Startseite The Limits of Behavioral Economics in Tort Law
Artikel
Lizenziert
Nicht lizenziert Erfordert eine Authentifizierung

The Limits of Behavioral Economics in Tort Law

  • Daniel Pi EMAIL logo
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 17. November 2021
Veröffentlichen auch Sie bei De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

Skeptics of rational choice theory have long predicted that behavioral economics would radically transform the legislation, adjudication, and analysis of law. Using tort law as an exemplar, this Article maps out the narrow set of conditions where substantive law can be modified to accommodate irrational decision-makers. Specifically, this Article demonstrates that if injurers are systematically biased, and the due care standard can be expressed quantitatively, and victims are unable to take meaningful precautions, then imposing punitive damages can induce irrational injurers to exercise efficient precautionary care. In all other cases, it is better that the law adopt a presumption of rationality, regardless whether individuals behave rationally in fact.

JEL Codes: D03; K13

Corresponding author: Daniel Pi, University of Maine, School of Law, 246 Deering Ave., Portland, ME 04101, USA, E-mail:

References

Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risqué: critique des postulats et axioms de l’école Américaine. Econometrica 21: 503–546. https://doi.org/10.2307/1907921.Suche in Google Scholar

Becker, G.S. (1962). Irrational behavior and economic theory. J. Polit. Econ. 70: 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1086/258584.Suche in Google Scholar

Brown, J. (1973). Toward an economic theory of liability. J. Leg. Stud. 2: 323–349. https://doi.org/10.1086/467501.Suche in Google Scholar

Camerer, C.F. and Loewenstein, G. (2004). Behavioral economics: past, present, future. In: Camerer, C.F., Loewenstein, G., and Rabin, M. (Eds.), Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.10.2307/j.ctvcm4j8j.6Suche in Google Scholar

Cohen, L.R. (2001). The lure of the lottery. Wake For. Law Rev. 36: 705–745.Suche in Google Scholar

Cooter, R. (1985). Unity in tort, contract, and property: the model of precaution. Calif. Law Rev. 73: 1–51.10.2307/3480463Suche in Google Scholar

Cooter, R. and Ulen, T.S. (2012). Law and economics, 6th ed. Boston, MA: Addison-Wesley.Suche in Google Scholar

Dari-Mattiacci, G. and Mangan, B.M. (2008). Disappearing defendants versus judgment-proof injurers. Econometrica 75: 749–765. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0335.2007.00663.x.Suche in Google Scholar

Dari-Mattiacci, G. and Parisi, F. (2013). Liability rules: an economic taxonomy. In: Bussani, M. and Sebok, A.J. (Eds.), Comparative tort law: global perspectives. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.Suche in Google Scholar

Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk ambiguity and the savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 75: 643–669. https://doi.org/10.2307/1884324.Suche in Google Scholar

Glazier, A. and Mone, T. (2019). Success of opt-in organ donation policy in the United States. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 322: 719–720. https://doi.org/10.1001/jama.2019.9187.Suche in Google Scholar

Hicks, J.R. (1956). A Revision of demand theory. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Hill, C.A. (2011). A positive agenda for behavioral law and economics. Cognitive Critique 3: 85–92.Suche in Google Scholar

Jolls, C. (2007). Behavioral law and economics. In: Diamond, P. and Vartiainen, H. (Eds.), Behavioral economics and its applications. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.10.3386/w12879Suche in Google Scholar

Jolls, C., Sunstein, C.R., and Thaler, R. (1998). A behavioral approach to law and economics. Stanford Law Rev. 50: 1471–1550. https://doi.org/10.2307/1229304.Suche in Google Scholar

Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Suche in Google Scholar

Korobkin, R. (2011). What comes after victory for behavioral law and economics? Univ. Ill. Law Rev. 2011: 1653–1674.Suche in Google Scholar

Korobkin, R. and Ulen, T. (2000). Law and behavioral science: removing the rationality assumption from law and economics. Calif. Law Rev. 88: 1051–1144. https://doi.org/10.2307/3481255.Suche in Google Scholar

Kuhn, T.S. (2012). The structure of scientific revolutions, 4th ed. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226458144.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar

Little, I.M.D. (1949). A reformulation of the theory of consumer’s behaviour. Oxf. Econ. Pap. 1: 90–99. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordjournals.oep.a041063.Suche in Google Scholar

Luppi, B. and Parisi, F. (2016). Optimal liability for optimistic tortfeasors. Eur. J. Law Econ. 41: 559–574. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-016-9523-6.Suche in Google Scholar

Luppi, B. and Parisi, F. (2018). Behavioral models in tort law. In: Teitelbaum, J.C. and Zeiler, K. (Eds.), Research handbook on behavioral law and economics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.10.4337/9781849805681.00017Suche in Google Scholar

Markham, F. and Young, M. (2015). ‘Big gambling’: the rise of the global industry-state gambling complex. Addiction Res. Theor. 23: 1–11. https://doi.org/10.3109/16066359.2014.929118.Suche in Google Scholar

Pi, D. (2019). Meta-rational choice. In: Essays in law and economics, Doctoral dissertation, Available at: http://amsdottorato.unibo.it/8753/1/Pi_Daniel_tesi.pdf.Suche in Google Scholar

Polinsky, M.A. (1980). Strict liability vs. negligence in a market setting. Am. Econ. Rev. 70: 363–367.10.4324/9781315188133-6Suche in Google Scholar

Posner, R.A. (1997). Rational choice, behavioral economics, and the law. Stanford Law Rev. 50: 1551–1575.10.2307/1229305Suche in Google Scholar

Samuelson, P.A. (1938). A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behavior. Econometrica 5: 61–71. https://doi.org/10.2307/2548836.Suche in Google Scholar

Schmitz, D. (2009). Reasons for altruism. Soc. Philos. Pol. 10: 52–68.10.1017/S0265052500004015Suche in Google Scholar

Shavell, S. (1980). Strict liability versus negligence. J. Leg. Stud. 9: 1–25. https://doi.org/10.1086/467626.Suche in Google Scholar

Smith, V.L. (2007). Rationality in economics: constructivist and ecological forms. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Sugden, R. (1991). Rational choice: a survey of contributions from economics and philosophy. Econ. J. 101: 751–785. https://doi.org/10.2307/2233854.Suche in Google Scholar

Thaler, R.H. (2015). Misbehaving: the making of behavioral economics. New York, NY: W. W. Norton.Suche in Google Scholar

Thaler, R.H. (2016). Behavioral economics: past, present, and future. Am. Econ. Rev. 106: 1577–1600. https://doi.org/10.1257/aer.106.7.1577.Suche in Google Scholar

Thaler, R.H. and Sunstein, C.R. (2008). Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Ulen, T.S. (1998). The growing pains of behavioral law and economics. Vanderbilt Law Rev. 51: 1747–1763.Suche in Google Scholar

Ulen, T.S. (2014). The importance of behavioral law. In: Zamir, E. and Teichman, D. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of behavioral economics and the law. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199945474.013.0004Suche in Google Scholar

Wilson, T. (2019). The promise of behavioral economics for understanding decision-making in court. Criminol. Publ. Pol. 18: 785–805. https://doi.org/10.1111/1745-9133.12461.Suche in Google Scholar

Zamir, E. (2020). Refounding law and economics: behavioral support for the predictions of standard economic analysis. Rev. Law Econ. 16: 1–35.10.1515/rle-2019-0023Suche in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2021-11-17

© 2021 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Heruntergeladen am 11.10.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/rle-2021-0076/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen