Abstract
We make a critical review of the semiclassical interpretation of quantum cosmology and emphasise that it is not necessary to consider that a concept of time emerges only when the gravitational field is (semi)classical. We show that the usual results of the semiclassical interpretation and its generalisation known as the Born–Oppenheimer approach to quantum cosmology can be obtained by gauge fixing, both at the classical and quantum levels. By “gauge fixing,” we mean a particular choice of the time coordinate, which determines the arbitrary Lagrange multiplier that appears in Hamilton’s equations. In the quantum theory, we adopt a tentative definition of the (Klein–Gordon) inner product, which is positive definite for solutions of the quantum constraint equation found via an iterative procedure that corresponds to a weak coupling expansion in powers of the inverse Planck mass. We conclude that the wave function should be interpreted as a state vector for both gravitational and matter degrees of freedom, the dynamics of which is unitary with respect to the chosen inner product and time variable.
1 Introduction
In canonical general relativity, the bulk Hamiltonian is constrained to vanish [1]. This constraint is related to the symmetry of the theory (“general covariance”), which is enforced by the Bergmann–Komar group in phase space [2], [3]. Upon quantisation, one may promote the constraints to operators that annihilate the wave functional, which is equivalent to requiring that physical states are invariant under the action of the symmetry group. In the absence of boundary terms, this implies that physical states are annihilated by the Hamiltonian. Such states are therefore independent of the choice of spacetime coordinates and, in particular, independent of coordinate time. This time independence seems to imply that the wave functional is static and there is no dynamics. This is the so-called “problem of time” in canonical quantum gravity. There are many approaches to understanding and solving this problem (see, e.g. [4], [5], [6] and references therein).
In this article, we will examine and reinterpret one such approach, known as the semiclassical interpretation of quantum gravity (see, e.g. [4], [5] for a review), which proposes that the notion of time emerges if the gravitational wave functional is semiclassical, i.e. if it can be approximated by its Wentzel–Kramers–Brillouin (WKB) counterpart. In this case, the first approximation to the phase of the WKB wave functional is a solution to the Einstein–Hamilton–Jacobi equations [7]. This solution defines a congruence of classical gravitational trajectories and a standard of time with respect to which quantum matter evolves according to the (functional) time-dependent Schrödinger equation (TDSE) [8]. Thus, one is able to derive quantum field theory on a classical gravitational background from the quantum constraint equations for the composite system of gravitational and matter degrees of freedom. If one proceeds to higher orders in the semiclassical expansion, usually performed as a formal expansion in powers of the inverse Planck mass [9], [10], [11], [12], it is possible to compute corrections to the TDSE [11], [12], [13], [14].
In this approach, the concept of time is taken to be inherently semiclassical, and it cannot be defined when the gravitational field is fully quantum. This was argued by Banks [9], who followed an earlier argument of DeWitt [15] that time should be a phenomenological concept in a covariant theory. The view expressed by Banks was shared by many authors in subsequent works in quantum gravity and cosmology [16], [17], [18], [19], [20], [21], [22], [23], [24], [25], [26], as well as in articles regarding the nonrelativistic quantum mechanics of closed, isolated systems [27], [28], [29].
In the present article, we take a different view, motivated by the fact that the choice of time coordinate in canonical general relativity is analogous to a choice of gauge in canonical Yang–Mills theories. More precisely, both general relativity and Yang–Mills theories are constrained systems, and thus, the canonical field equations contain arbitrary Lagrange multipliers. In the Yang–Mills case, the multipliers are fixed by a gauge condition on the vector potential, whereas in the case of general relativity, they are fixed by a choice of spacetime coordinates, i.e. a “coordinate condition.” In analogy to the Yang–Mills case, we refer to the choice of spacetime coordinates as “gauge fixing.” This terminology is unrelated to gauge theories of gravitation, such as Poincaré gauge theory [30].
As it is possible to fix the gauge both in the classical and quantum versions of Yang–Mills theories, we assume that the same is true for (quantum) general relativity. Although it might be indeed meaningless to discuss the interpretation of clock readings in a fully quantum regime, we assume that there is in principle no inconsistency in parametrising the dynamics with respect to a given choice of time coordinate also in the quantum theory. We will thus argue that it is unnecessary to relegate the concept of time to the (semi)classical level and that the usual results obtained in the semiclassical interpretation of quantum gravity coincide with a particular gauge fixing of the theory, both at the classical and quantum levels.
It is not unexpected that the results of the semiclassical approach should coincide with a particular choice of gauge. Indeed, the emergent semiclassical time is a time coordinate associated with the background geometry defined from the phase of the semiclassical gravitational wave functional. Once this coordinate is defined, it may be used to parametrise the dynamics not only of the background geometry, but also of the composite system of gravitational and matter degrees of freedom. Classically, time evolution is only defined once a choice of coordinates has been made, as this corresponds to fixing the arbitrary multipliers that appear in Hamilton’s equations. Therefore, any notion of time (even if it is “emergent”) must correspond to a particular fixation of the multipliers. We will provide closed-form expressions for the Lagrange multiplier (the “lapse”), as well as the classical reduced gauge-fixed Hamiltonian associated with the choice of time given by the phase of the semiclassical gravitational wave functional. To the best of our knowledge, such closed-form expressions for this choice of time have not been derived before.
In [31], Parentani showed that a time-dependent Hamilton–Jacobi equation (TDHJE) for matter fields could be derived from the Einstein–Hamilton–Jacobi equations in a way analogous to the derivation of the TDSE from the quantum constraints in the standard semiclassical approach. He emphasised that such a derivation amounts to a background field approximation, as the notion of time in both classical and quantum cases is defined from the (classical) gravitational background. The higher-order corrections to the TDHJE and TDSE thus depend on the choice of this background. More recently, Briggs [32] has independently derived the TDHJE from the time-independent Hamilton–Jacobi equation. It remained unclear, however, whether the derivation of the approximate TDHJE corresponds to a choice of gauge by fixing the arbitrary multipliers in the equations of motion. As already mentioned, we will show that this is indeed the case.
More generally, one can fix the coordinates to be given by functions of the canonical variables. This “canonical gauge” choice is in line with DeWitt’s view [15] that, in a covariant theory, the contents of the universe itself should be used to define the coordinates and, in particular, time. In this way, the evolution of physical quantities is described through the correlation of their configuration with the trajectory of a quantity chosen to be the “clock” [33], [34]. Moreover, it is important to note that gauge fixing is not merely a mathematical convenience, as different choices of coordinates may also be associated with different reference frames and observers. This marks a difference between the external symmetry of general relativity and the internal symmetries of Yang–Mills theories, for which different gauge choices are unobservable.
Regarding the quantum theory, we take the position that the independence of the wave functional on the choice of coordinates does not preclude its dynamical and probabilistic interpretation. Rather, the invariance of physical states implies that the quantum dynamics is the same for any choice of spacetime coordinates. To fix the gauge in the canonical quantum theory, we proceed in analogy to the classical Hamilton–Jacobi theory. At the classical level, the Einstein–Hamilton–Jacobi equations are gauge-independent. However, if we choose suitable functions of the canonical variables (e.g. the Weyl scalars or matter scalar fields) to define the spacetime coordinates, the solutions to the Einstein–Hamilton–Jacobi equations may be interpreted dynamically, as their variation in the chosen time coordinate will be encoded in their dependence on the canonical variables. If we take the view that the same is true for the quantum constraint equations, the time dependence of the wave functional will be encoded in its dependence on the configuration or momentum variables in the appropriate representation.
The difficulty in establishing such a quantum theory resides in defining the inner product on the space of physical states and assessing whether the theory is unitary with respect to different choices of the time parameter. There have been various proposals for selecting such a physical inner product and constructing the physical Hilbert space (see, for instance, [35], [36] and references therein). This is a subtle issue that is outside the scope of this article. We will adopt a tentative definition of the inner product, with respect to which we will interpret the usual results of the semiclassical approach as a particular gauge fixing. Thus, the quantum theory here presented is provisional. Our goal is not to provide a definitive solution to the problem of time, but rather to reinterpret the standard semiclassical approach and to emphasise how the emergent semiclassical time is related to the freedom of choosing coordinates in general relativity; it corresponds to a particular class of canonical gauge choices, and there are more general choices of time coordinate that could be employed.
The semiclassical interpretation can be generalised to what is often referred to as the Born–Oppenheimer (BO) approach to quantum gravity and cosmology [17], [18], [19], [20], [37], [38], [39], [40], [41], [42], [43], [44], [45], [46], as it was inspired by the BO approximation in molecular physics [47], [48]. We will use the terms “semiclassical interpretation,” “semiclassical approach,” and “BO approach” interchangeably. As our focus is on the problem of time (in its simplest manifestation) and its solution given by the semiclassical approach, we will not be concerned with field-theoretic issues, such as regularisation of the quantum constraint equations. In the main body of the article, we will restrict ourselves to finite-dimensional models with a single constraint, which are useful for analysing homogeneous and isotropic cosmologies. We include an appendix with the formal generalisation of the results of the article to the field-theoretic case.
Finally, we mention a recent article in which Kamenshchik et al. [40] compared the results of the BO approach and the gauge-fixing approach for a simple minisuperspace model and obtained similar results for both methods. The formalism presented here is complementary to their work. We show that the BO approach is simply a particular choice of gauge for a general homogeneous, isotropic minisuperspace model with nonvanishing potential.
The article is organised as follows. In Section 2, we give a critical overview of the standard semiclassical interpretation and the BO approach to the problem of time. We then describe the particular gauge fixing with which it coincides at the classical level in Section 3. There, we show how the reduced gauge-fixed Hamiltonian can be approximated by the “corrected” Hamiltonian used in the standard semiclassical approach. In Section 4, we analyse the corresponding quantum theory, in particular the question of unitarity in perturbation theory. The archetypical example of the relativistic particle is analysed in Section 5. Finally, in Section 6, we summarise our results and present our conclusions. We include three appendices. Appendices A and B contain formulae that are needed in Section 3 and 4. Appendix C formally extends the results of the article to field theory. We work in units in which
2 The Born–Oppenheimer Approach to the Problem of Time
In this section, we make a critical review of the BO approach to the problem of time in preparation for Section 3 and 4, where we show that the standard results of the BO approach can be obtained by a particular choice of gauge.
2.1 Overview
The Hamiltonian constraint of quantum gravity, referred to as the Wheeler–DeWitt (WDW) equation, does not depend on a time variable, and it is thus analogous to the time-independent Schrödinger equation (TISE) of quantum theory. If some of the variables on which the TISE or the WDW equation depends can be treated semiclassically, one can define a time variable from the phase of the semiclassical part of the wave function. In this way, time emerges from a timeless quantum equation (TISE or WDW) in a semiclassical regime. The basis for such a semiclassical interpretation of time was laid in Mott’s work [49], [50] on α-particle tracks. In [49], [50], Mott analysed the TISE for the composite system of atoms and α particles and showed that, by treating the high-energy α-particle wave function semiclassically, one can derive a TDSE for the atoms. The time parameter is defined from the phase of the α-particle wave function. Mott’s derivation of the TDSE from the TISE was further analysed in [28], [29], [51] and inspired an application to quantum cosmology in [52].
The semiclassical regime in which time emerges can be understood in the context of the BO approximation [17], [18], [19], [20], [37], [38], [39], [40], which is frequently employed in molecular physics [47], [48]. There, one is interested in computing molecular spectra by analysing the quantum dynamics of a system of heavy nuclei and light electrons. In many cases, one can make a WKB approximation to the nuclear wave function and consider an adiabatic approximation in which the electronic wave function follows the semiclassical dynamics of the nuclei. The combination of the WKB expansion for the heavy nuclei and the adiabatic approximation comprises the BO approximation. This can be generalised to any composite system, composed of a “heavy” (or “slowly varying”) part and a “light” (sub)system [28], [29], [32]. In the BO approximation, the evolution of the “light” system follows adiabatically the semiclassical dynamics of the “heavy” part. In the BO approach to the problem of time, the time parameter is defined from the phase of the semiclassical wave function of the “heavy” sector and is sometimes referred to as “WKB time” [53].
Englert [27] and subsequently Briggs and Rost [28], [29] took the position that the (nonrelativistic) quantum mechanics of closed, isolated systems should be fundamentally timeless and thus described by the TISE. They suggested that the BO approximation (or a generalisation thereof) should be used to derive the TDSE from the TISE in a procedure analogous to Mott’s derivation. In this way, Briggs and Rost emphasise that the TDSE would be only an approximation and a mixed classical-quantum equation, as the time parameter is defined in the limit in which the heavy sector becomes classical. Thus, the TISE would be promoted to the fundamental equation of quantum mechanics. This approach was further pursued by Arce [54].
In the context of quantum gravity, Lapchinsky and Rubakov [8] derived the functional TDSE for matter fields propagating in a fixed, vacuum gravitational background by treating the gravitational field semiclassically in the quantum constraint equations. Thus, the gravitational variables served as the heavy sector for the “light” matter fields. Essentially, the same procedure was followed independently by Banks [9] and Banks et al. [10]. Although other separations are possible, the “heavy” variables usually coincide with the gravitational degrees of freedom, whereas the “light” sector consists of the matter variables.
In [9], [10], the semiclassical approximation for the gravitational sector was obtained by formally expanding the quantum constraint equations and their solution in powers of the inverse Planck mass. Such an expansion is valid when all energy scales are much smaller than the Planck scale (weak-coupling expansion), and it is analogous to what was done in Born and Oppenheimer’s original article [47]. In [47], the average mass M of the nuclei was considered to be much larger than the mass m of electrons, such that it was possible to expand the Hamiltonian operator and energy eigenfunctions in powers of
It is possible to include corrections to the (functional) TDSE by computing terms of higher orders in the inverse Planck mass. Such corrections have been computed in [11], [12], [13], [14]. In [12], it was concluded that the corrections include terms that violate unitarity in the matter sector. We shall reexamine this question in Sections 2.2 and 4.5 and find that the dynamics of the gravity-matter system is unitary with a suitable definition of the inner product.
In [8], [9], [10], the backreaction of quantum matter onto the classical gravitational background was not included. In a series of articles, Brout and colleagues [17], [18], [19], [20] refined the method of Banks to include the effect of backreaction of matter in the form of a source term in the Einstein–Hamilton–Jacobi equations for the classical gravitational background. The source term consisted of the expectation value of the matter Hamiltonian (averaged only over matter degrees of freedom) and was also accompanied by Berry connection [55], [56] terms, which is in line with the usual BO approximation used in molecular physics [48], [57], [58], [59]. In [39], [60], [61], it was claimed that the inclusion of backreaction and Berry connection terms leads to a unitary description of the matter-sector dynamics to all orders in the weak-coupling expansion.
However, following an earlier article by Hartle [62], the authors Halliwell [63], D’Eath and Halliwell [64], and Padmanabhan [65] stressed that the backreaction terms were spurious, as they depend on the arbitrary choice of phase for the gravitational wave function, which in turn is related to the freedom associated with the definition of the Berry connection. Halliwell [63] and Singh and Padmanabhan [22], [23] concluded that a semiclassical theory of gravity sourced by the expectation value of the matter Hamiltonian or, in a covariant setting, of the matter energy-momentum tensor is well defined only when the distribution of the matter Hamiltonian is peaked about its average value, or the quantum corrections to the energy-momentum tensor of matter are small in comparison to the classical contribution. This arbitrariness related to the definition of backreaction terms casts doubt on the claim that the inclusion of backreaction guarantees unitarity in the matter sector. In what follows, we will see how this can be resolved.
2.2 A Critical Assessment of the Method. Nonrelativistic Case
To clarify the conceptual points mentioned above and illustrate the BO approach to the problem of time, let us consider a nonrelativistic example, analysed in a different way in [28], [29], [32], [66]. We focus on a composite system of a heavy sector interacting with a “light” subsystem. The heavy sector is associated with a mass scale M and degrees of freedom Qa,
where V is a potential term for the heavy sector and
where ψk form a complete system, which is orthonormal with respect to the inner product taken only over the “light” variables q, i.e.
Such an exact factorisation was considered in [32], [54], [57], [58], [59], [67], [68], and it avoids the complication of having to consider the dynamics of each of the ψk states. Evidently, this factorisation is ambiguous, as one can redefine each factor as follows:
where ξ and η are smooth functions of the Q variables. Under such a redefinition, the total state remains invariant,
The usual procedure is to insert (2) or (3) into (1), multiply the result by
where J and K are the real and imaginary parts of the “source” 𝔍. They can be written in terms of the amplitude and phase of χ as follows:
where we used the polar decomposition
We now insert (3) into (1) to obtain
If we define
which resembles a TDSE. Nevertheless, the presence of higher derivatives with respect to the Q variables on the right-hand side makes it more akin to a Klein–Gordon equation. Traditionally, the “time” derivative in (9) is defined only when χ (the “heavy”-sector wave function) is approximated by its WKB counterpart [8], [9], [10], such that t is the “WKB time.” However, we stress that this is not necessary. Indeed, we have defined t from the general phase[1] of χ and used the exact polar decomposition
If the terms proportional to
In the literature [9], [10], [24], [25], [28], [29], [32], [54], (10) is often interpreted as the Schrödinger equation for the “light” system alone, in which the heavy variables provide the clock that parametrises the evolution of the “light” degrees of freedom. The (real part of the) source term J in (10) can be removed by a phase transformation of ψ [32], [60]. However, such a phase transformation corresponds to a redefinition given in (4), which would lead to a redefinition of φ and t, unless one defines time only from a part of the phase of χ or in some other way. By taking into account the terms of order
2.2.1 Partial Averages. Berry Connection
Given an operator Ô, we define its light-sector partial average as
provided the integrals converge. The partial averages
where Aa and Va are real, are of particular interest. The one-form with components Aa will be referred to as “Berry connection,” in analogy to the usual Berry connections that appear in adiabatic quantum mechanics [55], [56]. We can write Va and Aa explicitly as
Under the redefinition given in (4), we obtain the transformation laws
We will also be interested in the partial average
By multiplying (8) by
The real and imaginary parts of (17) form a coupled system for Va and Aa, which can be used to eliminate two of the 2n real components of the partial average
2.2.2 Backreaction
Let us now relate (5) and (8) to the nonlinear system of equations with backreaction terms, which was analysed in [17], [18], [19], [20]. We first define the “covariant” derivatives [17], [18], [19], [20], [60], [76]
which, under the state redefinition given in (4), transform as follows:
We now substitute (17) in (5) and (8) to find the system
Due to (19), one can immediately verify that (20) and (21) are invariant under the state redefinitions given in (4). Although (20) and (21) form a nonlinear system due to the presence of the partial averages, they are equivalent to (5) and (8), respectively, which form a linear system if 𝔍 is considered as an independent function.
Equations (20) and (21) were analysed in [17], [18], [19], [20], [39], [60], [76] as equations incorporating the nonlinear effects of the backreaction of the light sector (which usually corresponds to matter in quantum cosmology) onto the heavy sector (normally gravity in quantum cosmology). Backreaction is here understood as the collection of terms involving the light-sector partial averages, in particular the term
Halliwell [63] and Padmanabhan [65] already stressed that the arbitrariness of χ implies that the backreaction terms in (20) and (21) are also arbitrary. This can be understood from the fact that, although
Furthermore, the physical meaning of different choices of χ is most clearly seen from (9). As we define the time variable from phase φ, which is a particular function of the heavy variables Q, changing φ via (4) corresponds to changing what one means by time. Equivalently, a transformation of the Berry connection Aa [cf. (15)] entails a redefinition of the time variable in the BO approach to the problem of time. This has not been emphasised in the literature so far. In Section 3 and 4, we will analyse how this is related to a gauge choice of the time coordinate. In Section 5, we examine the question of backreaction and partial averages for the archetypical example of the relativistic particle.
2.2.3 “Light”-Sector Unitarity
In the BO approach of [11], [12], [17], [18], [19], [20], [60], [61], [76], the question of whether the dynamics of the light sector is unitary arose due to the interpretation of ψ as the light-sector wave function and of (9) as a “corrected” Schrödinger equation for the light sector.[3] By light-sector unitarity, we mean the condition
which is equivalent to
As Va is not necessarily zero, (22) can only be enforced by a particular choice of χ. Indeed, we see from (13) that
which implies
Equation (22) does not follow from the equations with “backreaction” terms. Indeed, by multiplying (21) by
2.2.4 Marginal and Conditional Wave Functions
Let us assume that we are able to choose a factorisation
where
In this case, it is possible to interpret
Alternatively, one may choose
At the nonperturbative level (without resorting to such an expansion), the choice of factorisation
3 The BO Approach as a Choice of Gauge. Classical Theory
We now illustrate how the results of the BO approach to the problem of time discussed in the previous section can be obtained by a choice of gauge in the classical theory. We focus on cosmological minisuperspace models and consider for simplicity that the heavy sector coincides with the gravitational sector, while the light variables are given by the matter degrees of freedom, although more general separations are possible [21], [24], [25].
The gravitational-sector configuration space is endowed with local coordinates
where summation over repeated indices is implied. A dot over a variable indicates differentiation with respect to the parameter t. The lapse N is taken to be an arbitrary multiplier[5] and the Hamiltonian constraint is
where
One may solve these equations after making a choice of lapse. Alternatively, we can perform a canonical transformation, with generating function
which will be referred to simply as the Hamilton–Jacobi equation, while W will be called the Hamilton characteristic function. Given a solution of (26), one may pass to the new canonical frame described by the variables
for a given choice of lapse.
3.1 Canonical Variables Adapted to a Choice of Background
The presence of the matter-sector Hamiltonian
At this stage, however, we can consider J(Q) as arbitrary.[6] The solution φ will be referred to as the background Hamilton function, and it is analogous to the phase used in (8). It is convenient to define the quantities
which will be called background momenta. Equations (28) and (29) imply the background momenta are normalised to
As in (5), we note that (28) may be regarded either as a definition of φ given J or as a definition of J given φ. If we change the background Hamilton function,
If φ is chosen to be a nonconstant function of the Q coordinates, then the background momenta Φa will be nontrivial. In this case, we assume that one may define a holonomic vector-field basis in the tangent bundle composed of the vector fields
We then define new coordinates
In this way, the gravitational-sector configuration space is foliated by surfaces of constant x1, on which
In Appendix A, we collect formulae related to the change of coordinates given in (33).
The change of coordinates
We can now use the above variables adapted to the background Hamilton function φ to rewrite the Hamiltonian constraint of the full theory, in which
3.2 Gauge Fixing. Reduced Phase Space
Due to time-reparametrisation invariance, we are free to choose a parametrisation in which the following gauge fixing condition holds,
where τ is some smooth function of the Q coordinates.[8] Such a choice of time parametrisation leads to the following equation for the lapse
We can choose[9] the parametrisation in which the “background time” function x1 defines the time coordinate, i.e.
which leads to the fixation of the lapse
The momentum conjugate to
where we used the fact that
The reduced phase space thus comprised the degrees of freedom
3.3 Background Transformations
In the presence of matter, the Hamilton characteristic function
If we change the background Hamilton function,
If we now change to the x coordinates, we find
where we used (34). Using (32) and (44) and the fact that
Let us now choose the parametrisation
We may rewrite the gauge-fixed lapse of (40) as
where we used (44). Using (47), we can also rewrite (41) as
which is the solution of the transformed constraint equation (45). The function
Therefore, the reduced canonical theories described by (42) and (50) are equivalent.
3.4 Perturbation Theory
3.4.1 Expansion of the Reduced Hamiltonian
If we assume that all energy scales involved are much smaller than the heavy scale
We further assume that J is chosen such that the inequality
The term proportional to M is needed if the potential V is nonzero [cf. (28)], and we assume this is the case. We then expand the square root in (49) to obtain
where
If we choose
which imply that, to the lowest order,
Alternatively, if we choose
which imply that, to the lowest order, both
It is also useful to expand the gauge-fixed lapse given in (48). Using (53), we find
which yields
3.4.2 Propagation of Matter in a Fixed Gravitational Background
We have seen that for both choices of κ the trajectory of the gravitational configuration variables is independent of the matter-sector dynamics (i.e. there is no backreaction from the matter sector onto the gravitational configuration variables) at the lowest order of the weak-coupling expansion. This implies that the clock defined from the heavy variables is not affected by the dynamics of the light variables at this order and thus provides an “external” notion of time for their evolution. The lowest-order equations of motion for the matter sector read [cf. (54)]
which are the equations of motion for matter propagating in the fixed gravitational background characterised by the “lapse”
3.4.3 Iterative Procedure
The choice
This expression may be obtained directly from the transformed Hamiltonian constraint given in (45) in a self-consistent, iterative fashion. We first rewrite (45) as
By neglecting terms of order
which is the zeroth-order part of (59). We then substitute (61) in the right-hand side of (60), with the result
which coincides with (59). This iterative solution is essentially the one found in the BO approach in the quantum theory. Indeed, the term proportional to
The terms of (59) and (60), which are of order
3.4.4 Hamilton–Jacobi Theory
We may rewrite (60) as the Hamilton–Jacobi equation[12]
and solve it iteratively, as before. To the lowest order, one finds the TDHJE:
which may be interpreted as the ordinary Hamilton–Jacobi equation associated to (58) when
which corresponds to (54) when
4 The BO Approach as a Choice of Gauge. Quantum Theory
The main challenge in quantising the constrained system associated with the action given in (23) is to define the Hilbert space of physical states. A state is defined to be “physical” if it is annihilated by the constraint operator.[13] In Section 4.2, we will choose a tentative definition of the inner product that is conserved with respect to our chosen time variable. To determine the quantum version of the constraint equation (24), we adopt the Laplace–Beltrami factor ordering for both the gravitational and matter-sector Hamiltonians, which yields[14]
For simplicity of notation, we define the gravitational-sector Laplace–Beltrami operator to be
The quantum constraint equation then reads
which will be referred to as the WDW equation. The factor ordering in (65), (66), and (67) was chosen so as to guarantee that the WDW equation is covariant under arbitrary coordinate transformations in the configuration space of both gravitational and matter degrees of freedom [4], [5].
4.1 Quantum Background Transformations
In the classical theory, the Hamilton characteristic function W can be decomposed into
for any (physical) state Ψ and any operator Ô. If we change the background Hamilton function,
so as to keep Ψ and Ô invariant. We will fix φ by demanding that it be a solution to the (classical) equation (28), after a choice of source J is made. As before, we define the (real-valued) background momenta to be
We note that 𝔍 is not the operator
in addition to the transformation laws given in (31). From the full WDW equation (68) and from (71), we obtain an equation for Ψφ [cf. (8)],
One may verify that this equation is invariant under quantum background transformations by using (31), (70), and (73). This is also understood from the fact that (74) is simply
for the Laplace–Beltrami factor ordering. By performing the coordinate transformation given in (33) (see also Appendix A), we can rewrite (74) as
which is a quantisation of the corresponding classical (60) and (62). The solution to (76) is the wave function of the gauge-fixed system that comprised the degrees of freedom
It is worthwhile to mention the “complex structure problem” [4], [5], which in the formalism presented here can be understood as follows. The factor of i in (76) leads to the coupling of the real and imaginary parts of Ψφ. On the other hand, the WDW equation (68) is real, and no such coupling occurs for the real and imaginary parts of Ψ. In fact, we can take Ψ to be real. The complex structure of (76) originates solely from the phase prefactor in
4.2 Inner Product and Unitarity
Given a solution φ to the (classical) equation (28), we may define the coordinate x adapted to the background Hamilton function φ as in (33) (and in Appendix A). Due to the Laplace–Beltrami factor ordering, we may change coordinates
Equation (77) leads to the continuity equation
where the Klein–Gordon current is defined as [4], [5], [21]
for any two solutions
is conserved with respect to the x1 coordinate,
The conserved charge given in (80) is the Klein–Gordon inner product. If x1 is considered to be the time parameter, then (81) implies that the dynamics based on the Klein–Gordon inner product is unitary with respect to x1 evolution. As is well known, the Klein–Gordon inner product is indefinite. Nevertheless, we will see in Sections 4.3 and 4.5 that this inner product is of a definite sign in the perturbative regime, i.e. for solutions of the WDW equation found via the iterative procedure. Thus, a probability interpretation is possible in perturbation theory.
If we perform a quantum background transformation,
Using the first of (34), which implies
which we can rewrite as
This form of the Klein–Gordon inner product will be useful in perturbation theory.
4.3 Perturbation Theory I
As in the classical theory, if we restrict ourselves to a regime in which all energy scales are much smaller than the heavy scale
Together with (52), (85) implies that the states
where
We now set out to solve the constraint equation (76) in a self-consistent, iterative fashion in analogy to what was done in the Hamilton–Jacobi theory in Section 3.4.4. Let us at first keep only terms to the lowest order in
Let us restrict ourselves to a region of configuration space where
which can be rewritten as
for constant
4.4 Propagation of Quantum Matter in a Fixed Gravitational Background
4.4.1 Partial Ehrenfest Equations
As before, we define the matter-sector partial averages of an operator Ô as
provided the integrals converge. We note that
We note that (90) holds despite the fact that the dynamics of Ψφ is not unitary in the matter sector. Equation (90) is the Ehrenfest equation for a self-adjoint matter-sector operator defined in the gravitational background corresponding to the time parameter x1, its associated lapse function
4.4.2 Matter-Sector Unitarity
We can impose unitarity in the matter sector by considering the factorisation
By inserting
Using (91) and (92), one may explicitly verify that
Thus, unitarity is enforced separately in each sector. The solution to (91) is
where J is understood as its lowest-order approximation, and
The original total state Ψ, which is a solution to the WDW equation (68), can thus be written as
which is just the BO exact factorisation for the total state Ψ [cf. (3)]. We note that we have defined the time variable from φ, which is only part of the phase of the “gravitational factor”
4.5 Perturbation Theory II
Let us now continue with the iterative procedure and keep terms only up to order
where we used the fact that
The inequality (98) should be satisfied in the regime of validity of perturbation theory. To continue the iterative procedure, we use (88) to eliminate the x1 derivatives in the right-hand side of (76). After some algebra, we obtain
where we defined[19]
and
Equation (99) was computed in [12] for a vacuum background (J = 0), and the terms involving the derivatives with respect to the xi variables as well as the term proportional to 𝒱 were absent.[20] Here, such terms arise from the iterative solution of the constraint equation (76). Moreover, the x1 derivatives of the matter Hamiltonian
4.6 Backreaction
We now show how the formalism of [17], [18], [19], [20], [39], [60], [76] can be recovered from the above construction. Following what was done in Section 2.2, we compute the equations with “backreaction” terms from (71) and (74). Upon taking the matter-sector partial average[21] of (74), we find
Using (33) and (75), we can write
If we now insert the real part of (102) into (28), we obtain
where we defined the “Berry connection” as
where
The background Hamilton function φ in (103) is sourced by
If we insert (102) back into (71) and (74), we obtain
where we defined
Nonlinear coupled equations such as (106) and (107) were used in [17], [18], [19], [20], [39], [60], [76] to describe the dynamics of the composite gravity-matter system, and in particular, Ψφ was interpreted as the matter-sector wave function. We stress that such an interpretation requires the additional choice of matter-sector unitarity and the ensuing interpretation of χφ and Ψφ as marginal and conditional wave functions, respectively. Alternatively, Ψφ may be interpreted as the wave function for both gravitational and matter degrees of freedom, obtained from the solution Ψ of the WDW equation by a phase transformation. “Semiclassical gravity” emerges from the BO approach to quantum gravity in the sense that (106) is equivalent to (71), which leads to the Hamilton–Jacobi equation with backreaction terms [cf. (103)].
5 A Simple Example: The Relativistic Particle
As a simple example of the above formalism, let us consider the action for a massive relativistic particle in two spacetime dimensions,
where we have restored factors of the speed of light c, and m is the mass of the particle. We will develop an expansion in powers of
We will choose a gauge adapted to a given background Hamilton function φ. We take
Let us now define the configuration-space coordinate adapted to this choice of φ. Let us set
which leads to
Solving the constraint equation for
Inserting (111) into (110) yields [cf. (57)]
Upon performing the canonical transformation
which is the solution to the transformed constraint equation [cf. (45)]
The solution of (114) found in the iterative procedure is the one with the positive sign in front of the square root and reads
In the quantum theory, we promote the variables to operators
The conserved Klein–Gordon inner product with a suitably chosen constant prefactor is
We perform the phase transformation
For solutions of (117) found in the iterative procedure, the transformed inner product reads
Equation (106) reads
If we substitute
which is simply the partial average of the constraint equation (117), as
6 Conclusions
The problem of time in canonical quantum gravity has many facets and has inspired various interpretations of the theory [4], [5], [6]. In this article, we have reinterpreted the usual results of the semiclassical interpretation of quantum cosmology based on the view that the independence of the wave function on the time parameter does not conceal the dynamical content of the quantum theory and that it is unnecessary to restrict some of the fields to the (semi)classical regime to recover a notion of dynamics. We have followed a conservative route, in which the interpretation of the quantum dynamics closely follows that of the canonical classical theory, which is far less controversial. The diffeomorphism-induced symmetry of the theory implies that the choice of time parameter is not unique. At the classical level, this implies that Hamilton’s equations can only be solved once the arbitrary Lagrange multipliers associated with the gauge symmetry are fixed. This corresponds to a choice of gauge, i.e. a choice of coordinate system. In a closed, isolated universe, it is natural to fix the gauge by functions of the canonical variables. In this way, the coordinates are fixed by the contents of the universe [15]. In particular, the time variable is given by (the level sets of) a particular function of the canonical variables.
We took the position that the same is true in the quantum theory, which we constructed in analogy to the Hamilton–Jacobi theory. As in the classical case, the quantum dynamics must be understood with respect to a nonunique choice of time as a function of configuration variables and momenta. Such a time function is measured by physical clocks composed of the quantised variables themselves, as Singh [11] noted for the case of “WKB time.” Indeed, the “WKB time” used in the semiclassical interpretation (and its generalisation known as the BO approach) is a function of the canonical variables, and thus, it must correspond to a particular gauge fixing. We have shown that this is the case and that the usual results of the BO approach are obtained by a particular class of gauge choices, which can be made both at the classical and quantum levels. The (WKB) time parameter x1 is chosen from a congruence of (classical) trajectories associated with a background Hamilton function, which solves the Hamilton–Jacobi equation with arbitrary sources J. Its interpretation is that of the standard of time measured by clocks that travel along the background trajectories defined from the background Hamilton function.
At the quantum level, the chosen time parameter x1 appears in the quantum constraint equation by a change of coordinates in configuration space, and the usual BO factorisation of the wave function can be replaced by a phase transformation determined by the background Hamilton function. The ambiguity in the usual BO factorisation corresponds to the ambiguity in the choice of phase factor, which, in turn, is related to the freedom to choose different time variables. Thus, there is no need to perform a WKB approximation to recover the concept of time. The inner product and the dynamical interpretation of the theory here constructed, although provisional, are independent of the semiclassical limit. Nevertheless, some approximation method is needed to perform practical computations. In the formalism we have presented, the only approximation used was a weak-coupling expansion. The formalism is applicable not only to quantum cosmology, but also to the timeless nonrelativistic quantum mechanics of closed systems, which was studied in [27], [28], [29], [32], [54].
To reproduce the results of the usual semiclassical approach, the background Hamilton function is chosen such that a weak-coupling expansion is possible. Equivalently, the fields are separated into heavy and light variables, such that a perturbative expansion in the “light-to-heavy” ratio of mass scales can be performed. The background trajectories coincide with the trajectories of the heavy variables to the lowest order in perturbation theory. In the case of general relativity, the “heavy” mass scale is the Planck scale. We have shown that, in the perturbative regime, one can expand the reduced Hamiltonian of the gauge-fixed classical theory to obtain some of the corrections found in the semiclassical approach to quantum cosmology. This shows that some of the “corrections from quantum gravity” found in [11], [12] are, in fact, a result of the weak-coupling expansion of the gauge-fixed system and are present even in the classical theory. The correction terms can be obtained by an iterative solution of the constraint equation both at the classical and quantum levels. In the quantum theory with the Laplace–Beltrami factor ordering, additional correction terms are present, which guarantee unitarity of the theory with respect to the (Klein–Gordon) inner product in the perturbative regime.
The arbitrary source J approximates the backreaction of the light-sector Hamiltonian onto the heavy-sector dynamics in the perturbative regime. This is true both in the classical and quantum theories. In particular, we have shown that the arbitrary source J is associated with the usual quantum backreaction terms, which comprised the expectation value of the light-sector Hamiltonian (averaged only over light variables) and Berry connection terms. We have shown that the ambiguity in the choice of J is equivalent to the ambiguity in the definition of the Berry connection terms, which corresponds to the freedom to choose a particular background Hamilton function and its associated time parameter. We refer the reader to [63], [65], [81] for a complementary discussion on the quantum backreaction terms.
As we have seen, a TDSE appears as the lowest-order approximation to the quantum constraint equation in the weak-coupling expansion. We have interpreted the solution of the quantum constraint equation as the wave function of the composite system of gravitational and matter degrees of freedom. This interpretation is motivated by the fact that higher orders in the weak coupling expansion lead to a corrected TDSE, which includes the momenta of gravitational degrees of freedom (here denoted by xi) and which therefore incorporates their dynamics. Nevertheless, we have argued that it is possible to factorise the wave function such that light-sector unitary is guaranteed, and a marginal-conditional interpretation of the factors is warranted, as was advocated in [54]. In this way, the conditional wave function describes the unitary dynamics of the light sector.
Such observations are important if one wants to analyse the phenomenology of the corrected TDSE. Several works in the literature [37], [38], [85], [86], [87], [88], [89], [90], [91], [92] have addressed this topic by applying the semiclassical or BO approaches to compute quantum gravitational corrections to the Cosmic Microwave Background power spectrum of cosmological scalar and tensor perturbations. Kiefer and Krämer [85], [86], Bini et al. [87], and Brizuela et al. [88], [89], [90] used the corrected TDSE found in [12] to compute the corrected power spectrum. Their method can be reinterpreted with the formalism presented in this article as a particular gauge fixing and subsequent weak-coupling expansion. It is also worth mentioning that Kamenshchik et al. [37], [38], [91] found corrections to the power spectrum by considering “nonadiabatic” effects related to the quantum backreaction and Berry connection terms.
The results of this article lead us to the conclusion that time does not “emerge” only when a subset of the fields is (semi)classical, which is the central tenet of the semiclassical interpretation of quantum gravity. Rather, different notions of time are available in the full quantum theory and are associated with the different coordinate systems that one can employ. The semiclassical approach can be reinterpreted as a particular gauge fixing, and the chosen time function x1 is meaningful beyond the semiclassical level when interpreted as a combination of the quantised heavy variables. Thus, we expect that the semiclassical approach can be superseded by gauge-fixing methods in a more definitive version of the quantum theory. Moreover, it would be desirable to generalise the inner product that was employed in this article to guarantee positive definiteness and unitarity beyond the perturbative regime and such that the interference between perturbative and nonperturbative solutions could be analysed. In addition to this, it would be useful to compare the quantum dynamics with respect to x1 to the results associated with more general choices of the time variable (i.e. not given by the phase of the heavy part of the wave function). This will be left for future work.
Appendix A: Canonical Variables Adapted to a Choice of Background. Formulae
In this Appendix, we collect useful formulae related to the change of coordinates given in (33), which we repeat as follows:
The coordinates defined via (119) induce the following transformation between basis vectors in the tangent space,
The metric tensor in the new coordinates has components [cf. (32)]
whereas the inverse metric tensor has components
The old basis vectors can thus be expressed in terms of the new basis as[22]
By differentiating the first of (119) with respect to Qb, we obtain the useful identity
We also have the Hessian identities
which lead to
Due to the identity given in (124), we may rewrite the function K defined in (72) as follows:
Now using (119), (123), and (126), we can rewrite (127) in the x-coordinate system,
Appendix B: Conservation of the Inner Product in Perturbation Theory. Definition of Partial Averages
It is instructive to verify that the approximate inner product given in (96) is conserved for solutions of (99) up to order
Second, recall that we define the derivative of an operator as
Using (100), (130), and (132), it is possible to show that
We can now rewrite (99) as
Using (134), we obtain
where we used the symmetry condition given in (129) for
which is consistent with the exact equation (81) and confirms that the term
A final comment about matter-sector partial averages is in order. In Section 4.6, the matter-sector inner product was tacitly taken to be
Appendix C: Extension to Field Theory
We now comment on how one can formally extend the formalism presented in this article to the field-theoretic case. The canonical approach to General Relativity in 3 + 1 spacetime dimensions involves a foliation of spacetime into a family of space-like hypersurfaces Σt defined as the level sets of some scalar function,
where yi are the coordinates used to parametrise each hypersurface, Qij are the components of the induced metric on a given hypersurface, N is the lapse function, and Ni is the shift vector. The covariant derivative compatible with the induced metric will be denoted by a semicolon, such that
where
is the inverse DeWitt metric. The DeWitt metric reads
We work only with closed three-manifolds such that no boundary terms are present in the Hamiltonian. The canonical momenta conjugate to the lapse, and shift functions vanish and constitute primary constraints (see, e.g. [3] and references therein), which we have already eliminated. The lapse and shift are thus multipliers. By varying the action with respect to N and Ni, we obtain the constraints
where W is the Hamilton characteristic functional for the composite system of both gravitational and matter degrees of freedom, and we defined the potential
A change of background Hamilton functional
where we defined the background momenta
Given φ, we define the functionals
where
where the B functionals obey[24] [cf. (144)]
The inverse metric tensor has components
We can thus write
Using (147) and (150), we can rewrite (145) as
Equation (151) is analogous to (62) and can also be solved iteratively. The result is
where we have assumed that J⊥ can be expanded as in (51). If we now fix the arbitrary shift vector
We can then combine (146) and (152) to obtain
which is the field-theoretic analogue of (64). As we have argued in the mechanical case, (154) is most appropriately interpreted as an approximation to the Hamilton–Jacobi equation for the reduced gauge-fixed system that comprised both gravitational and matter degrees of freedom. In this way, the solution S of (154) is not the “corrected” Hamilton principal functional of a system composed of the matter fields alone.
To see the how this corresponds to a particular gauge fixing, we define a field
which coincides with
where we have used the first of (144).
We now fix the canonical gauge condition
Using (156), we can rewrite the above equation as
Using
Now, using the first of (144) and the first of (147), the above equation becomes
Finally, using (52) and assuming that
which agrees with (57) at the lowest order for the choice
The quantum theory can be constructed in analogy to what was done in Section 4. The formal Laplace–Beltrami-ordered quantum constraint equations read
where h is the determinant of the matter-sector field-space metric. Equations (158) are the quantum analogues of (143). Given a choice of background Hamilton functional
where we have neglected the covariant derivatives
Using (150) and (153), we can combine both equations given in (159) into the approximate Schrödinger equation
which was derived in [8], [9], [10], [12], [24], [25] without the
Acknowledgement
The author would like to thank David Brizuela, Claus Kiefer, Manuel Krämer, Ward Struyve, and especially Branislav Nikolić for useful discussions and the Bonn-Cologne Graduate School of Physics and Astronomy for financial support.
References
[1] R. L. Arnowitt, S. Deser, and C. W. Misner, Gen. Rel. Grav. 40, 1997 (2008).10.1007/s10714-008-0661-1Search in Google Scholar
[2] P. G. Bergmann and A. Komar, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 5, 15 (1972).10.1007/BF00671650Search in Google Scholar
[3] J. M. Pons, D. C. Salisbury, and K. A. Sundermeyer, J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 222, 012018 (2010).10.1088/1742-6596/222/1/012018Search in Google Scholar
[4] K. V. Kuchař, Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 20, 3 (2011).10.1142/S0218271811019347Search in Google Scholar
[5] C. J. Isham, Canonical Quantum Gravity and the Problem of Time 19th Int. Colloquium on Group Theoretical Methods in Physics, Salamanca, Spain 1992 (arXiv:gr-qc/9210011).Search in Google Scholar
[6] E. Anderson, in: Fundamental Theories of Physics Vol 190, Springer International Publishing, Cham, Switzerland 2017.Search in Google Scholar
[7] U. H. Gerlach, Phys. Rev. 177, 1929 (1969).10.1103/PhysRev.177.1929Search in Google Scholar
[8] V. G. Lapchinsky and V. A. Rubakov, Acta Phys. Polon. B 10, 1041 (1979).Search in Google Scholar
[9] T. Banks, Nucl. Phys. B 249, 332 (1985).10.1016/0550-3213(85)90020-3Search in Google Scholar
[10] T. Banks, W. Fischler, and L. Susskind, Nucl. Phys. B 262, 159 (1985).10.1016/0550-3213(85)90070-7Search in Google Scholar
[11] T. P. Singh, Class. Quant. Grav. 7, L149 (1990).10.1088/0264-9381/7/7/006Search in Google Scholar
[12] C. Kiefer and T. P. Singh, Phys. Rev. D 44, 1067 (1991).10.1103/PhysRevD.44.1067Search in Google Scholar
[13] S. P. Kim, Phys. Rev. D 52, 3382 (1995).10.1103/PhysRevD.52.3382Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[14] A. O. Barvinsky and C. Kiefer, Nucl. Phys. B 526, 509 (1998).10.1016/S0550-3213(98)00349-6Search in Google Scholar
[15] B. S. DeWitt, Phys. Rev. 160, 1113 (1967).10.1103/PhysRev.160.1113Search in Google Scholar
[16] J. J. Halliwell and S. W. Hawking, Phys. Rev. D 31 1777 (1985) [Adv. Ser. Astrophys. Cosmol. 3, 277 (1987)].10.1103/PhysRevD.31.1777Search in Google Scholar
[17] R. Brout, Found. Phys. 17, 603 (1987).10.1007/BF01882790Search in Google Scholar
[18] R. Brout, G. Horwitz G, and D. Weil, Phys. Lett. B 192, 318 (1987).10.1016/0370-2693(87)90114-6Search in Google Scholar
[19] R. Brout, Z. Phys. B Con. Mat. 68, 339 (1987).10.1016/0016-6480(87)90047-5Search in Google Scholar
[20] R. Brout and G. Venturi, Phys. Rev. D 39, 2436 (1989).10.1103/PhysRevD.39.2436Search in Google Scholar
[21] A. Vilenkin, Phys. Rev. D 39, 1116 (1989).10.1103/PhysRevD.39.1116Search in Google Scholar
[22] T. P. Singh and T. Padmanabhan, Ann. Phys. 196, 296 (1989).10.1016/0003-4916(89)90180-2Search in Google Scholar
[23] T. Padmanabhan and T. P. Singh, Class. Quant. Grav. 7, 411 (1990).10.1088/0264-9381/7/3/015Search in Google Scholar
[24] C. Kiefer, Report Freiburg THEP-94/4, Contribution for the Lanczos Conference Proceedings, arXiv:gr-qc/9405039 (1994).Search in Google Scholar
[25] C. Kiefer, The Semiclassical Approximation to Quantum Gravity Canonical Gravity: From Classical to Quantum (Lecture Notes in Physics vol 434) (Eds. J. Ehlers. H. Friedrich), Springer, Berlin 1994.Search in Google Scholar
[26] C. Kiefer, Does Time Exist in Quantum Gravity? Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories (Einstein Studies vol 13) (Eds. D. Lehmkuhl, G. Schiemann, E. Scholz), Birkhäuser, New York, NY 2017 [arXiv:0909.3767 [gr-qc]].10.1007/978-1-4939-3210-8_10Search in Google Scholar
[27] F. Englert, Phys. Lett. B 228, 111 (1989).10.1016/0370-2693(89)90534-0Search in Google Scholar
[28] J. S. Briggs and J. M. Rost, Eur. Phys. J. D 10, 311 (2000).10.1007/s100530050554Search in Google Scholar
[29] J. S. Briggs and J. M. Rost, Found. Phys. 31, 693 (2001).10.1023/A:1017525227832Search in Google Scholar
[30] Gauge Theories of Gravitation (Eds. M. Blagojević, F. W. Hehl), Imperial College Press 2013 [arXiv:1210.3775 [gr-qc]].Search in Google Scholar
[31] R. Parentani, Class. Quant. Grav. 17, 1527 (2000).10.1088/0264-9381/17/6/314Search in Google Scholar
[32] J. S. Briggs, Phys. Rev. A 91, 052119 (2015).10.1103/PhysRevA.91.052119Search in Google Scholar
[33] R. Parentani, Phys. Rev. D 56, 4618 (1997).10.1103/PhysRevD.56.4618Search in Google Scholar
[34] R. Brout and R. Parentani, Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 8, 1 (1999).10.1142/S0218271899000031Search in Google Scholar
[35] D. Marolf, arXiv:gr-qc/9508015 (1995).Search in Google Scholar
[36] J. B. Hartle and D. Marolf, Phys. Rev. D 56, 6247 (1997).10.1103/PhysRevD.56.6247Search in Google Scholar
[37] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, and G. Venturi, Phys. Lett. B 726, 518 (2013).10.1016/j.physletb.2013.08.067Search in Google Scholar
[38] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, and G. Venturi, Phys. Lett. B 734, 72 (2014).10.1016/j.physletb.2014.05.028Search in Google Scholar
[39] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, and G. Venturi, Class. Quant. Grav. 35, 015012 (2018).10.1088/1361-6382/aa8fb3Search in Google Scholar
[40] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, T. Vardanyan, and G. Venturi, Int. J. Mod. Phys. D 28, 1950073 (2019).10.1142/S0218271819500731Search in Google Scholar
[41] R. Balbinot, A. Barletta, and G. Venturi, Phys. Rev. D 41, 1848 (1990).10.1103/PhysRevD.41.1848Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[42] E. Anderson, Class. Quant. Grav. 24, 2935 (2007).10.1088/0264-9381/24/11/011Search in Google Scholar
[43] E. Anderson, Class. Quant. Grav. 24, 2979 (2007).10.1088/0264-9381/24/11/012Search in Google Scholar
[44] E. Anderson, Class. Quant. Grav. 28, 185008 (2011).10.1088/0264-9381/28/18/185008Search in Google Scholar
[45] E. Anderson, Class. Quant. Grav. 31, 025006 (2014).10.1088/0264-9381/31/2/025006Search in Google Scholar
[46] E. Anderson, Gen. Rel. Grav. 46, 1708 (2014).10.1007/s10714-014-1708-0Search in Google Scholar
[47] M. Born and R. Oppenheimer, Ann. der Phys. 389, 457 (1927).10.1002/andp.19273892002Search in Google Scholar
[48] L. S. Cederbaum, J. Chem. Phys. 128, 124101 (2008).10.1063/1.2895043Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[49] N. F. Mott, Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A 126, 79 (1929).10.1098/rspa.1929.0205Search in Google Scholar
[50] N. F. Mott, Math. Proc. Cambridge 27, 553 (1931).10.1017/S0305004100009816Search in Google Scholar
[51] J. B. Barbour, Class. Quant. Grav. 11, 2875 (1994).10.1088/0264-9381/11/12/006Search in Google Scholar
[52] J. J. Halliwell, Phys. Rev. D 64, 044008 (2001).10.1103/PhysRevD.64.044008Search in Google Scholar
[53] H. D. Zeh, Phys. Lett. A 126, 311 (1988).10.1016/0375-9601(88)90842-0Search in Google Scholar
[54] J. C. Arce, Phys. Rev. A 85, 042108 (2012).10.1103/PhysRevA.85.042108Search in Google Scholar
[55] C. A. Mead and D. G. Truhlar, J. Chem. Phys. 70, 2284 (1979).10.1063/1.437734Search in Google Scholar
[56] M. V. Berry, Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A 392, 45 (1984).10.1098/rspa.1984.0023Search in Google Scholar
[57] A. Abedi, N. T. Maitra, and E. K. U. Gross, Phys. Rev. Lett. 105, 123002 (2010).10.1103/PhysRevLett.105.123002Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[58] A. Abedi, N. T. Maitra, and E. K. U. Gross, J. Chem. Phys. 137, 22A530 (2012).10.1063/1.4745836Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[59] J. L. Alonso, J. Clemente-Gallardo, P. Echenique-Robba, and J. A. Jover-Galtier, J. Chem. Phys. 139, 087101 (2012).10.1063/1.4818521Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[60] C. Bertoni, F. Finelli, and G. Venturi, Class. Quant. Grav. 13, 2375 (1996).10.1088/0264-9381/13/9/005Search in Google Scholar
[61] C. Kiefer and D. Wichmann, Gen. Rel. Grav. 50, 66 (2018).10.1007/s10714-018-2390-4Search in Google Scholar
[62] J. B. Hartle, ASI Series (Series B: Physics) vol 156 (Eds. B. Carter, J. B. Hartle), Springer, Boston, MA 1987.Search in Google Scholar
[63] J. J. Halliwell, Phys. Rev. D 36, 3626 (1987).10.1103/PhysRevD.36.3626Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[64] P. D. D’Eath and J. J. Halliwell, Phys. Rev. D 35, 1100 (1987).10.1103/PhysRevD.35.1100Search in Google Scholar
[65] T. Padmanabhan, Class. Quant. Grav. 6, 533 (1989).10.1088/0264-9381/6/4/012Search in Google Scholar
[66] C. Kiefer, Quantum Gravity (International Series of Monographs on Physics), 3rd ed., Oxford University Press, Oxford 2012.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199298204.003.0024Search in Google Scholar
[67] G. Hunter, Int. J. Quantum Chem. 9, 237 (1975).10.1002/qua.560090205Search in Google Scholar
[68] L. S. Cederbaum, J. Chem. Phys. 138, 224110 (2013).10.1063/1.4807115Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[69] E. Anderson, in: XXIXth International Workshop on High Energy Physics: New Results and Actual Problems in Particle & Astroparticle Physics and Cosmology. World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd, Singapore 2014, p. 182 (arXiv:1306.5812 [gr-qc]).Search in Google Scholar
[70] A. Schild, Phys. Rev. A 98, 052113 (2018).10.1103/PhysRevA.98.052113Search in Google Scholar
[71] J. Greensite, Nucl. Phys. B 342, 409 (1990).10.1016/0550-3213(90)90196-KSearch in Google Scholar
[72] T. Padmanabhan, Pramana 35, L199 (1990).10.1007/BF02875295Search in Google Scholar
[73] J. Greensite, Nucl. Phys. B 351, 749 (1991).10.1016/S0550-3213(05)80043-4Search in Google Scholar
[74] T. Brotz and C. Kiefer, Nucl. Phys. B 475, 339 (1996).10.1016/0550-3213(96)00304-5Search in Google Scholar
[75] N. Pinto-Neto and W. Struyve, (arXiv:1801.03353 [gr-qc]) (2018).Search in Google Scholar
[76] G. Venturi, Class. Quant. Grav. 7, 1075 (1990).10.1088/0264-9381/7/6/014Search in Google Scholar
[77] S. P. Kim, Phys. Lett. A 205, 359 (1995).10.1016/0375-9601(95)00584-PSearch in Google Scholar
[78] S. Massar and R. Parentani, Phys. Rev. D 59, 123519 (1999).10.1103/PhysRevD.59.123519Search in Google Scholar
[79] C. Kiefer, Phys. Rev. D 47, 5414 (1993).10.1103/PhysRevD.47.5414Search in Google Scholar
[80] C. Kiefer, Class. Quant. Grav. 4, 1369 (1987).10.1088/0264-9381/4/5/031Search in Google Scholar
[81] J. J. Halliwell, Phys. Rev. D 39, 2912 (1989).10.1103/PhysRevD.39.2912Search in Google Scholar
[82] J. B. Barbour, Phys. Rev. D 47, 5422 (1993).10.1103/PhysRevD.47.5422Search in Google Scholar
[83] B. S. DeWitt, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 377 (1957).10.1103/RevModPhys.29.377Search in Google Scholar
[84] C. Lämmerzahl, Phys. Lett. A 203, 12 (1995).10.1016/0375-9601(95)00345-4Search in Google Scholar
[85] C. Kiefer and M. Krämer, Phys. Rev. Lett. 108, 021301 (2012).10.1103/PhysRevLett.108.021301Search in Google Scholar PubMed
[86] C. Kiefer, J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 442, 012025 (2013).10.1088/1742-6596/442/1/012025Search in Google Scholar
[87] D. Bini, G. Esposito, C. Kiefer, M. Krämer, and F. Pessina, Phys. Rev. D 87, 104008 (2013).10.1103/PhysRevD.87.104008Search in Google Scholar
[88] D. Brizuela, C. Kiefer, and M. Krämer, Phys. Rev. D 93, 104035 (2016).10.1103/PhysRevD.93.104035Search in Google Scholar
[89] D. Brizuela, C. Kiefer, and M. Krämer, Phys. Rev. D 94, 123527 (2016).10.1103/PhysRevD.94.123527Search in Google Scholar
[90] D. Brizuela and M. Krämer, Galaxies 6, 6 (2018).10.3390/galaxies6010006Search in Google Scholar
[91] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, and G. Venturi, Phys. Rev. D 94, 123524 (2016).10.1103/PhysRevD.94.123524Search in Google Scholar
[92] A. Y. Kamenshchik, A. Tronconi, T. Vardanyan, and G. Venturi, Phys. Rev. D 97, 123517 (2018).10.1103/PhysRevD.97.123517Search in Google Scholar
[93] D. Giulini and C. Kiefer, Class. Quant. Grav. 12, 403 (1995).10.1088/0264-9381/12/2/009Search in Google Scholar
©2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Atomic, Molecular & Chemical Physics
- Selenium Zinc Oxide (Se/ZnO) Nanoparticles: Synthesis, Characterization, and Photocatalytic Activity
- Dynamical Systems & Nonlinear Phenomena
- Fluid Flow and Solute Transfer in a Tube with Variable Wall Permeability
- Gravitation & Cosmology
- Gauge Fixing and the Semiclassical Interpretation of Quantum Cosmology
- Hydrodynamics
- Formation of the Capillary Ridge on the Free Surface Dynamics of Second-Grade Fluid Over an Inclined Locally Heated Plate
- Solid State Physics & Materials Science
- Green Zn3Al2Ge2O10: Mn2+ Phosphors: Solid-Phase Synthesis, Structure, and Luminescent Properties
- First Principles Study of Thermodynamic Properties of CdxZn1−xO (0 ≤ x ≤ 1) Ternary Alloys
- Elastic and Ultrasonic Studies on RM (R = Tb, Dy, Ho, Er, Tm; M = Zn, Cu) Compounds
- Tailoring of Bandgap to Tune the Optical Properties of Ga1−xAlxY (Y = As, Sb) for Solar Cell Applications by Density Functional Theory Approach
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Atomic, Molecular & Chemical Physics
- Selenium Zinc Oxide (Se/ZnO) Nanoparticles: Synthesis, Characterization, and Photocatalytic Activity
- Dynamical Systems & Nonlinear Phenomena
- Fluid Flow and Solute Transfer in a Tube with Variable Wall Permeability
- Gravitation & Cosmology
- Gauge Fixing and the Semiclassical Interpretation of Quantum Cosmology
- Hydrodynamics
- Formation of the Capillary Ridge on the Free Surface Dynamics of Second-Grade Fluid Over an Inclined Locally Heated Plate
- Solid State Physics & Materials Science
- Green Zn3Al2Ge2O10: Mn2+ Phosphors: Solid-Phase Synthesis, Structure, and Luminescent Properties
- First Principles Study of Thermodynamic Properties of CdxZn1−xO (0 ≤ x ≤ 1) Ternary Alloys
- Elastic and Ultrasonic Studies on RM (R = Tb, Dy, Ho, Er, Tm; M = Zn, Cu) Compounds
- Tailoring of Bandgap to Tune the Optical Properties of Ga1−xAlxY (Y = As, Sb) for Solar Cell Applications by Density Functional Theory Approach