Kapitel
Lizenziert
Nicht lizenziert Erfordert eine Authentifizierung

Seneca: Knowledge of Self and Nature

  • Gudrun Holtz
Veröffentlichen auch Sie bei De Gruyter Brill
Know Yourself
Ein Kapitel aus dem Buch Know Yourself

Abstract

Knowledge of self is at the heart of Seneca’s philosophical work. Yet, he cites the Delphic maxim only twice. Self-knowledge in Seneca thus is not derived from the maxim but from the Stoic self-understanding of what philosophy is, namely “wisdom of things divine and human.” In one of the rewordings of this definition, he puts it in terms of “knowledge of self and nature.” Since both aspects are intrinsically related, they circumscribe the scope of the present paper. After a general introduction (1), a sketch of Seneca’s philosophical project concerning “knowing oneself” is given (2). Subsequently, I discuss those two passages in which this maxim is quoted. In contrast to other interpreters, for him, knowing oneself in the first-place means knowing oneself to be mortal. Furthermore, it will be argued that this maxim is of minor importance in his work because, for him, its proper place is popular philosophy and not philosophy in the sense of the Stoic definition of this concept, to which he is indebted (3). In section 4, the question is raised how a person can achieve knowledge of self. It will be shown that for Seneca, knowing oneself is not in the first place an intellectual endeavor, but an eminently practical one that is gained through self-examination. In the process, at least two persons are involved: the philosopher as teacher and mental guide or therapist and the person who is in need of therapy of emotions or passions. There is an objective side to knowing oneself and a subjective one. To different degrees, they are present in both the instructor and the person in need of instruction. In section 5, I ask why Seneca defines knowing oneself in terms of knowing oneself to be mortal. I argue that, for him, being conscious of one’s mortality is the key to a happy life, that is, ethically, existentially, and religiously. With transcendence pointing to the philosophical realm of physics dealing with nature, section 6 at first explains Seneca’s reasoning for the unity of knowledge of self and nature. Then, content and benefits of knowledge of self and nature are discussed. Whereas the former is concerned with ethics in terms of eradicating passions like anger and fear in order to become one’s own person, the latter leads to transcending the limitations of ethics and becoming free from oneself and entering into partnership with the gods and knowing them. In section 7 a summary follows.

Abstract

Knowledge of self is at the heart of Seneca’s philosophical work. Yet, he cites the Delphic maxim only twice. Self-knowledge in Seneca thus is not derived from the maxim but from the Stoic self-understanding of what philosophy is, namely “wisdom of things divine and human.” In one of the rewordings of this definition, he puts it in terms of “knowledge of self and nature.” Since both aspects are intrinsically related, they circumscribe the scope of the present paper. After a general introduction (1), a sketch of Seneca’s philosophical project concerning “knowing oneself” is given (2). Subsequently, I discuss those two passages in which this maxim is quoted. In contrast to other interpreters, for him, knowing oneself in the first-place means knowing oneself to be mortal. Furthermore, it will be argued that this maxim is of minor importance in his work because, for him, its proper place is popular philosophy and not philosophy in the sense of the Stoic definition of this concept, to which he is indebted (3). In section 4, the question is raised how a person can achieve knowledge of self. It will be shown that for Seneca, knowing oneself is not in the first place an intellectual endeavor, but an eminently practical one that is gained through self-examination. In the process, at least two persons are involved: the philosopher as teacher and mental guide or therapist and the person who is in need of therapy of emotions or passions. There is an objective side to knowing oneself and a subjective one. To different degrees, they are present in both the instructor and the person in need of instruction. In section 5, I ask why Seneca defines knowing oneself in terms of knowing oneself to be mortal. I argue that, for him, being conscious of one’s mortality is the key to a happy life, that is, ethically, existentially, and religiously. With transcendence pointing to the philosophical realm of physics dealing with nature, section 6 at first explains Seneca’s reasoning for the unity of knowledge of self and nature. Then, content and benefits of knowledge of self and nature are discussed. Whereas the former is concerned with ethics in terms of eradicating passions like anger and fear in order to become one’s own person, the latter leads to transcending the limitations of ethics and becoming free from oneself and entering into partnership with the gods and knowing them. In section 7 a summary follows.

Kapitel in diesem Buch

  1. Frontmatter I
  2. Foreword V
  3. Contents VII
  4. Part 1: Introductory Chapters
  5. The Delphic Maxim Interpreted: Aims, Scope, and Significance of the Present Study 1
  6. Ancient Self-Knowledge: Exploring Some of the Scholarly Debates 21
  7. Interpretations and Echoes of the Delphic Maxim in Pre-Christian Greek Philosophy 55
  8. “Know Your Text”: the Integrity and Interpretation of Alcibiades m. 133c8–17 85
  9. Part 2: Main Chapters
  10. Philo of Alexandria and the Transitory and Apophatic Dimensions of Knowing Oneself 125
  11. Seneca: Knowledge of Self and Nature 159
  12. Plutarch: Know God and Know Yourself 211
  13. Know Your Exceptionality. The Delphic Maxim Know Yourself in Epictetus 231
  14. Between Self-Knowledge and Self-Enjoyment: ΓΝѠθΙ ϹAYTON in the Skeleton Mosaic from beneath the Monastery of San Gregorio 269
  15. Self-Knowledge as Alienation and Unification in the Hermetica 293
  16. Self-Knowledge and the Hidden Kingdom: The Delphic Maxim in the Manuscripts of Gos. Thom. 3 319
  17. What does it Mean to be Human? The Delphic Maxim in Irenaeus 337
  18. Know Yourself in Clement of Alexandria: Self-Knowledge, God-Knowledge and the Transformation of Self 365
  19. When Mortals Become Sinners: Tertullian Grappling with the Delphic Maxim 385
  20. A Maxim of Greek Philosophy Found in Scripture: “Know Yourself” in Origen and Reflections in Gregory of Nyssa 423
  21. Jesus Knowing Himself: Origen and the Gospel of John 473
  22. Plotinus on the Delphic Maxim: Knowing and Being One’s True Self 505
  23. Knowing Yourself as an Essential Part of Origen’s Teaching According to Gregory Thaumaturgus 527
  24. Forged in the Community of Divine Love: Augustine’s Quest through the Maxim of Self-Knowledge for Finite Wholeness within the Infinite God 569
  25. Author Index 595
  26. Index of biblical and classical sources 603
Heruntergeladen am 3.10.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783111083858-006/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen