Home When God was a Woman꞉ From the Phocaean Cult of Athena to Parmenides’ Ontology
Article Open Access

When God was a Woman꞉ From the Phocaean Cult of Athena to Parmenides’ Ontology

  • Marco Montagnino EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: February 25, 2025

Abstract

The aim of this article is to present a new hermeneutic perspective on Parmenides’ theology, which, it is argued, will also have consequences for our understanding of his ontology. The following interrelated hypotheses are presented for consideration: first, that the anonymous goddess introduced by Parmenides in the proem of his poem is identical to the Phocaean poliadic goddess of Elea, Athena; second, that she is the personification of Parmenides’ tò eón.

The modern reinterpretation of Parmenides’ poem, privileging certain aspects of its content, has certainly contributed to advancing our knowledge of it, but at the same time has had the effect of further articulating and differentiating the difficulties and ambiguities of its interpretation. On one point, however, scholars seem to agree: the most enigmatic and debated theme of the Parmenidean poem, besides that of tò eón (τὸ ἐόν; “that which is”), is the role and function of the anonymous goddess (theá; θεά; B1, 21)[1] introduced in the proem, to whose sacred speech (mŷthos; μῦθος; B2, 1; B8, 1) Parmenides entrusts the revelation of the poem’s truth, of tò eón.

The question has been subjected to a variety of analyses and interpretations by readers and commentators of the poem since ancient times, resulting in a plethora of divergent conclusions. In numerous instances, these interpretations of the goddess’ identity have been found to be contradictory or inconsistent with the general interpretations of the poem established by the very scholars who formulated them.

A preliminary analysis of the existing studies on this topic reveals four broad thematic areas in which the goddess’ identity has been considered by scholars:

  1. as a “literary device” created by Parmenides that would allow him to present, from the outset of the poem, his detachment from any sapiential doctrine developed up to his time;

  2. as a conceptual abstraction present in the poem (such as Necessity, Truth, or Totality), i.e. a new deity not present in any pre-existing pantheon, to which Parmenides would have given a conceptual rather than a religious form;

  3. as a physical abstraction present in the poem, such as genesis, light, night, and aether. As such, she would not be a deity subject to a religious cult, but rather a poetic creation of Parmenides;

  4. as a deity to whom an identifiable cult corresponded and to whom Parmenides assigned the role she plays in the poem by deriving his doctrine from the lore associated with her cult.

It seems reasonable to suggest that Parmenides’ goddess cannot be a mere literary device: she certainly cannot be reduced to a generic muse or nymph, as some scholars have suggested. None of these deities seems to have the absolute authority and dominion that Parmenides’ goddess displays in the poem.

Furthermore, it was not possible for Parmenides to represent a new deity. Such an endeavour would have been anachronistic for a man of the sixth century BC and would probably have led to accusations of asebeia from his detractors and political opponents. Indeed, we know that Parmenides was a lawmaker (nomothétes; νομοθέτης) of his city and that the magistrates of Elea swore in his name when they were appointed. It is therefore unlikely that he committed sacrilege against the civic pantheon. On the contrary, it seems likely that he played a religious role associated with his political position. It is possible that he was the priest of the anonymous goddess to whom he entrusts the truth of tò eón in the poem.

It is also evident that Parmenides’ goddess cannot be compared to any of the Orphic deities with which she has been identified, including Persephone, Mnemosyne, and Nyx, among others. This is because they are all chthonic deities, whereas she is a celestial one, as will be shown, and they are not supreme deities. Indeed, each of them has a male counterpart in her pantheon, without whom she would not be what she is. In contrast, Parmenides’ goddess is the only supreme goddess of the pantheon to appear in the poem. Moreover, it seems reasonable to assume that cults related to Demeter or Persephone were introduced in Elea in the second half of the fifth century BC, which is to say after Parmenides’ lifetime. This conclusion is supported by historical–archaeological reconstructions.[2]

Nevertheless, as Cerri observes, a theological identification of the goddess was unavoidable. Parmenides had to paint a picture of her in the mind of his audience. If he does not explicitly identify her, it is because he wants to suggest that she represents the epitome of a goddess, an absolute deity.[3]

In light of these considerations, an investigation into the possibility of identifying Parmenides’ goddess within the context of the supreme deity of the Phocaean pantheon is warranted. I propose that this deity is Athena, who was the poliadic goddess of Phocaea and Elea.[4] In order to prove my hypothesis, however, this study will not delve into the mythological traditions surrounding the Olympian daughter of Zeus. Instead, I will focus on the cult of the goddess Athena in the Egyptian city of Sais. The aim is to show that Parmenides’ goddess exhibits syncretistic traits similar to those of the Egyptian Athena.

While the evidence suggests that the goddess has a cultic character that would have been recognisable to Parmenides’ fellow citizens, this does not exclude the possibility that she also represents conceptual or physical abstractions present in the poem, as do the other deities that populate these verses. Indeed, as Cerri points out, an analysis of Parmenides’ poem reveals a theological perspective that is still grounded in scientific reasoning to some extent, rather than a fanciful account of ancient and hypothetical events.[5] In line with this scholar’s view, it can be argued that the poem represents a reinterpretation of the Phocaean pantheon in a physical context and that it espouses the compatibility of physics with this pantheon.

Before proceeding, it seems wise to clarify another methodological premise. According to Aristotle, “of those who first philosophized” – the Greek thinkers whom we now call the pre-Socratics – most thought that the principles of all things were only of the material kind, and that this principle and element must be some nature (physis; φύσις), whether one or more than one, from which all beings originate and from which as the first thing they come to be and into which they finally pass, while it persists throughout as the underlying subject while its attributes change.[6]

As Cordero points out

from the Aristotelian description of the type of research carried out by the first philosophers we can extract the following specific data: (a) the object of study was the φύσις; (b) the φύσις is the element primordial from which all things emerge, which are in perpetual evolution as they inherit the principle of movement from the φύσις; (c) the φύσις is “conserved safe and sound, grazing” …; (d) the φύσις is the οὐσία of natural beings, which are characterised by change, and, in this sense, (e) to reason about φύσις in general is to reason about “being”, interpreted as the ever-active source of a dynamic process.[7]

In other words, for those ancient thinkers, “reality” has its own being, characterized by a vital, dynamic force that, even if it is not evident,[8] gives rise to the whole and unfolds in everything that exists, and this principle, element, or substance corresponds to the concept of physis.[9] Therefore, it would be inappropriate and anachronistic to understand the physis as a matter and to consider it materialistically in modern terms, but also as what we call “nature.”

Let us now consider, as Cordero underlines, that “already in the remote Indo-European origins, the root of the term φύσις was related to some forms of the verb ‘to be,’” so I agree with the scholar, “that φύσις and being are synonymous is then a reality.”[10] In the Parmenides fragments, we find the term physis three times: twice in fr. 10 (verses 1 and 6) and once in fr. 16 (verse 3). Perhaps, we could think that the word is not privileged by Parmenides because he uses for its concept, for the first time, the generic singular eón.[11]

Indeed, I agree with Cerri’s assertion that the doctrine of tò eón is not a purely logical–dialectical concoction or a philosophical metaphysics in the post-Aristotelian sense. Rather, it is a cosmological doctrine that is intrinsic to the history of pre-Socratic physics.[12] In this perspective, while we should not consider Parmenides’ tò eón as matter,[13] and his doctrine as a materialistic system, we can certainly consider tò eón to be corporeal.[14]

In Cerri’s view, the corporeity of tò eón is posited by Parmenides in opposition to what we call empty space, the possibility of which is denied. The Parmenidean expression “non-being,” as Cerri observes, comes to mean “empty space.”[15] The scholar proposes a comparison between Parmenides’ physics and Einstein’s physics, starting from the above premise. Einstein’s theory eliminated the classical distinction between material particles and vacuum. Moreover, it showed that what we call vacuum is the potential dimension of all forms within the world of particles. This dimension is not inhomogeneous with respect to matter; rather, it is equivalent to matter and can be transformed with it according to the parameters of this equivalence.[16]

If we are to understand Parmenides’ eón as a corporeal reality, as both Plato and Aristotle did,[17] then we must understand its doctrine as a physics. However, it cannot be defined as a physics in the Aristotelian[18] or Newtonian sense. It can more accurately be described as a relativistic physics, in which the content is identical to its container.[19]

Cerri refers to Parmenides’ physics as a “cosmological ontology.”[20] It seems to me more accurate to view Parmenides’ doctrine as a theological cosmology. Indeed, Parmenides’ ontology can only be defined as a consequence, or, in terms of complexity science, as an emergence from Parmenides’ cosmological reflection, rather than as a presupposition of it.[21] Moreover, for Parmenides, as for every other individual who lived at the turn of the fifth century BCE, cosmology and theology were inextricably linked.[22] In a worldview in which the divine was understood as the totality of reality, and the divine and reality were regarded as one and the same, because the divine was conceived of as encompassing everything that exists, the pre-Socratics did not distinguish between physis and theĩon. [23] This was probably also the case with regard to Parmenides’ doctrine. Indeed, Parmenides’ theology is “scattered throughout” his poem, to use Cerri’s words.[24]

In accordance with this intrinsic relationship between the cosmological and theological realms, it is reasonable to claim that investigating the identity of the goddess who reveals the truth of reality to Parmenides would entail looking for a cult in the Phocaean pantheon in which the worshipped goddess represents the personification of reality in its oneness and wholeness. In other words, the aim of this investigation would be to identify a deity who could be said to represent tò eón in person.

In using the language of theology, Parmenides finds himself in a situation analogous, but not identical,[25] to that of contemporary physicists who attempt to describe the origin of the universe by resorting to the metaphor of the Big Bang. Although such a description may seem to offer a rational explanation of a phenomenon, its adequacy is debatable. This is because, prior to the Big Bang, there was no space in which the “explosion” could occur, nor indeed any time, so the idea of a pre-Big Bang state is essentially meaningless, just as “not-being” refers to the “being” in Parmenides’ doctrine. This would be the reason that led Parmenides to use the mythological language and the cult of the anonymous goddess to convey his new doctrine.[26]

If the hermeneutical hypothesis presented in this text is correct, there is a cult with which Parmenides could have had contact as a Phocaean, as will be discussed below, which conveys a theo-cosmological system in which an absolute goddess generates herself and the world from herself, without any other cosmological or theological counterpart. Consequently, she is regarded as the genesis, the matter, and the necessity of reality in its totality and in its multiplicity. According to her cult, the world and everything in it are composed of the same substance of her, the unique and absolute goddess, and they exist as a matter of her being, because they are her generation.[27]

The theological interpretation of the poem may therefore prove to be instrumental in resolving the inconsistencies between the different forms of knowledge it encompasses, and in restoring their interconnections. The indirect aim of this article is therefore to present a new hermeneutical approach to Parmenides’ theology which, I will anticipate, may also have implications for our understanding of what is currently referred to as his ontology.[28]

This perspective might allow us to go beyond the assumption that Parmenides rejected the reality of the world by reducing it to an illusion, à la Berkley – a view that Plutarch (Adv. Col. 1114B-C) has already categorically ruled out – and to understand how, in Parmenides’ doctrine,

  1. tò eón can be understood as both one and multiple, as both the total being and the totality of beings, and as both the absolute body and the unlimited bodies (which are not infinite, however, insofar as the absolute is complete; cf. fr. B4 and B8);

  2. beings are corporeal and real, insofar as they are tò eón, i.e. they are of the same “matter” as tò eón;

  3. nothing can exist that is not tò eón.

1 Who is Parmenides’ Goddess?

Despite the extensive research into the cultural and cultic contexts within which the Phocaeans, the Greek people to which Parmenides belonged, are believed to have interacted, the question of who Parmenides’ goddess is remains unanswered. There is, however, one notable absence from this framework of investigation.

A detailed examination of the history of Parmenides’ ancestors reveals that a community of Phocaeans settled in Egypt from the middle of the seventh century BC, near the emporium of Naukratis, which was attached to Sais, the capital of Egypt.[29] The city–state of Phocaea, the Phocaeans’ metropolis, was in fact one of the select few to found the Hellenion in Naucratis, which was the Pan–Hellenic temple established by the earliest Greek settlers in Egypt. This settlement gave the ancestors of Parmenides with the opportunity to gain access to the Egyptian knowledge held by the priests of Athena–Neith in Sais.

In the book When God Was a Woman, which has been described as one of the most iconic texts of the 1970s feminist counterculture, Merlin Stone devotes just one sentence to this Egyptian deity: “The goddess known as Neith was attended only by priestesses.”[30] This assertion is not only false,[31] but also ignores the fact that the goddess Neith, whom the Greeks called Athena, was considered the supreme deity of the pantheon of the city of Sais, that is, of all Egypt during the reign of the Saitic dynasty. She was worshipped as the personification of reality in its oneness and multiplicity. Indeed, Athena–Neith was not only the genesis and fundamental material of all things, but also the intrinsic necessity and universal norm of all existence.[32]

Historical sources indicate that Parmenides’ forefathers were granted the privilege of having officials at the goddess’ temple in Sais[33] in order to negotiate trade and political agreements with the Pharaoh.[34] It is possible that trade contributed to the development of a common cultural understanding. Over time, Naucratis established itself as a cosmopolitan intellectual centre where Greeks, Egyptians, and Phoenicians lived and interacted.[35]

The resemblance between the iconography of the Phocaean statue of Athena[36] and the Saitic statue of Athena may not be a mere coincidence. Archaeological findings from excavations of the temple of Athena in Phocaea, Turkey (now Foça), support the hypothesis that the deity Athena worshipped by Parmenides’ ancestors in both Phocaea and Elea had cultic characteristics analogous to those of the Egyptian Athena worshipped in Sais.[37]

The etymology of the name Athena can also be traced back to a cult practised at Sais. The most widely accepted theory of the origin of the name traces it back to a Linear B tablet from the Bronze Age (ca. 1400 BC) found at Knossos, which contains a list of divine names. Among these is A-ta-na-po-ti-ni-ja, which is generally interpreted as “Athena the mistress,” or more precisely “Athena, she who rules.”[38] However, Deacy notes that the tablet does not explicitly refer to a goddess named Athena, but rather to a goddess from a place called At(h)ana (which cannot be Athens).[39]

This clarification by the scholar would thus serve to corroborate Bernal’s hypothesis that the name Athena, in its more ancient form Athenaie (Ἀθηναΐη), refers to the sacred name of the city of Sais, i.e. “Temple of Neith,” because the city was dedicated to the goddess.[40]

In light of the hypothesis that the Phocaean poliadic goddess of Elea is the anonymous goddess referred to in Parmenides’ poem, and that her cult shared some syncretistic features with the cult of the goddess worshipped at Sais, we will examine the similarities between the known aspects of the cult of Athena–Neith (designated as Ath.) and the known aspects of Parmenides’ doctrine (designated as Par.):

  1. Both deities were considered to be celestial goddesses.

  • Ath.Athena–Neith was, indeed, a celestial goddess.[41] Some inscriptions evoke her appearance as a heavenly vault.[42] In one inscription, the deity is referred to as “heaven,” while in another, she is described as “the heaven that embraces what is in her.”[43] The temple was designated as “the whole sky” and the central door as “the gateway to heaven.”[44] The high priestess of the temple was known as “she who enters the sky,”[45] while the initiate of the cult was also referred to as “an initiate into the secrets of heaven.”[46]

  • Par.In the gesture of greeting Parmenides, the anonymous goddess takes his right hand with her own right hand, which would indicate that she is a celestial deity, rather than a chthonic one.[47] Poliadic deities were celestial deities, so this could be an argument in favour of identifying Parmenides’ goddess as the poliadic goddess of the Phocaeans.

  1. Both Sais and Elea boasted medical academies.

  • Ath.Sais had a medical academy specialising in obstetrics and gynaecology, located inside the temple of Athena–Neith.[48] Egyptian gynaecological practices included the diagnosis of pregnancy, the determination of foetal gender, and the study of infertility.[49]

  • Par.Parmenides’ possible interest in the field of embryology is suggested by fragments B17 and B18. In addition, there is evidence that he established a medical facility in Elea, which, as far as we know, was highly regarded until at least the first century AD.[50]

  1. An examination of Athena–Neith’s diakósmēsis in Plato’s Timaeus and the diákosmos of Parmenides’ goddess.[51]

  • Ath.In Plato’s dialogue, Critias claims that the ancestors of the Athenians worshipped the same goddess as the Egyptians who founded Sais, and that when Athens was founded, Athena–Neith “arranged” (διακοσμέω; diakosméō) everything in a comprehensive way, as a complete “arrangement” (διακόσμησις; diakósmēsis) (24c4–5), which included rules for organising the political life of the Athenians as well as their intellectual life (24a4–b7). This diakósmēsis enabled them to study the universe in a comprehensive manner and to apply its divine principles to human affairs, so that they could discover everything that contributes to good health, right down to divination and medicine, and to acquire all related branches of knowledge (24b7–c3).

  • Par.An analysis of the language used by Critias in relation to the Saitic myth of Athena–Neith reveals that the verb diakosméō and the noun diakósmēsis are derived from the noun diákosmos (διάκοσμος), originally used by Parmenides (B8.60). There are two testimonies indicating that for ancient scholars the concept of diakósmēsis was closely associated with the Parmenidean doctrine. Simplicius (in Cael. 558.5) uses the term diakósmēsis to describe Parmenides’ arrangement of the universe, which encompasses the Earth, the sun and the other stars, and biology (B10–B18). This terminology corresponds exactly to Plato’s use of the term in the Timaeus. Plutarch recounts that Parmenides established an “arrangement” (diákosmon pepoíētai; Adv. Col. 1114B6) to justify all phenomena (ibid. 1114B7–C1), which thoroughly covers the Earth, the heavens, the sun, the moon and the other stars, and the genesis of humanity.

  • Ath.At the end of the dialogue, Timaeus describes the cosmos (92c) as “monogenetic” (monoghenḗs).

  • Par.It is apparent that Plato is echoing Parmenides, B8.4, at this point.[52]

  • Ath.Timaeus (29c) asserts that in matters of theology and cosmology one should accept a “likely” (εἰκός; eikṓs) explanation without demanding more.

  • Par.Again, eikṓs is a term used by Parmenides’ goddess with regard to the diákosmos which she describes to him (B8.60).

  • Ath.The organisation of the cosmos in the Timaeus unfolds through an intermediary figure: the Demiurge.

  • Par.In the Parmenidean poem too there is a kind of demiurge, namely the δαίμων of B12,[53] who “steers” the creation of everything.[54]

  • Ath.According to passage 22c–d of the dialogue, the priest argues that the Greek myth of Phaeton, associated with the rising and setting of the morning star, serves as a purely mythological explanation of the reciprocal motion of the celestial bodies around the Earth.

  • Par.We have doxographic evidence that Parmenides was the first to observe that the morning and evening stars coincided and were manifestations of the motion of a single celestial body.

  • Ath.The Egyptian priest explains to Solon that the movements of celestial objects are related to the equilibrium of fire in the lower regions of the sky.

  • Par.Parmenides’ poem describes the cosmos as structured according to concentric zones formed by “fire” and “darkness,” with the inner ones containing pure fire (verses B12.1–2). Furthermore, as Aëtius (II 7.1) notes, Parmenides referred to pyrôdes (“fiery” [scil. region]) as what we call the sky (A37). There seems to be a similarity between the two cosmologies, since both have “fire” in the celestial regions nearest to the Earth.

  • Ath.The priest divides the Earth into different climatic zones and considers only the temperate ones habitable (22e5–23a1).

  • Par.Parmenides also classified different climatic zones and held that only the more temperate ones were inhabitable (A44 and A44a).

  • Ath.There can be no doubt that the Athena to whom the characters in the dialogue offer their speeches as a truthful hymn (20d8; 21a2–3) is not the poliadic deity of the Athenians that we know from the Olympian tradition. Rather, she is the Athena worshipped in Sais, who by no means coincides with the traditional Olympian Athena. Furthermore, Solon’s sojourn in Egypt is not proven beyond doubt.[55]

  • Par.On the side of Parmenides, however, we have seen that his Phocaean ancestors had the opportunity to gain new knowledge of nature, the cosmos, and medicine from the ministers of the cult of Athena in Sais,[56] which Parmenides came to know and embrace.[57]

It seems reasonable to conclude from these comparisons that it is not such an odd hypothesis to suggest that Parmenides’ anonymous goddess, like the Phocaean poliadic deity Athena, might be related to the Athena–Neith worshipped at Sais.

2 What is Parmenides’ Goddess?

The second hypothesis that I put forward is that Parmenides’ anonymous deity is the personification of tò eón itself. In order to substantiate this hypothesis, it is essential to ascertain whether the deity in question exhibits cultic characteristics that correspond to the cosmological and ontological attributes that Parmenides attributes to tò eón by Parmenides. In light of the surviving fragments of the poem and the evidence for its doctrine, it is thus necessary to verify that the deity in question is:

  1. the Absolute herself, like tò eón (see B4; B7; B8);

  2. neither born nor ever dying (see B8, 3–5, 9–15);

  3. the origin and necessity of reality (see B4; B7; B8);

  4. the coincidence of thinking, speaking, and existing (see B6);

  5. both “light” and “darkness” (see B9).

    Conversely,

  6. if tò eón were associated by Parmenides with the feminine, this could reinforce the suggestion that the absolute divine, embodied by tò eón, should be personified by a goddess rather than a god.

Having established the influence of the cult of Athena–Neith on the Phocaean Athena cult, and consequently on the knowledge expressed in Parmenides’ poem, it is now necessary to ascertain whether the theological characteristics of the Saitic goddess correspond to the aforementioned criteria.

  1. The goddess should be the Absolute herself, as tò eón is in the words of Parmenides

  • Ath.In an inscription reported by Plutarch (Is. Hos., 354C),[58] placed at the foot of the statue of Neith in the temple of Sais, we could have read this sentence:

“I am all that was, is, and shall be; and there is nobody except me.”[59]

In this declaration of the goddess, the totality of all that has been, is, and will be is expressed as a single, total, and absolute divine oneness. She is that totality, and when she asserts that there is no other entity, she is indicating that there is nothing but her.

  • Par.The same unity, albeit expressed on an ontological level, is evident in Parmenides’ poem on tò eón, which represents the absolute whole of all “being.” No other entity, nor “what is not,” can exist in opposition to it or beyond it (see B4; B7; B8).

  • Ath.The name Neith corresponds exactly to the description given in the inscription on the statue dedicated to her in Sais. The etymological reconstruction of the name, first proposed by Mallet[60] and based on the phonetic spelling of the letters of the Egyptian alphabet that form it, Nt, would in fact refer to the hieroglyphic signs , which indicate the existence of a thing in an absolute manner, independently of any attributes.

Indeed, in ancient Egyptian, the feminine form of a word was also conventionally used to indicate the “neuter”[61] (quotation marks are obligatory because the Egyptian language did not provide for the neuter). According to the scholar, in the name of the goddess the meaning of the relative adjective nt had been “sacralised” and “absolutised,” and thus the hieroglyph Neith meant in an absolute sense “celle qui est, ou: ce qui est.”[62]

Ramadan El Sayed,[63] echoing Mallet’s argument, explains that the name of the goddess is sometimes written with the noun nty, which also corresponds to the relative neuter “ce qui est.” Thus, the scholar continues, we can interpret the name nt as “une allusion à l’origine meme de Neith qui personnifie l’être en soi, ce que nous trouvons développé avec abondance à Esna où Neith est considérée comme la substance unique primordial.”

More recently, in The Routledge Dictionary of Egyptian Gods and Goddesses, Hart[64] has pointed out that the etymology deriving Neith’s name from the word meaning “that which is” fits her procreative aspect and seems preferable to other proposed etymological reconstructions.

  • Par.It is conceivable that Parmenides used the concept of tò eón to describe the reality in its totality and singularity, as well as a hyperonym for the entities that exist, as postulated by Bernabé.[65] This would be consistent with the Milesians’ practice of coining abstract terms in the singular neuter to define the nature of the whole and of everything, as evidenced by the Anaximandrean concept of apeiron.[66] Unlike Ancient Egyptian grammar, which did not allow for a neuter gender, Greek grammar permitted such a distinction. If the hypothesis that Parmenides’ goddess, Phocaean Athena exhibited cultic traits analogous to those of the Egyptian goddess is correct, it can be argued that Parmenides could not have devised a more appropriate term than tò eòn to express the theological meaning that can be derived from the name of the goddess Athena–Neith: “that which is” in its wholeness and oneness, and in its multiplicity.

  1. The goddess should neither have been born nor should she ever die.

  • Ath.In accordance with the tenets of her cult, Athena–Neith was considered to have existed even “before creation,” since no beginning is attributed to her. She was “the divine being who was in the beginning,” “the one who began to exist before those who were to exist, since those who were to exist existed after she first existed,” “the mother who was without being brought into the world,” and “the one who gave birth to her own birth” when birth did not yet exist.[67] In another inscription, Athena–Neith is explicitly referred to as “she who appeared out of herself.” According to Plutarch’s account (Is. Hos., 376A–B), for the Egyptians, the name Athena meant “I came out of myself” (‘ἦλθον ἀπ᾿ ἐμαυτῆς’).[68] With regard to the necessity of having no end, Athena–Neith was called “the Eternal”[69] and was credited with the creation of time, eternity, and everlastingness.[70] Consequently, she was beyond the limitations of time and space and was therefore incapable of having an end.

  • Par.On several occasions in his poem, Parmenides asserts that the tò eón is ungenerated and unending (see B8, 3–5, 9–11, 13–14, 19–21). This argument could lend support to the hypothesis that Parmenides had in mind the cult of his goddess, if her theology was syncretistic with that of Athena–Neith, when he developed the concept of tò eón.

  1. The goddess should be the origin and necessity of reality.

  • Ath.Athena–Neith was not only a self-generated deity, but also a parthenogenetic deity. Among the Egyptian deities, like Atum Ra and Amon, she was a self-created “All-One” that generated the world out of herself. As previously discussed, Athena–Neith generated not only time but also space. With the creation of the Earth and the sky, she gave birth to the stars and the moon, and populated the Earth with all that exists.[71] In this context, the universe she generated is a monogenetic universe.[72]

  • Par.There is a textual account that leads to the conclusion that Parmenides’ goddess already existed at the beginning of his cosmos. This is the Platonic passage from the Symposium (178a–b), also reproduced by Aristotle (Met. 984b 25–28), in which the philosopher refers to the Parmenidean goddess as Genesis.[73]

  • Ath.Athena–Neith is described as having “filled the heavens and Earth with her beauty and her perfection.”[74] The myth thus implies that her creation was not a phenomenon confined to the past, but rather a continuous process. In the context of her cult, the world was perceived as a perpetual creation, and the principle of that creation was understood to be continuously at work, sustaining it through cycles of rebirth.[75] In this perspective, Athena–Neith was present in all things and continued to exist in all things that she had created, ensuring their continued existence.[76]

  • Par.Parmenides is clear about the fact that it is impossible to cut each eón off from every other eón, because in its wholeness tò eón is not a bunch of things randomly scattered everywhere or collected together (B4, 2–4), but a continuous full tò eón in which each eón is seamlessly adjacent to every other eón (B8, 24–25). Therefore, in Parmenides’ doctrine, the eónta are not to be understood as discrete parts of the whole, but rather as integral and inseparable constituents of the continuum of tò eón, that is to say, as the modes of existence of the latter.[77] It is not implausible that Parmenides, elaborating this cosmology, had in mind the coincidence of tò eón with his anonymous goddess, especially if her cult was syncretistic with that of Athena–Neith.

  • Ath.In his commentary on Plato’s Timaeus (In Plat. Tim., I 84.14–20), Proclus states that Athena–Neith “holds together the whole cosmic organization and holds intelligent lives within herself which she uses to weave together the whole, and unificatory powers which she uses to manage all the cosmic oppositions.”

  • Par.In Parmenides’ poem, there is an anonymous daímōn (δαίμων) who “steers” Parmenides’ cosmos and governs the birth and mingling of all things, not as an external rule that transcends them, but precisely by configuring their internal order, ensuring that every single thing is what it must be.[78] Furthermore, even within Parmenides’ doctrine there are cosmic opposites, namely “light” and “darkness.” The anonymous goddess informs him that this opposition is merely apparent, since it is in fact the necessary and unique “form”[79] that constitutes tò eón (cf. B8, 53–59 and B8, B9).

  • Ath.The notion of an “All-One” deity responsible for the creation of the universe implies a dependence of the world on that deity. Assman argues that this notion encompasses not only “cosmogonic monotheism” but also “cratogonic monotheism.”[80] This dependence can be conceptualised as the dominion of the deity over the world that has emerged from it. Conversely, it means that this deity is also the necessity of the world which it has created. In relation to the cult of Athena–Neith, all things generated by her, material and immaterial (including, for example, political life), were her property and subject to her authority, order, and harmony.[81]

  • Par.In Parmenides’ poem, the concept of necessity is of paramount importance, both in the theological and in the cosmological dimensions. Indeed, as Mourelatos points out, if Themis, Dike, Ananke, Moira, and Peitho are “faces or hypostases” of Parmenides’ anonymous goddess, they may represent the “aspects of the modality of necessity that controls” Parmenides’ tò eón.[82] Furthermore, the idea of ineluctable “necessity” is a recurrent theme in the poem, articulated in various ways (χρῆν, χρέος, χρέων, χρῆ) and “dans des passages essentiels,”[83] as Cordero underlines.

  1. Thinking, saying, and existing should coincide in the goddess.

  • Ath.As noted earlier, Athena–Neith was born out of herself because there was nothing or no one before her, and she began to generate reality in its multiplicity from within herself because there was nothing or no one outside of her. She created everything from her heart, as is attested to in the Hymn of Esna, which states that all things which her heart conceived became immediately real when she pronounced their names.[84]

  • Par.As Plato attests in the passage from the Symposium that has become fr. B13 of the poem, Parmenides’ goddess is said to have created eros by “conceiving it” (the verb used is μητίομαι). It is likely that she has also created all other things by “conceiving” them (A37).

Furthermore, the concept of the heart as the organic seat of thought was not confined to the Egyptian tradition. It was also embraced by the Greeks, and it is reasonable to assume that this was also the case for Parmenides. Indeed, Empedocles believed that thought resided in the circulatory system (see DK 31 B105, A97).[85] It is possible that the promise made by the goddess to Parmenides to reveal to him the unshakable heart of truth (B1, 29) is precisely the promise to reveal to him her own heart, which, as the seat of her thoughts, is also the seat of the truth of reality, if she is the personification of tò eón, as I claim.

  • Ath.The model of the creation of the universe as espoused by the cult of Athena–Neith does not entail that all outcomes are predetermined. Rather, as Sauneron states,[86] it means that creation and its many aspects were present within the goddess’s mind. Therefore, in order to predict the future, it was not necessary for the goddess to see what would come into being beyond time; rather, it was sufficient for her to recognise what was present within her, for everything is “now” within her. The mere act of affirming what her heart had conceived was sufficient to give existence to what she affirmed.

  • Par.In this perspective, it is worth noting that the Parmenidean assertion that noûs is identical with tò eón in frag. B6 corresponds in frag. B16, 4 with the assertion that the “full,” i.e., reality in its totality, is “thought.” Parmenides is thus referring to the goddess’s thought, since fragment B13 provides evidence of her ability to generate reality through the act of conceiving it. In verses B4, 1–2, where it is stated that absent things are firmly present in the noûs, Parmenides could therefore be referring to the noûs of the goddess (in a similar way to what happens in the mind of Athena–Neith), which in the poem could coincide with the noûs of tò eón, i.e. the noûs of reality in its entirety and wholeness (see B8, 35–36). Indeed, Parmenides’ goddess states that tò eón “is now, together, whole” (B8, 5).

  1. The goddess should be both “light” and “darkness.”

  • Ath.In the theo-cosmogonic hymn dedicated to her at Esna, Athena–Neith is said to have been born from the primordial waters, the Nūn, which mythologically represented darkness and was “her (own) body.” The narrative goes on to say that “by making the gaze of her eyes bright,” Athena–Neith caused “light to come into being.” This light was not the sun, as Ra was born later, but rather the primordial light, analogous to the darkness of Nūn.[87] According to this myth, Athena–Neith is thus presented as both light and darkness.

  • Par.In his poem, Parmenides posits that everything is made up of light and night (darkness), and that without either there would be nothing (B9). They are the dynámeis of tò eón, which make up the eónta. Furthermore, in B12, Parmenides posits at the centre of his universe a divinity composed of light and darkness as the governing principle of the coming into being of all things.[88] In conceiving these cosmological features, Parmenides may have had in mind a theology in which a deity is “made” of both light and darkness, like Athena–Neith.

  1. Tò eón should be linked by Parmenides with the feminine.

  • Ath.Mallet advanced the claim that within Saitic cosmogony, “sous la forme féminine mieux adaptée à la mythologie vulgaire,” Athena–Neith thus personified “le premiere être, l’être unique, le τὸ ἓν ὄν des Alexandrins.”[89] In accordance with the theology of the Saitic Athena, as Mallet notes, “l’être au sens le plus general,” “la substance primordiale, d’où sortent tous les autres êtres,” is an absolute “principe féminin qui produit à lui seul et sans le secours d’un mâle.”[90]

  • Par.It seems reasonable to suggest that the absolute feminine principle represented by Athena–Neith is consistent with the feminine absolute that emerges from what we know of Parmenides’ doctrine. An analysis of the verses of the poem and the available evidence leads to the conclusion that Parmenides associated tò eón with the feminine in a theological, ontological, cosmological, and gnoseological way (see A24; A52; A43; A46; A53; Simplicius In Phys. 31.3–7).

It seems reasonable to assume that Parmenides had a compelling reason for immediately grabbing his audience’s attention with the first verse of his poem. This verse reveals that the horses hitched to the chariot on which he is travelling are female.[91] This is significant in a culture where the mare was regarded as a symbol of the lack of measure and the constitutive imperfection of the feminine.[92]

The proem’s narrative thus proceeds to weave a reality that is presented as one and multiple, yet integral and absolute, through a kaleidoscopic complex of female deities that represent the unfolding of the one great anonymous goddess in her manifold functions and aspects, which in turn lead back to the unity of the substratum and nature of the one and the same goddess.

It is evident that there is an intention to stress the feminine aspect of the poem. This is further reinforced by the deliberate use of the definite article after the subject, which serves to reinforce the feminine gender (see B1, 1; B1, 3; B1, 25; B12, 3), in contrast to the lack of emphasis on the masculine identity.

As De Santillana points out, in the feminine element that prevails in the poem we can discern “something which cannot be mistaken for an allegorical dressing, which is actually the intrinsic and living form, the ‘entelechy’ in the Aristotelian sense, of Parmenides’ thought.”[93]

Even from these comparisons, it seems that the theology of the cult of Athena–Neith is the only one, among those of which we have any tangible evidence and of which the Phocaeans were aware, that contains a monistic cosmology comparable to that which emerges from Parmenides’ poem. It is therefore reasonable to hypothesise that it could be precisely the lore preserved by its priests to which the “stranger from Elea” in the Platonic Sophist (242 d4–6) refers when he states that the Eleatic conception that “what people call ‘all things’ are actually one” derives from ancient wisdom, older than the doctrine of Xenophanes.

3 Conclusions

Although I am aware that the hypothesis I have outlined is only speculative, there are no compelling reasons to reject it out of hand. It is important to bear in mind that – if I may borrow Timaeus’ words – when dealing with facts and writings that go back some two and a half thousand years, it may not always be possible to give accounts that are entirely internally consistent and perfectly accurate, so that we too should confine ourselves to acknowledging an eikṓs account.

Conversely, the constant effort to assimilate the Parmenidean goddess to an unidentifiable pan-Mediterranean religious figure – whose existence is far from historically plausible – or to an Olympian, Orphic, or Pythagorean deity has led to controversial conclusions and has proved inadequate to fully explain the relationship between the theology that emerges from the poem and the philosophical doctrine of tò eón.

Should my hypothesis prove to be correct, it could be argued that the knowledge that we call “ontology” would have had a “mother,” so to speak, before it had a “father,” as Plato calls Parmenides in the Sophist.

Furthermore, if my hypothesis is correct, Parmenides’ goddess, the Phocaean Athena, like the other great goddesses mentioned by Merlin Stone in her book, would also have suffered the fate of being annihilated and swallowed up by the androcentric order of the Olympian religion. Indeed, the cult was subverted and she took on the iconographic connotations of the patron goddess of Athens when this city extended its political influence to Elea from the second quarter of the fifth century BC.

The Phocaean Athena was initially depicted as Athena–Neith, seated on a throne (in the iconographic posture called ergane). According to Tréziny, the fact that the Phocaean Athena was depicted without a helmet on the first coins is evidence that she was not regarded as a warrior goddess like, for example, the Athenian promachos. Analysing the development of Elea’s coinage, the scholar comes to the conclusion that since the coins minted from 460 BC onwards[94] already show an owl on the opposite side of the woman’s head without a helmet (previously there was a lion), and since the woman’s head appears with a helmet from 440 BC onwards,[95] this would demonstrate the transition “d’une iconographie traditionnelle de l’Athéna phocéenne à une iconographie attique,” in which not only the political message is strong, but also the religious and, consequently, the cultural one.[96]

We can see that the poliadic goddess of Elea gradually relinquished the role of Genesis, matter, and ruler of all and everything, and took on the cultic characteristics of the Olympian Athena, the virgin born from the head of Zeus, who, as in the Eumenides (vv. 736–740), submits in all respects to the will of her father and “safeguards the patriarchal system that comes into place at the time when she was born.”[97]

And it is probably because of the passage of the Phocaean cult of Athena into the Attic cultural area that we have lost all the theological traces of Parmenides’ anonymous goddess, who was not really anonymous to Parmenides’ audience, and we have lost an important key to deciphering his doctrine. Therefore, given the cultural context in which Parmenides is thought to have been born and lived, I think it appropriate to continue to explore the theology that emerges from Parmenides’ poem in comparison with the cult of the goddess Athena–Neith, which seems to be the only pre-existing theology that could have inspired the cult of the Phocaean poliadic deity and, consequently, the monistic ontology that emerges from Parmenides’ poem. It seems reasonable to argue that such an approach could contribute to a more complete understanding of Parmenides’ ontology, which we have previously argued emerges from a theological cosmology.

  1. Funding information: Author states no funding involved.

  2. Author contribution: The author confirms the sole responsibility for the conception of the study, presented results, and manuscript preparation.

  3. Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.

References

Allen, James P. Middle Egyptian. An Introduction to the Language and Culture of Hieroglyphs. Third Edition, Revised And Reorganized, with a New Analysis of the Verbal System. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.10.1017/CBO9781107283930Search in Google Scholar

Antonelli, Luca. Traffici focei di età arcaica: dalla scoperta dell’Occidente alla battaglia del mare Sardonio. Roma: L’Erma di Bretschneider, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Arici, Sabri. “Phokaia’daki Athena Kültü Ve Kökeni Hakkinda Düşünceler (Thoughts on the Cult and Origin of Athena in Phokaia).” In II. International Symposium on Mythology. 8 – 10 June 2021, Ardahan. Proceedings Book, edited by Ahmetkocaoğlu, Serpil et al., 568–81. Ardahan: Ardahan University, 2021.Search in Google Scholar

Assman, Jan. Moses the Egyptian. The Memory of Egypt in Western Monotheism. Cambridge-London: Harvard University Press, 1998.10.4159/9780674020306Search in Google Scholar

Assman, Jan. Un solo Dio e molti déi. Monoteismo e politeismo nell’antico Egitto. Bologna: EDB, 2016.Search in Google Scholar

Bernabé, Alberto P. Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia. Eleatica 7, edited by B. Berruecos Frank and S. Giombini. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag, 2019.10.5771/9783896658081-47Search in Google Scholar

Bernal, Martin. Black Athena. The Afroasiatic Roots of Classical Civilization. Vol. III. New Brunswick (New Jersey): Rutger University Press, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Burnyeat, Myles. “EIKΩΣ MYΘOΣ.” Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 2 (2005), 143–65.Search in Google Scholar

Carson, Anne. “Putting her in her Place: Woman, Dirt, and Desire.” In Before Sexuality. The Construction of Erotic Experience in the Ancient Greek World, edited by D. M. Halperin, J. J. Winkler, and F. I. Zeitlin, 135–70. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990.10.1515/9780691221335-009Search in Google Scholar

Cassola, Filippo. “Chi erano i Greci?.” In I Greci, edited by Salvatore Settis, vol. 2.1, 5–23. Torino: Einaudi, 1996.Search in Google Scholar

Cerri, Giovanni. Parmenide, Poema sulla natura. Milano: BUR, 1999.Search in Google Scholar

Cerri, Giovanni. “Livello scientifico e livello mitico nei poemi di Empedocle.” In Empedocle tra poesia, medicina, filosofia e politica, edited by Giovanni Casertano, 122–42. Napoli: Loffredo, 2007.Search in Google Scholar

Cerri, Giovanni. Dall’universo-blocco all’atomo nella scuola di Elea: Parmenide, Zenone, Leucippo. Eleatica 6, edited by M. Pulpito and S. Ranzato. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Cordero, Nestor L. “L’histoire du texte de Parménide.” In Études sur Parménide, edited by Paul Aubenque, vol. 2, 3–24. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1987.Search in Google Scholar

Cordero, Nestor L. “Les ‘opinions des mortels’ de Parménide et un éventuel pythagorisme éléatique.” Archai 31 (2021), 1–24.10.14195/1984-249X_31_14Search in Google Scholar

Cordero, Nestor L. “The Dynamic Conception of Being in the First Philosophers and the Notion of φύσις.” Journal of Ancient Philosophy 16:2 (2022), 1–23. 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v16i2p1-23.Search in Google Scholar

Cordero, Nestor L. “Les conséquences tragiques pour Parménide d’une erreur d’Aristote.” Journal of Ancient Philosophy 18:1 (2024), 1–24. 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v18i1p1-24.Search in Google Scholar

Cornford, Francis M. Plato’s Cosmology. The Timaeus of Plato. Cambridge: Routledge, 1935; repr.: Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997.Search in Google Scholar

Coxon, Allan H. The Fragments of Parmenides: A Critical Text with Introduction and Translation, the Ancient Testimonia and a Commentary, 2nd ed., Revised and Expanded Edition Edited with new Translations by McKirahan, Richard D., and a New Preface by Schofield, Malcom. Las Vegas, Zurich and Athens: Parmenides Publishing, 2009.Search in Google Scholar

Deacy, Susan. Athena. London and New York: Routledge, 2008.10.4324/9780203932148Search in Google Scholar

De Santillana, Giorgio. Prologue to Parmenides. Cincinnati: The University of Cincinnati, 1964.Search in Google Scholar

De Santillana, Giorgio and Herta von Dechend. The Hamlet’s Mill. An Essay Investigating the Origins of Human Knowledge and Its Transmission Through Myth. Boston: Gambit, 1969.Search in Google Scholar

Diels, Hermann and Walther Kranz, (eds.). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin: Weidmann, 1951.Search in Google Scholar

Diels, Hermann. Parmenides Lehrgedicht. Berlin: Georg Reimer, 1897.10.1515/9783111546100Search in Google Scholar

El Sayed, Ramadan. La deesse Neith de Sais, 2 vol. Le Caire: Institut Français d’Archéologie Orientale du Caire, 1982.Search in Google Scholar

Ferrari, Franco. “Parmenide «antiplatonico». Riflessioni sul Parmenide di Platone.” Rivista di Cultura Classica e Medioevale LI/2 (2009), 315–30.Search in Google Scholar

Fronterotta, Francesco. “La dottrina eleatica dell’‘unità del tutto’: Parmenide, il Parmenide platonico e Aristotele.” Annali dell’Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Storici 17 (2000), 31–53.Search in Google Scholar

Greco, Giovanna. “Strutture e materiali del sacro ad Elea/Velia,” In Velia. Atti del XLV Convegno di Studi sulla Magna Grecia. Taranto – Marina di Ascea 21-25 settembre 2005, 287–362. Taranto: Istituto per la storia e l’archeologia della Magna Grecia, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Griffith, Francis L. L. Hieratic Papyri from Kahun and Gurob. London: Bernard Quaritch, 1897; the text is available online at http://digi.ub.uni–heidelberg.de/cgi–bin/digi–downloadPdf.fcgi?projectname=griffith1897bd1&zoom=4; (last accessed: 6 January 2024).Search in Google Scholar

Griffiths, J. Gwyn (ed.), Plutarch’s De Iside et Osiride. Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 1970.Search in Google Scholar

Guthrie, William Keith Chamers. A History of Greek Philosophy, 2 vol. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965.Search in Google Scholar

Hart, George. The Routledge Dictionary of Egyptian Gods and Goddesses. London and New York: Routledge, 2005.10.4324/9780203023624Search in Google Scholar

Hoch, James E. Middle Egyptian Grammar. Mississauga: Benben Publications, 1997.Search in Google Scholar

Kerenyi, Karoly. Figlie del sole. Torino: il Saggiatore, 1991.Search in Google Scholar

Kraus, Manfred. “Commento ad Alberto Bernabé, Parménides a través del prisma de la lingüística.” In Bernabé Alberto P., Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia. Eleatica 7, edited by B. Berruecos Frank and S. Giombini, 181–9. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag, 2019.10.5771/9783896658081-181Search in Google Scholar

Léveque, Pierre. Sulle orme degli dèi Greci. Roma: Salerno Editrice, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Lloyd, Alan B. (ed.), Herodotus. Book II. Commentary 99–182. Leiden: Brill, 1988.10.1163/9789004301351Search in Google Scholar

Mallet, Dominique. Le culte de Neit à Saïs. Paris: Ernest Leroux Editeur, 1888.Search in Google Scholar

Mansfeld, Jaap, “Parmenides from Right to Left.” Études platoniciennes 12 (2015), available online at http://journals.openedition.org/etudesplatoniciennes/699. 10.4000/etudesplatoniciennes.699.Search in Google Scholar

Möller, Astrid. Naukratis: Trade in Archaic Greece. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.10.1093/oso/9780198152842.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Mondolfo, Rodolfo, “La natura (physis) e il divino (tò theĩon).” In Zeller-Mondolfo (a cura di), La filosofia dei Greci nel suo sviluppo storico, Parte I vol. 2, 60–71. Firenze: La Nuova Italia, 1966.Search in Google Scholar

Montagnino, Marco. “Could Themis be the Deity who «Steers» Parmenides’ Cosmos?.” Philosophia. Yearbook of the Research Center for Greek Philosophy at the Academy of Athens 51 (2021), 88–104.Search in Google Scholar

Montagnino, Marco. “How can Parmenides’ τὸ ἐόν be Unending but Non-endless?.” Ancient Philosophy 43:2 (2023), 299–314.10.5840/ancientphil202343218Search in Google Scholar

Montagnino, Marco. “The Saitic Goddess Athena in Plato’s Timaeus and the Anonymous Goddess in Parmenides’ Poem.” Contributed Paper presented at the 25th World Congress of Philosophy “Philosophy across Boundaries”, held at the Sapienza University in Rome, Italy, 1-8 August 2024.Search in Google Scholar

Morel, Jean Paul. “De Marseille à Velia. Problèmes phocéens.” Comptes rendus des séances de l’Académie des Inscriptions et Belles-Lettres Anné 150:4 (2006), 1723–83.10.3406/crai.2006.88124Search in Google Scholar

Morel, Jean Paul. “Observations sur les cultes de Velia.” In Les cultes des cités phocéennes: actes du colloque international Aix-en-Provence/Marseille 4-5 juin 1999, Études massaliètes 6, edited by A. Hermary and H. Treziny, 33–49. Aix-en-Provence: Édisud/Centre Camille-Jullian, 2000.Search in Google Scholar

Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. The Route of Parmenides. Revised and Expanded Edition. Las Vegas, Zurich, and Athens: Parmenides Publishing, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. “The Epistemological Section (29b–d) of the Proem in Timaeus’ Speech: M.F. Burnyeat on eikôs mythos, and Comparison with Xenophanes B34 and B35.” In One Book, The Whole Universe: Plato’s Timaeus Today, edited by Richard D. Mohr and Barbara M. Sattler, 225–47. Las Vegas, Zurich, and Athens: Parmenides Publishing, 2010.Search in Google Scholar

Naddaf, Gerard. “Anthropogony and Politogony in Anaximander of Miletus.” In Anaximander in Context. New Studies in the Origins of Greek Philosophy, edited by Dirk L. Couprie, Robert Hahn, and Gerard Naddaf, 7–70. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003.10.2307/jj.18253497.6Search in Google Scholar

Palmer, John A. Plato’s Reception of Parmenides. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.10.1093/oso/9780198238003.003.0009Search in Google Scholar

Pugliese Carratelli, Giovanni. “La θεά di Parmenide.” La Parola del Passato XLIII (1988), 337–46.Search in Google Scholar

Ronco, Claudio. “Donne e Medicina: storia e risvolti sociali.” In Donne e medicina. Amore, genere, cura, edited by Filiberto Tartaglia and Claudio Ronco, 11–8. Padova: Libreriauniversitaria.it, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Sauneron, Serge. Esna V. Le fêtes religieuses d’Esna au derniers siècles du paganisme. Le Caire: Publications de l’Institut Français d’Archéologie Orientale, 1962.Search in Google Scholar

Stone, Merlin. When God was a Woman. New York: Harvest/Harcourt, 1976.Search in Google Scholar

Tréziny, Henri. “Hyélè ou Athéna sur le monnaies de Vélia?” In Les cultes des cités phocéennes. Actes du colloque international Aix–en–Provence/Marseille 4–5 juin 1999, edited by Antoine Hermary and Henri Treziny, 80. Aix–en–Provence: Édisud/Centre Camille–Jullian, 2000.Search in Google Scholar

Vecchio, Luigi. Elea. Un profilo storico. I. Dalle origini alla fine del V secolo a.C. Alessandria: Edizioni dell’Orso, 2017.Search in Google Scholar

Wilson, Pebby and Gregory Gilbert. “Sais and its Trading Relations with Eastern Mediterranean.” In Moving Across Borders. Foreign Relations, Religion and Cultural Interactions in the Ancient Mediterranean, edited by P. Kousoulis and K. D. Magliveras, 251–65. Peeters: Leuven-Dudley, 2008.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2024-09-20
Revised: 2024-12-15
Accepted: 2025-01-28
Published Online: 2025-02-25

© 2025 the author(s), published by De Gruyter

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Articles in the same Issue

  1. Special issue: Mathematically Modeling Early Christian Literature: Theories, Methods and Future Directions, edited by Erich Benjamin Pracht (Aarhus University, Denmark)
  2. Mathematically Modeling Early Christian Literature: Theories, Methods, and Future Directions
  3. Comparing and Assessing Statistical Distance Metrics within the Christian Apostle Paul’s Letters
  4. Something to Do with Paying Attention: A Review of Transformer-based Deep Neural Networks for Text Classification in Digital Humanities and New Testament Studies
  5. Paul’s Style and the Problem of the Pastoral Letters: Assessing Statistical Models of Description and Inference
  6. Seek First the Kingdom of Cooperation: Testing the Applicability of Morality-as-Cooperation Theory to the Sermon on the Mount
  7. Modelling the Semantic Landscape of Angels in Augustine of Hippo
  8. Was the Resurrection a Conspiracy? A New Mathematical Approach
  9. Special issue: Reading Literature as Theology in Islam, edited by Claire Gallien (Cambridge Muslim College and Cambridge University) and Easa Saad (University of Oxford)
  10. Reading Literature as Theology in Islam. An Introduction and Two Case Studies: al-Thaʿālibī and Ḥāfiẓ
  11. Human Understanding and God-talk in Jāmī and Beyond
  12. Was That Layla’s Fire?: Metonymy, Metaphor, and Mannerism in the Poetry of Ibn al-Fāriḍ
  13. Divine Immanence and Transcendent Love: Epistemological Insights from Sixteenth-Century Kurdish Theology
  14. Regional and Vernacular Expressions of Shi‘i Theology: The Prophet and the Imam in Satpanth Ismaili Ginans
  15. The Fragrant Secret: Language and Universalism in Muusaa Ka’s The Wolofal Takhmīs
  16. Love as the Warp and Weft of Creation: The Theological Aesthetics of Muhammad Iqbal and Rabindranath Tagore
  17. Decoding Muslim Cultural Code: Oral Poetic Tradition of the Jbala (Northern Morocco)
  18. Research Articles
  19. Mortality Reimagined: Going through Deleuze’s Encounter with Death
  20. When God was a Woman꞉ From the Phocaean Cult of Athena to Parmenides’ Ontology
  21. Patrons, Students, Intellectuals, and Martyrs: Women in Origen’s Life and Eusebius’ Biography
  22. African Initiated Churches and Ecological Sustainability: An Empirical Exploration
  23. Randomness in Nature and Divine Providence: An Open Theological Perspective
  24. Women Deacons in the Sacrament of Holy Orders
  25. The Governmentality of Self and Others: Cases of Homosexual Clergy in the Communist Poland
Downloaded on 6.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/opth-2025-0036/html
Scroll to top button