded in De servo arbitrio.[65] To fully grasp Luther’s understanding of divine–human cooperation, we therefore have to go to some of his other writings.
4 Luther’s Incarnational Worldview
The central doctrine of the Christian faith is the doctrine of the incarnation, according to which God lets himself be known by becoming a human (John 1:18). Human nature is thus qualified as the area for divine revelation in a way that allows for a more precise understanding of the relationship between God and human, and this possibility was not lost on Luther. According to the idea of communicatio idiomatum, the human nature of Christ participates in the predicates of the divine and vice versa.[66] This adds a new layer of credibility to the rejection of determinism; as the area of divine revelation, human nature participates in divine freedom and goodness. At the same time, this sets the life of Christ as the ideal for humans to emulate; as he loved his neighbours with divine love and infinite forgiveness, so should we (John 13:34; Matt 6:14).
What Luther wrote after 1519/20 is informed by this christologically founded worldview. Two good examples are De libertate Christiana from 1520 and Refutation of Latomus, usually called Anti-Latomus, from 1521. According to De libertate, a Christian is both a free lord over all things and a most dutiful servant of all.[67] As united with Christ, one is united with his victory over sin and death, but at the same time also with his loving service for all humans. Through the happy exchange,[68] one receives one’s identity from God and expresses it in the way one relates to others.[69] Luther finds this well expressed in Philippians 2. According to this passage, Christ did not need to do anything to be saved for his own part, but instead of demanding what was his right, he became one of us and served us as if this was something he needed. In this way, Christ achieves two things at the same time: He serves us by letting us receive what he has won for us as our servant, and in his loving service for others, he sets the model for us to emulate. As Christ served others in his incarnated manifestation, a Christian should be satisfied with the form of God he has obtained by faith while still increasing this faith until it is perfect[70] by taking upon himself the form of a servant. This is for Luther the fulfilment of the exhortation “Let this mind be in you, which was also in Christ Jesus” (Phil 2:5).[71]
In Anti-Latomus, this is expressed through the distinction between Christ as grace and gift.[72] The unconditionality of recreation is expressed through the understanding of Christ as pure grace; at the same time, however, one receives Christ as a gift who is united with the believer, who for that reason cannot fail to produce divine goodness in his or her life. Luther can here even use two nature Christology as a model for how grace is present in sinful humans, thus speaking of “impeccified grace” and “graced sin”[73] as a description of the “deified human.”[74] In the Preface to Romans, written about the same time as Anti-Latomus, the gift-aspect is expressed through Luther’s confidence that faith as God’s work in us cannot but incessantly do what is good.[75]
The application of Christology to the understanding of the human lets Luther identify the lack of the second aspect, the part of sanctification, as a kind of Nestorianism; it is an understanding of the human life that fails to apply the Chalcedonian doctrine of the inseparability of the divine and human nature of Christ correctly on the life of the Christian.[76] It is for Luther impossible to stay with a gospel of forgiveness alone; when receiving forgiveness, one is recreated into participation in Christ and thus placed in the world with the task of serving it with the gift of divine love.
This service even has a structure, which is explored by Luther precisely in a Christological context. In 1528, Luther wrote Vom Abendmahl Christi, where he rejects Zwingli’s and Oecolampadius’s spiritual understanding of Christ’s presence in the Lord’s Supper because of its Nestorian implications. Divine presence is not a spatially limited presence; it is God acting in creation.[77] To the refutation of the two, he adds a part where he explains his understanding of the Christian faith as faith in God the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. In the part concerning the confession of the faith in the Son, Luther gives the following interesting actualization: He rejects the doctrine of free will and the doctrine of old and new Pelagians who reject the doctrine of original sin. At the same time, he rejects those who have established vows and obligations like monastic orders and rules, which are human inventions with no biblical foundation;[78] they may still be kept, though, for the sake of educating the youth in the word of God. But the divinely instituted orders are only three: the office of the priesthood, marriage, and secular government. The first of these has to do with the task of preaching, administering the sacraments, supervising the common chest, etc. The second one is the task of maintaining one’s house and bringing up children.[79] The third one is defined as the obligation of obedience toward one’s superiors. These three tasks are founded on the word of God and are for that reason holy; they are “places in which God integrates human beings into God’s own story with humankind.”[80]
Scholasticism often explored anthropology according to the Aristotelian doctrine of the four causes. Thereby, the understanding of the final cause becomes particularly important, as it sets the goal human flourishing is supposed to fulfil.[81] Luther repeatedly uses the four causes-doctrine in a similar way, but he sceptical towards a purely rational approach to this problem.[82] The appropriate understanding of human existence must be based on the biblical uncovering of the all-determining power of divine presence,[83] and this is what in Luther’s view is done through the doctrine of the three orders or estates. In all of these, one is to serve with love, and the one who does so, with or without faith, is holy. But faith in Christ is the only way to be saved. Holiness is understood as works of love within the divinely instituted orders that follow from faith but can also to some extent be realized without faith.[84] God works in everybody irrespective of their attitude towards him.
The first two of these offices are taken straight from the story of the creation in Genesis 1 and 2. The office of the priesthood is prefigured in God declaring that the fruits of all trees in the garden are for the humans to eat as a sign that humans are made for an immortal and spiritual life.[85] The office of marriage reflects the will of God as expressed through the creation of humans as man and woman, thereby enabling them to procreate.[86] Priesthood and marriage thus give structure to the idea of humans as God’s co-operators participating in divine realities; they are to act as God did in creation. Differing from these, secular government is necessitated by the fall and for that reason does not reflect God’s goodness as clearly and directly as the other two.[87] What is to be avoided in this context is primarily secular government yielding to the temptation to stray into the spiritual, thus confusing both the goals and the means of the temporal and the spiritual.[88]
What Luther never does is to separate the secular and the spiritual in the sense that the latter does not inform the understanding of the former. Luther’s worldview is both theological and teleological in the sense that the life of humans is prefigured by God’s loving activity in creation and recreation as incarnated in the life and work of Jesus Christ. In Luther, there is no concession to the modern understanding of human liberty as the power to do what one wants to do as maintained by Erasmus and Locke.[89]
5 Conclusions
There is a certain emphasis on the exteriority of salvation in Luther. This is related to his strong emphasis both on divine omnipotence and on divine unconditionality. There is no distance between thought and action in God; what God knows is – or, from the point of view of temporal beings, will become – real. An entity dependent on the immanent web of causality is for Luther a part of creation, not a Creator. There is thus a strict difference between the Creator and the created in Luther’s thought.
God’s creative activity is what determines even what humans do. There is thus no anticipation in Luther of a modern and secular worldview where God does not have any role to play. This unconditionality of God’s creative activity is what sets the pattern for how humans should understand themselves. As caught up in divine unconditionality humans are called to emulate this unconditionality in their own lives. As loved by God, humans should love each other, inclusively and unconditionally. Luther’s emphasis on divine unconditionality and his rejection of any concession to the idea of the contingency and conditionality of divine action is thus accompanied by a parallel emphasis on the importance of humans following the divine pattern in their own lives.
The implication of this simultaneous emphasis on divine unconditionality both as a reality and as the goal of the lives of humans lets Luther emphasize a relative independence of human agency within the realm of infallible divine omnipotence. This relative independence of human agency is an implication of the humans being created in the image of God. For that reason, it is a manifestation of the humans’ inherent capacity for goodness; it can never be forced.[90]
The outcome of this simultaneous emphasis on absolute divine freedom and relative human freedom is a strong emphasis on divine unknowability. How the infallibility of divine foreknowledge and the omnipotence of divine love can be compatible with the relative freedom of human choice and the danger of human perdition is unknowable even with the light of grace. What will be the case with the light of glory, time will show.
After the fall, human nature’s potential for goodness is fully realized only in the person of Jesus Christ. It has always been the case that the realization of the truly human is conditioned upon its participation in the truly divine. The work of Christ through atonement and resurrection implies that this possibility has been re-established. The goal of his work of salvation is thus the restoration of divine–human cooperation as it existed before the fall. This sets the twin institutions of priesthood – the proclamation of divinely instituted unconditionality – and marriage, with its double emphasis on fecundity and intimacy, as the materialization of divine–human cooperation, with secular government added after the fall as a means of minimizing its effects. Living a loving life within the framework of these three estates, humans realize their inherent nature through their cooperation with their Creator.
There is thus no movement in the direction of a modern, secularized worldview in Luther’s thought. On the contrary, his worldview is strictly theological and Christocentric. In a world where teleology has disappeared and human freedom has been reduced to a pointless ability to choose for no other purpose than the choice itself, the time is ripe for a renewal of this perspective. Scholars who agree with this analysis should see Luther as an ally, not an opponent.
-
Funding information: APC has been covered by VID Specialized University.
-
Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.
References
Alfsvåg, Knut. Christology as Critique: On the Relation between Christ, Creation and Epistemology. Eugene: Wipf and Stock, 2018.Search in Google Scholar
Alfsvåg, Knut. “Impassibility and Revelation: On the Relation between Immanence and Economy in Orthodox and Lutheran Thought.” Studia Theologica 68 (2014), 169–83. 10.1080/0039338x.2014.957865.Search in Google Scholar
Alfsvåg, Knut. “Luther on Necessity.” Harvard Theological Review 108 (2015), 52–69.10.1017/S0017816015000036Search in Google Scholar
Alfsvåg, Knut. “Natural Theology and Natural Law in Martin Luther.” In The Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Martin Luther, edited by Derek Nelson and Paul Hinlicky. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.10.1093/acrefore/9780199340378.013.368Search in Google Scholar
Alfsvåg, Knut. What No Mind has Conceived: On the Significance of Christological Apophaticism. Studies in philosophical theology 45. Leuven, Paris, Walpole: Peeters, 2010.Search in Google Scholar
Bayer, Oswald. Martin Luther’s Theology: A Contemporary Interpretation. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 2008.Search in Google Scholar
Beintker, Horst. “Luthers Gotteserfahrung und Gottesanschauung.” In Leben und Werk Martin Luthers von 1526 bis 1546, edited by Helmar Junghans, 39–62. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1983.Search in Google Scholar
Berthoud, Jean-Marc. “Luther and Erasmus: The Central Confrontation of the Reformation.” Unio cum Christo 3 (2017), 65–81.10.35285/ucc3.1.2017.art4Search in Google Scholar
Dupré, Louis. Passage to Modernity: An Essay in the Hermeneutics of Nature and Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993.Search in Google Scholar
Ebeling, Gerhard. Lutherstudien II: Disputatio De homine 2: Die Philosophische Definition des Menschen. Tübingen: Mohr, 1982.Search in Google Scholar
Erasmus. Ausgewählte Schriften. 8 vols. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1967.Search in Google Scholar
Erasmus, Desiderius. Collected Works, translated by Peter Macardle and Clarence H. Miller. Vol. 76, Toronto, Buffalo, London: University of Toronto Press, 1999.Search in Google Scholar
From Conflict to Communion: Lutheran-Catholic Common Commemoration of the Reformation in 2017. Leipzig and Paderborn: Evangelische Verlagsanstalt, Bonifatius, 2013. https://lutheranworld.org/sites/default/files/From%20Conflict%20to%20Communion%20EN.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. Ancient Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.10.1017/CBO9780511801730Search in Google Scholar
Hampson, Margaret Daphne. Christian Contradictions: The Structures of Lutheran and Catholic Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.10.1017/CBO9780511487743Search in Google Scholar
Herman, Stewart W. “Embodying Confident Agency: Luther’s ‘Three Estates’ as a Resource for Virtue Theory.” Dialog: A Journal of Theology 56 (2017), 428–40. 10.1111/dial.12362.Search in Google Scholar
Herms, Eilert. “Opus Dei Gratiae: Cooperatio Dei et Hominum: Luthers Darstellung Seiner Rechtfertigungslehre in De Servo Arbitrio.” Lutherjahrbuch 78 (2011), 61–135.Search in Google Scholar
Holm, Bo Kristian. “Det Legemlige Promissio: Socialitet Som Nøgle til Luthers Nadverskrifter.” Dansk Teologisk Tidsskrift 86 (2023), 3–39.10.7146/dtt.v86i1.137461Search in Google Scholar
Hütter, Reinhard. “St. Thomas on Grace and Free Will in the Initium Fidei: The Surpassing Augustinian Synthesis.” Nova et Vetera 5 (2007), 521–54.Search in Google Scholar
Kolb, Robert. Bound Choice, Election, and Wittenberg Theological Method: From Martin Luther to the Formula of Concord. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans, 2005.Search in Google Scholar
Käfer, Anne. Inkarnation und Schöpfung: Schöpfungstheologische Voraussetzungen und Implikationen der Christologie bei Luther, Schleiermacher und Karl Barth. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2010.10.1515/9783110226348Search in Google Scholar
Landrum, Timothy Scott. Martin Luther’s Hidden God: Toward a Lutheran Apologetic for the Problem of Evil and Divine Hiddenness. Eugene, Oregon: Wipf & Stock, 2022.Search in Google Scholar
Luther, Martin. Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe. Weimar: H. Bühlau, 1883–1990.Search in Google Scholar
Luther, Martin. Works, edited by Helmut T. Lehmann and Jaroslav Pelikan. 55 vols. St. Louis: Concordia, 1958–1967.Search in Google Scholar
Lønning, Inge. “Gott VIII. Neuzeit/Systematisch-Theologisch.” In Theologische Realenzyklopädie 13, edited by Gerhard Müller, 668–708. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1984.Search in Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. 3rd ed. London: Bloomsbury, 2011.Search in Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. A Short History of Ethics. New York: Macmillian, 1966.10.4324/9780203267523Search in Google Scholar
Malysz, Piotr J. “Exchange and Ecstasy: Luther’s Eucharistic Theology in Light of Radical Orthodoxy’s Critique of Gift and Sacrifice.” Scottish Journal of Theology 60 (2007), 294–308. 10.1017/S0036930607003298.Search in Google Scholar
McSorley, Harry J. Luthers Lehre vom unfreien Willen nach seiner Hauptschrift De Servo Arbitrio im Lichte der biblischen und kirchlichen Tradition. München: Max Huebner Verlag, 1967.Search in Google Scholar
Milbank, John. “Reformation 500: Any Cause for Celebration?.” Open Theology 4 (2018), 607–29. 10.1515/opth-2018-0045.Search in Google Scholar
Plathow, Michael. “Das Cooperatio-Verständnis M. Luthers im Gnaden- und Schöpfungsbereich: Zur Frage nach dem Verhältnis von Mensch und Schöpfung.” Luther 56 (1985), 28–46.Search in Google Scholar
Pleines, Jürgen-Eckardt. “Teleologie.” In Theologische Realenzyklopädie XXXIIII, edited by Gerhard Müller, 36–41. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2002.Search in Google Scholar
Ruokanen, Miikka. Trinitarian Grace in Martin Luther’s The Bondage of the Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021.10.1093/oso/9780192895837.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Schindler, D. C. “The Crisis of Marriage as a Crisis of Meaning: On the Sterility of the Modern Will.” Communio 41 (2014), 331–71.Search in Google Scholar
Schindler, D. C. Freedom from Reality: The Diabolical Charachter of Modern Liberty. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2017.10.2307/j.ctvpg85wjSearch in Google Scholar
Schwanke, Johannes. “Luther’s Theology of Creation.” In The Oxford Handbook of Martin Luther’s Theology, edited by R. Kolb, I. Dingel, and L. Batka, 201–11. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.Search in Google Scholar
Skottene, Ragnar. Grace and Gift: An Analysis of a Central Motif in Martin Luther’s Rationis Latomianae Confutatio. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2008.Search in Google Scholar
Steiger, Johann Anselm. “The Communicatio Idiomatum as the Axle and Motor of Luther’s Theology.” Lutheran Quarterly 14 (2000), 125–58.Search in Google Scholar
Steiger, Johann Anselm. “Die Communicatio Idiomatum als Achse und Motor der Theologie Luthers: Der ‘fröhliche Wechsel’ als hermeneutischer Schlüssel zu Abendmahlslehre, Anthropologie, Seelsorge, Naturtheologie, Rhetorik und Humor.” Neue Zeitschrift für systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 38 (1996), 1–28. 10.1515/nzst.1996.38.1.1.Search in Google Scholar
Thiemann, Ronald F. “Sacaramental Realism: Martin Luther at the Dawn of Modernity.” In Lutherrenaissance Past and Present, edited by Christine Helmer and Bo Kristian Holm, 156–73. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2015.10.13109/9783666564154.156Search in Google Scholar
Vainio, Olli-Pekka. “Luther and Theosis: A Response to the Critics of Finnish Luther Research.” Pro Ecclesia 24 (2015), 459–74.10.1177/106385121502400406Search in Google Scholar
Vestrucci, Andrea. Theology as Freedom: On Martin Luther’s “De servo arbitrio”. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2019.Search in Google Scholar
Visala, Aku and Olli-Pekka Vainio. “Erasmus versus Luther: A Contemporary Analysis of the Debate on Free Will.” Neue Zeitschrift für systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 62 (2020), 311–35. 10.1515/nzsth-2020-0016.Search in Google Scholar
von-Wedel, Christine Christ. Erasmus of Rotterdam: Advocate of a New Christianity. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2013.10.3138/9781442665712Search in Google Scholar
Wendte, Martin. “Mystical Foundations of Politics? Luther on God’s Presence and the Place of Human Beings.” Studies in Christian Ethics 31 (2018), 422–34. 10.1177/0953946818792628.Search in Google Scholar
© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Topical issue: Political Theology and the State of Exception: Critical Readings on the Centenary of “Political Theology” and “Roman Catholicism and Political Form” by Carl Schmitt, edited by Guillermo Andrés Duque Silva
- With Schmitt, Against Schmitt, and Beyond Schmitt: Exception and Sovereign Decision to 100 Years of Political Theology I and Roman Catholicism and Political Form
- Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology of Revolution
- The Metaphysical Contention of Political Theology
- Secularism as Theopolitics: Jalāl ud-Dīn Akbar and the Theological Underpinnings of the State in South Asia
- Apophatic Confrontation: von Balthasar’s Thought on Kenosis and Community as a Veiled Response to the “Trend” of Political Theology
- Weak Decisionism and Political Polytheology: The Neutralization of Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology by Hans Blumenberg and the Ritter School
- Topical issue: Religion and Spirituality in Everyday Life, edited by Joana Bahia, Cecilia Bastos, and María Pilar García Bossio
- If You Have Faith, Exu Responds on-line: The Day-to-Day Life of Quimbanda on Social Networks
- Media and the Sacralization of Leaders and Events: The Construction of a Religious Public Sphere
- Exploring Twenty-First-Century Catholic Traditionalist Resistance Movement through Digital Cartoons of Pope Francis
- Contemporary Filiality and Popular Religion: An Ethnographic Study of Filiality Among Chinese University Students and their Parents
- Ritual Sweat Bath in a Cross-Cultural Perspective
- Regular Articles
- Naturalism Fails an Empirical Test: Darwin’s “Dangerous” Idea in Retrospect
- Talking about God from the Meaning of Life: Contributions from the Thought of Juan Antonio Estrada
- Symbolic Theology and Resistance in the Theology of Martin Luther King, Jr. and Paul Tillich
- Developing a Methodology for Hymnal Revision within a Contemporary, Multi-Ethnic Framework: A Proposal
- Development and Validation of Secularity Scale for Muslims
- God Does Not Work in Us Without Us: On the Understanding of Divine–Human Cooperation in the Thought of Martin Luther
Articles in the same Issue
- Topical issue: Political Theology and the State of Exception: Critical Readings on the Centenary of “Political Theology” and “Roman Catholicism and Political Form” by Carl Schmitt, edited by Guillermo Andrés Duque Silva
- With Schmitt, Against Schmitt, and Beyond Schmitt: Exception and Sovereign Decision to 100 Years of Political Theology I and Roman Catholicism and Political Form
- Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology of Revolution
- The Metaphysical Contention of Political Theology
- Secularism as Theopolitics: Jalāl ud-Dīn Akbar and the Theological Underpinnings of the State in South Asia
- Apophatic Confrontation: von Balthasar’s Thought on Kenosis and Community as a Veiled Response to the “Trend” of Political Theology
- Weak Decisionism and Political Polytheology: The Neutralization of Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology by Hans Blumenberg and the Ritter School
- Topical issue: Religion and Spirituality in Everyday Life, edited by Joana Bahia, Cecilia Bastos, and María Pilar García Bossio
- If You Have Faith, Exu Responds on-line: The Day-to-Day Life of Quimbanda on Social Networks
- Media and the Sacralization of Leaders and Events: The Construction of a Religious Public Sphere
- Exploring Twenty-First-Century Catholic Traditionalist Resistance Movement through Digital Cartoons of Pope Francis
- Contemporary Filiality and Popular Religion: An Ethnographic Study of Filiality Among Chinese University Students and their Parents
- Ritual Sweat Bath in a Cross-Cultural Perspective
- Regular Articles
- Naturalism Fails an Empirical Test: Darwin’s “Dangerous” Idea in Retrospect
- Talking about God from the Meaning of Life: Contributions from the Thought of Juan Antonio Estrada
- Symbolic Theology and Resistance in the Theology of Martin Luther King, Jr. and Paul Tillich
- Developing a Methodology for Hymnal Revision within a Contemporary, Multi-Ethnic Framework: A Proposal
- Development and Validation of Secularity Scale for Muslims
- God Does Not Work in Us Without Us: On the Understanding of Divine–Human Cooperation in the Thought of Martin Luther