Abstract
Isocrates is usually excluded from histories of philosophy. Two likely reasons are his tendency not to formulate rigorously structured arguments and his tendency not to deploy such arguments in support of universalizing positions that he takes – for example, about virtue or the good life. Nonetheless, Isocrates does come close to performing these functions, typical of what we expect from philosophers today, in Against the Sophists, written in the late 390s. In this work Isocrates criticizes, among others, educators who, he says, ‘involve themselves in disputations’. It is clear that these include followers of Socrates – at the least, Antisthenes and perhaps Plato. The disputers, Isocrates says, claim to teach a knowledge, ἐπιστήμη, that tells us what to do and thereby guarantees happiness. Against this claim, Isocrates does formulate a structured argument in service of universalizing claims, viz., his argument from Foreknowledge. He argues that the disputers’ purported knowledge requires that we foreknow outcomes of the actions about which we deliberate, if we are to attain happiness as promised. But humans do not have foreknowledge. Therefore, the disputers’ claims are false, and the cognitive attitude that we need for a happy life is not knowledge. Isocrates does not invent his rivals’ Foreknowledge premise, for Antisthenes, Plato and Xenophon present versions of it. As I ‘steelman’ and analyze Isocrates’ Foreknowledge argument, I find it sound if happiness consists in enjoying external goods, as in some Socratic dialogues, but not sound if genuine happiness is immune to fortune, as later in Plato and certain works of Antisthenes. I argue for dating those Antisthenic works later than Against the Sophists. Although certainty is elusive, it is attractive to think that Isocrates’ Foreknowledge argument played some role in pushing Plato, and perhaps Antisthenes, to seek to inoculate happiness and the good against fortune and to bring the virtuous one close to the divine.
References
Böhme, P. 2009. Isokrates. Gegen die Sophisten. Ein Kommentar. Berlin: W. Hopf.Suche in Google Scholar
Brancacci, A. 1992. “Struttura compositiva e fonti della terza orazione ‘Sulla regalità’ di Dione Crisostomo: Dione e l’‘Archelao’ di Antistene.” Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II 36 (5): 3308–34.10.1515/9783110857023-003Suche in Google Scholar
Brancacci, A. 2010. “Sull’ etica di Antistene.” In Socratica 2008. Studies in Ancient Socratic Literature, edited by L. Rossetti, and A. Stavru, 89–117. Bari: Levante.Suche in Google Scholar
Brancacci, A. 2019. “L’elogio Dell’ Isocrate Nel Fedro.” La Cultura 57: 289–319.Suche in Google Scholar
Conterno, M. 2014. “Temistio Orientale.” In Orazioni temistiane nella tradizione siriaca e araba. Brescia: Paideia Editrice.Suche in Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1999. Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691223261Suche in Google Scholar
Decleva Caizzi, F. 1966. Antisthenis Fragmenta. Milan: Istituto editoriale cisalpino.Suche in Google Scholar
Depew, D. 2004. “The Inscription of Isocrates into Aristotle’s Practical Philosophy.” In Isocrates and Civic Education, edited by T. Poulakos, and D. Depew, 157–85. Austin: University of Texas Press.10.7560/702196-009Suche in Google Scholar
Dorion, L. 2013. “L’autre Socrate.” In Études sur les écrits socratiques de Xénophon. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.10.14375/NP.9782251420493Suche in Google Scholar
Dorion, L. 2018. “Enkrateia et partition de l’âme chez Platon.” Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 36: 153–214, https://doi.org/10.3917/rpha.362.0153.Suche in Google Scholar
Ferejohn, M. 1984. “Socratic Thought-Experiments and the Unity of Virtue Paradox.” Phronesis 29: 105–22, https://doi.org/10.1163/156852884x00102.Suche in Google Scholar
Giannantoni, G. 1990. Socratis et socraticorum reliquiae (= SSR), 4 vols. Naples: Bibliopolis.Suche in Google Scholar
Kraus, M. 2006. “Antilogia—Zu Den Grundlagen Sophistischer Debattierkunst.” Rhetorik 25: 1–13.Suche in Google Scholar
Lachance, G. 2020. “Was Plato an Eristic According to Isocrates?” Apeiron 53: 81–96. https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2018-0090.Suche in Google Scholar
Mann, J. 2008. “Prediction, Precision, and Practical Experience: the Hippocratics on Technē.” Apeiron 41: 89–122. https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron.2008.41.2.89.Suche in Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2021. Plato’s Epistemology. Being and Seeming. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780198867401.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar
Murphy, D. 2013. “Isocrates and the Dialogue.” Classical World 106: 311–53. https://doi.org/10.1353/clw.2013.0048.Suche in Google Scholar
Murphy, D. 2018. “Isocrates as a Reader of Socratic Dialogues.” In Socrates and the Socratic Dialogue, edited by A. Stavru, and C. Moore, 105–24. Leiden: Brill.10.1163/9789004341227_006Suche in Google Scholar
Murphy, D. 2022. “Περιτροπή, or Reversal, Arguments from Antiphon and Socrates.” In Socrates and the Socratic Philosophies. Selected Papers from Socratica IV, edited by C. Mársico, 35–50. Baden-Baden: Academia Verlag.10.5771/9783985720057-35Suche in Google Scholar
Nestle, W. 1911. “Spuren der Sophistik bei Isokrates.” Philologus N.F. 24: 1–51.10.1524/phil.1911.70.14.1Suche in Google Scholar
Penner, T. 2011. “Socratic Ethics and the Socratic Psychology of Action. A Philosophical Framework.” In The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, edited by D. Morrison, 260–92. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CCOL9780521833424.012Suche in Google Scholar
Pohlenz, M. 1913. Aus Platos Werdezeit. Berlin: Weidmann.Suche in Google Scholar
Prince, S. 2015. Antisthenes of Athens. Texts, Translations, and Commentary. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.10.3998/mpub.5730060Suche in Google Scholar
Rigolio, A. 2019. Themistius: On Virtue. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Suche in Google Scholar
Rossetti, L. 1980. “Ricerche sui ‘Dialoghi Socratici’ di Fedone e di Euclide.” Hermes 108: 183–200.Suche in Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1909. “Φύσις, Μελέτη, Ἐπιστήμη.” Transactions of the American Philological Association 40: 183–5.10.2307/282631Suche in Google Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. 2006. “Reasoning with the Irrational: Moral Psychology in the Protagoras.” Ancient Philosophy 26: 243–58. https://doi.org/10.5840/ancientphil20062621.Suche in Google Scholar
Smith, N. 2021. Socrates on Self-improvement: Knowledge, Virtue, and Happiness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781009025959Suche in Google Scholar
Steidle, W. 1950. “Der Dialog Laches und Platons Verhältnis zu Athen in den Frühdialogen.” MH 7: 129–46.Suche in Google Scholar
Suvák, V. 2014. “Antisthenes between Diogenes and Socrates.” In Antisthenica Cynica Socratica, edited by V. Suvák, 72–120. Prague. ΟΙΚΟΥΜΕΝΗ.Suche in Google Scholar
Viidebaum, L. 2021. Creating the Ancient Rhetorical Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781108873956Suche in Google Scholar
Wareh, T. 2012. The Theory and Practice of Life. Isocrates and the Philosophers. Washington: Center for Hellenic Studies.Suche in Google Scholar
© 2025 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Frontmatter
- Anaximander Without the Apeiron: Making Sense of Aristotle’s and Theophrastusʼ Reports
- Knowledge of the Future and Knowledge of the Good: Isocrates and the Heirs of Socrates
- Being Per Se and Categorical Predication
- The Visibility of the Aorta. Anatomical Ideas Behind an Ancient Etymology (Aristotle, Historia Animalium, 3, 513a)
- Tragic Pharmacy: The ‘Noble’ Lie and the Fall of Kallipolis
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Frontmatter
- Anaximander Without the Apeiron: Making Sense of Aristotle’s and Theophrastusʼ Reports
- Knowledge of the Future and Knowledge of the Good: Isocrates and the Heirs of Socrates
- Being Per Se and Categorical Predication
- The Visibility of the Aorta. Anatomical Ideas Behind an Ancient Etymology (Aristotle, Historia Animalium, 3, 513a)
- Tragic Pharmacy: The ‘Noble’ Lie and the Fall of Kallipolis