Startseite Incentive Effects of Parents’ Transfers to Children: An Artefactual Field Experiment
Artikel
Lizenziert
Nicht lizenziert Erfordert eine Authentifizierung

Incentive Effects of Parents’ Transfers to Children: An Artefactual Field Experiment

  • A. Sinan Unur , Elizabeth Peters , Kent D. Messer EMAIL logo und William D. Schulze
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 11. April 2013

Abstract

The standard altruism model within the family predicts that transfers will be inversely related to the recipient’s income. Thus, parents will implicitly insure children against bad luck. This insurance may cause children to take undesirable risks. Anticipating this moral hazard, parents may alter their transfers. Using an artefactual field experiment, we show that parents use transfers to compensate for differences between their teenage children when incomes are independent of children’s actions. However, when a potential incentive problem is introduced, parents generally move away from compensating transfers. In addition, we find that the teenage children are more likely to take unfair bets when their behavior is not detectable by their parents.

JEL Classification Codes: D10; C92; D64

Acknowledgements

We gratefully acknowledge financial support from Bronfenbrenner Life Course Center at Cornell University, the Robinson Endowment, and through grants HD30944 and HD08382 from the National Institute of Child Health and Human Development. We thank the City of Ithaca School District and the Cornell Paw Print for their assistance with recruiting families. We are grateful to the families who participated in these experiments for their time. The experiments would not have been feasible without free software created by Rich Burridge at Sun Microsystems, the Apache Foundation, and Larry Wall and CPAN contributors. Our work has benefited from comments received from participants at the Economic Science Association Meetings, the Cornell University Department of Policy Analysis and Management Seminar Series and the University of Washington Economics Department Workshops. We are solely responsible for any errors and omissions.

Appendix – experiment instructions and screenshots

Sign on screen24

For children

For parents

Pure transfer stage instructions for children

Pure transfer stage instructions for parents

An example of information shown to children after the random income draw

Parent’s transfer decision screen

As the parent types in one field, the other automatically updates so both fields add up to $1.00. The fields are highlighted as shown below if the parent enters numbers that are out of bounds:

If she attempts to submit a decision that violates her budget constraint, she is shown an error message and asked to revise her decision:

If the parent’s transfer decision does not violate constraints, she is asked to confirm:

If the parent clicks No, she can go back and choose different numbers. If she clicks Yes, her decision is shown to all members of the family:

This process is repeated each period.

Betting practice instructions for children

Betting practice instructions for parents

Betting practice decisions for all participants

After making the choice, participants find out the outcome regardless of their choices:

Every period, all members of the family get the same amount and the outcome of the bet is the same for everyone as well. Since they find out the outcome of the bet regardless of their decisions, all family members get the same information about the nature of the bet.

Moral hazard stage instructions for Child A

Moral hazard stage instructions for Child B

Moral hazard stage instructions for parents

Child B’s decision screen in the moral hazard stage

Note that it is possible for Child B to get $0 as his income draw. He still needs to decide whether to bet. Once he makes his decision, he finds out the outcome of the bet:

Parent’s decision screen in the moral hazard stage

The rest of the family can then also see the incomes of the children and the parent can make her transfer decision:

References

Altonji, J. G., F.Hayashi, and l. J.Kotlikoff.1992. “Is the Extended Family Altruistically Linked Direct Tests Using Micro Data. American Economic Review82:117798.Suche in Google Scholar

Altonji, J. G., F.Hayashi, and l. J.Kotlikoff.1997. “Parental Altruism and Inter Vivos Transfers: Theory and Evidence”. Journal of Political Economy105:112166.10.1086/516388Suche in Google Scholar

Becker, G. S.1991. A Treatise on the Family. Enlarged edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Bergstrom, T. C.1999. “Systems of Benevolent Utility Functions”. Journal of Public Economic Theory1:71100.10.1111/1097-3923.00004Suche in Google Scholar

Bernheim, B., and S.Severinov.2003. “Bequests as Signals: An Explanation for the Equal Division Puzzle”. Journal of Political Economy111:73364.10.1086/375383Suche in Google Scholar

Bernheim, B. D., A.Schleifer, and L. H.Summers. 1985. “The Strategic Bequest Motive”. Journal of Political Economy93:104576.10.1086/261351Suche in Google Scholar

Bruce, N., and M.Waldman.1990. “The Rotten Kid Theorem Meets the Samaritan’s Dilemma”. Quarterly Journal of Economics105:15565.10.2307/2937823Suche in Google Scholar

Bruce, N., and M.Waldman.1991. “Transfers in Kind: Why They can be Efficient and Non-paternalistic.American Economic Review81:134551.Suche in Google Scholar

Cox, D.1987. “Motives for Private Income Transfers”. Journal of Political Economy95(3):50846.10.1086/261470Suche in Google Scholar

Fields, J., and L. M.Casper.2001. “America’s Families and Living Arrangements: March 2000. Current Population Reports, P20–537.”http://www.census.gov/prod/2001pubs/p20-537.pdf.Suche in Google Scholar

Harbaugh, W., and K.Krause.2000. “Children’s Altruism in Public Good and Dictator Experiments”. Economic Inquiry38:95109.10.1111/j.1465-7295.2000.tb00006.xSuche in Google Scholar

Harbaugh, W., K.Krause, and T.Berry.2007. “GARP for Kids: On the Development of Rational Choice Behavior. In Recent Developments in Behavioral Economics, edited by M.Shlomo,11319. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.Suche in Google Scholar

Harbaugh, W., K.Krause, and L.Vesterlund.2001. “Are Adults Better Behaved Than Children? Age, Experience, and the Endowment Effect”. Economics Letters70:17581.10.1016/S0165-1765(00)00359-1Suche in Google Scholar

Kanter, C., K. D.Messer, and H. M.Kaiser.2009. “Does Production Labeling Stigmatize Conventional Milk?American Journal of Agricultural Economics91(4):1097109.10.1111/j.1467-8276.2009.01317.xSuche in Google Scholar

List, J. A., and G. W.Harrison.2004. “Field Experiments”. Journal of Economic Literature42:100955.10.1257/0022051043004577Suche in Google Scholar

Light, A., and K.Mcgarry.2004. “Why Parents Play Favorites: Explanations for Unequal Bequests”. American Economic Review94:166981.10.1257/0002828043052321Suche in Google Scholar

Mcclelland, G., W.Schulze, and D.Coursey.1993. “Insurance for Low Probability Hazards: A Bimodal Response to Unlikely Events”. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty7:95116.10.1007/BF01065317Suche in Google Scholar

Mcgarry, K., and R.Schoeni.1995. “Transfer Behavior in the Health and Retirement Study: Measurement and the Redistribution of Resources within the Family”. Journal of Human Resources30:S184226.10.2307/146283Suche in Google Scholar

Menchik, P. L.1980. “Primogeniture, Equal Sharing and the U.S. Distribution of Wealth”. Quarterly Journal of Economics94:299316.10.2307/1884542Suche in Google Scholar

Pemberton, J.1996.“A Model of Family Fairness and Its Implications for Debt Neutrality”. Economic Inquiry34:24959.10.1111/j.1465-7295.1996.tb01376.xSuche in Google Scholar

Peters, H., A.Unur, J.Clark, and W.Schulze.2004. “Free-Riding and the Provision of Public Goods in the Family: A Laboratory Experiment”. International Economic Review45:28399.10.1111/j.1468-2354.2004.00126.xSuche in Google Scholar

Rabin, M.2000. “Risk Aversion and Expected Utility: A Calibration Theorem”. Econometrica68:128192.10.1111/1468-0262.00158Suche in Google Scholar

Rosenzweig, M. R., and K. I.Wolpin.1993. “Intergenerational Support and the Life-Cycle Incomes of Young Men and Their Parents: Human Capital Investments, Coresidence and Intergenerational Financial Transfers”. Journal of Labor Economics11:84112.10.1086/298318Suche in Google Scholar

Snedecor, G., and W.Cochran.1989. Statistical Methods. Iowa: Iowa State University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Stark,O.1995. Altruism and Beyond: An Economic Analysis of Transfers and Exchanges within Families and Groups. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511493607Suche in Google Scholar

Tomes, N.1981.“The Family, Inheritance and the Intergenerational Transmission of Inequality. Journal of Political Economy89:92858.10.1086/261014Suche in Google Scholar

U.S. Census Bureau. 2001a. “Table F1. Family Households, by Type, Age of Own Children, Age of Family Members, and Age, Race and Hispanic Origin of Householder: March 2000.http://www.census.gov/population/socdemo/hh-fam/p20-537/2000/tabF1.txt.Suche in Google Scholar

U.S. Census Bureau. 2001b. “Table FG7. Family Groups by Family Type, Sex, and Race and Hispanic Origin of Reference Person: March 2000.http://www.census.gov/population/socdemo/hh-fam/p20-537/2000/tabFG7.txt.Suche in Google Scholar

U.S. Census Bureau. 2001c. “Table ST-F1–2000. Average Number of Children Per Family and Per Family With Children, by State: March 2000.http://www.census.gov/population/socdemo/hh-fam/tabST-F1-2000.csv.Suche in Google Scholar

  1. 1

    Note that primogeniture (the law or custom for the firstborn to inherit all of the parent’s assets) would also accomplish the same result as would any other constant division rule.

  2. 2

    As Rosenzweig and Wolpin (1993) show, focusing solely on financial transfers misses the important effects that in-kind transfers and shared living arrangements can have on an individual’s well-being.

  3. 3

    Pemberton (1996) proposes that the prevalence of equal giving can be explained by par­ents’ preference to give equally. This argument, however, comes close to assuming its own conclusion. Bernheim and Severinov (2003) propose a model where children view parents’ transfers as signaling parents’ affection for them to explain equal division of bequests as well as unequal division of inter-vivos transfers. Light and McGarry (2004) contend that proxies for altruistic exchange and evolutionary motives all significantly increase the probability of unequal bequests.

  4. 4

    These experiments did not control for family structure or composition. For expositional consistency, we use the female pronoun when referring to the parent and the male pronoun when referring to the children.

  5. 5

    The participants in this experiment are family members who have an ongoing relationship. Accordingly, even the up-to $100 payout involved in the experiment are very small relative to the life-time incomes of the participants’ children. The curvatures of the utility functions involved are not likely to play a significant role in determining children’s’ preferences over various outcomes with respect to the uncertainty we introduce (see McClelland, Schulze, and Coursey 1993, Rabin 2000). Therefore, when looking at when it might pay for Child B to bet, we will compare expected payoffs rather than expected utility to make the analysis simpler.

  6. 6

    Bernheim and Severinov (2003) show that equal division may emerge as a social norm if parents’ transfers signal their affection to the children.

  7. 7

    During the actual experiments, the stages were identified by number only.

  8. 8

    See the Appendix for complete experimental instructions and screenshot of the computer interface.

  9. 9

    The parent’s transfer can be any amount in one cent increments up to $1. To facilitate the parent’s decision-making process and to ensure that the transfers to the two children summed up to $1, the computer software automatically updated the remaining amount to be given to the other child as the parent entered the transfer for one child. After submitting their decisions, parents were presented with a confirmation screen which again displayed both the transfer amounts and the pre-and post-transfer period incomes implied by their decisions. At that point, parents could either confirm their decisions or go back and edit their decisions until they were satisfied. Upon the parent’s confirmation of the transfer decision, the software displayed the outcomes to all members of the family.

  10. 10

    In the first eight sessions, there were five actual decision periods following practice. In all other sessions, there were 10 actual periods in the pure transfer stage.

  11. 11

    While we do not claim that the incentive problem used in this experiment has an exact analogue in real life, the design is intended to capture the idea that there are choices that parents would prefer their children not make, and they cannot observe whether their children’s outcomes were due to bad choices or bad luck. The fact that parents‘behavior changes in this setting with such relatively small stake suggests that parents are sensitive to these issues and thus would likely change their behavior in higher stakes settings.

  12. 12

    In one-child families there could be other somewhat credible beneficiaries such as more distant relatives, friends or charitable organizations. However, as Bernheim, Schleifer and Summers (1985) point out, the task of credibly committing to not giving to the sole child is considerably more difficult than situations where the parent has multiple children.

  13. 13

    We expect children in the experiment to have some familiarity with the notion of probabilities because the topic is introduced in the fourth grade and covered in state exams.

  14. 14

    In the first 20 sessions, a brief “cheap talk” break in the middle of the moral hazard stage was introduced. During the break, families were allowed to talk about anything they wanted in private for up to five minutes. Since participants were not told about this break in advance, in this analysis, we only use the data from periods before the cheap talk break was announced because there are too few post-cheap talk periods.

  15. 15

    Recruiting university staff increased the diversity of the sample as approximately 80% of the parents recruited through the school district had a college degree, while when the latter sample is included, this proportion falls to 66%. Similarly, 85% of the parents from the school district recruitment were married and that percentage dropped to 76% when university staff were included.

  16. 16

    Specifically, parents may try to behave in what they think would make the researchers think of them as “good parents”.

  17. 17

    This analysis assumes that if parents are compensating in their transfer behavior, they are doing so on a period-by-period basis. In addition, period-by-period decisions may be cognitively easier for parents. However, parents might follow a strategy of trying to equalize the cumulative sum of children’s post-transfer period incomes. To check for this possibility, we constructed vectors of implied transfers under the assumption of cumulative compensating behavior. The fit was worse than both the period-by-period compensation and equal division hypotheses.

  18. 18

    We recognize that there is the possibility of parents undoing the effects of their transfers outside the laboratory. However, this type of behavior makes little sense in the context of our design, because parents have the tools within the experiment itself to discourage inefficient behavior by making transfers independent of children’s observed incomes. A post-experiment survey of families in the second recruitment wave asked questions regarding post-experiment activities, and 95.8% of the parents reported that they did not redistribute their children’s incomes after the experiment. The only family deviating from this pattern decided to pool their money to buy new electronic equipment to share in their home.

  19. 19

    A random effects model is an appropriate way to account for the possibility of unobservables that are specific to each family. The random effects model assumes that the unobservables are uncorrelated with the covariates, and this is satisfied, because the covariates are constructed as a function of the exogenous random draw.

  20. 20

    In addition to the random effects model shown in Table 3, we also ran fixed-effects and OLS models. The estimated coefficients were stable across various models. Using the standard Lagrange multiplier test of the classical regression model versus fixed/random effects models, the classical regression model was not rejected. These results are available by request.

  21. 21

    We also ran a model where the predictor was constructed by assuming the parents were trying to equalize the cumulative sum of post-transfer incomes of the children. Given the randomness in children’s pre-transfer incomes, it is not clear if playing catch up in this way is a more effective way of equalizing the sum of the children’s incomes than compensating for differences in each period. In any case, the analogue of the joint restriction above in this case was rejected in both stages.

  22. 22

    Clearly, this is not an exhaustive enumeration of all possible signals parents can infer from children’s observed incomes. However, it does constitute a very transparent partitioning of signals.

  23. 23

    Given that situations where a bet would not have revealed their decisions were those where children’s random draws were relatively small, one possible way to interpret this is that children exhibit some sort of loss aversion or risk aversion for small stakes (see Rabin 2000 for additional information about this type of behavior).

  24. 24

    Participants were asked to enter their first names so that the computer could correctly display information about family members using their names rather than random sequences. The names entered were only stored only during the session and not saved with the experiment data. The group identifier was always a randomly selected four digit integer.

Published Online: 2013-04-11
Published in Print: 2013-07-01

©2013 by Walter de Gruyter Berlin / Boston

Heruntergeladen am 22.9.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/bejeap-2012-0001/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen