Home Socratic and Cartesian Personae: Undismembering and Liquidation
Article Open Access

Socratic and Cartesian Personae: Undismembering and Liquidation

  • Richard Polt EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: April 29, 2022

Abstract

The essay investigates two personae: Socrates as depicted by Plato and Descartes as narrator of the Discourse on Method and Meditations. Socrates is aware of his ignorance and insists on remembering to care for the self; Descartes claims to have overcome ignorance through a method that breaks problems into simple and certain elements, establishing a self-certain yet impersonal subject that comprehends and controls objects. The Cartesian approach has led to the modern process of “liquidation” that reduces beings, property, and truth to resources, wealth, and information – initiating the dangerous and unprecedented epoch known as the Anthropocene. The Socratic approach offers some promise of reintegration and resistance to liquidation by urging us to care for wholeness and recognizing that being exceeds what we comprehend.

Tout ce qui est incompréhensible ne laisse pas d’être. – Pascal

Plato’s persona Socrates and Descartes’ persona, the narrator of the Discourse on Method and Meditations, share a moment in which they realize their own ignorance. Socrates never abandons that realization; Descartes claims to have found the means to overcome it. This is, perhaps, the essential difference in their understandings of self, world, knowledge, and memory. The Cartesian persona, with its claim to certainty, promotes an attitude that liquidates or dismembers the whole; the Socratic persona, in its knowing ignorance, undismembers, recollects, and reintegrates.

Socrates and Descartes have always been controversial. Often, both are taken as emblems of a rationalism that one either celebrates for its brave independence or condemns for its corrosive effects on culture and tradition.[1] Here, we cannot review the personae and the controversies in their full complexity, but will focus on certain contrasts between Socrates and Descartes that pertain to our present and future ways of understanding and dwelling on the earth – for there is far more at stake here than literary devices and theoretical arguments. The Cartesian drive for certainty and control has transformed our planet and initiated the Anthropocene; the Socratic project of recollecting and caring for oneself sets limits to the Cartesian quest. Is there a way to revive Socratic recollection while keeping open to the unprecedented, unpredictable events that may come upon us in this new epoch? Can the Socratic project point the way to a paradoxical ontology of the incomprehensible, a metaphysics of surprise?

1 The Cartesian persona

Let us begin with the more recent philosophical persona, the one that has done more than any other to transform the planet – for well before Marx, Descartes insisted on a “practical philosophy” that would not just interpret the world, but change it (DM 6, AT 61–62).[2]

The Cartesian persona is impersonal. The Discourse on Method (1637) was published anonymously – for prudential reasons, to be sure, but its anonymity also helps it serve as Everyman’s story. It is written in French, a language that bypasses academic Latin to appeal to the “natural reason” in everyone (DM 6, AT 77). Its philosophical teachings are embedded in an autobiography, a life told as if it were a “fable” (DM 1, AT 4); but the author also warns us that even the most truthful histories are inevitably selective, so they yield a distorted picture (DM 1, AT 7). The reader is thus steered away from taking the text’s brief chapters as reliable accounts of an individual’s life. What matters, instead, are the rules and reasonings that anyone with sufficient “good sense” can adopt in order to achieve knowledge.

Who has good sense? The Discourse begins with the jest that good sense, also known as reason or the ability to tell the true from the false, must be equally distributed, since no one seems to want more of it than he already has (DM 1, AT 1–2). But the reader who thinks well will notice that a few pages later, Descartes writes that those who are not sufficiently able to tell the true from the false should not follow his method (DM 2, AT 15). Cartesian reasoning, then, is not accessible to all. However, it remains impersonal, since the qualification for participating in it is not some uniquely individual talent or virtue, but simply a high degree of the quality that makes human beings human: reason itself.

Descartes writes, with false modesty, that he is simply presenting his own, personal method, which may or may not be of use to others (DM 1, AT 4). But the book is not titled Discourse on My Method; it is Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting One’s Reason and of Seeking Truth in the Sciences. His method is not really his, not personal at all, but “one’s.” He promises that his techniques can be perpetuated, passing from generation to generation of researchers and engineers (DM 6, AT 63), until human beings become “the masters and possessors of nature” (DM 6, AT 62). They will turn nature into their slave and their possession by understanding the forces that drive natural phenomena and harnessing these forces for whatever purposes they are “appropriate” (propres: DM 6, AT 62). Since Descartes banishes teleology from physics,[3] this appropriateness or suitability seems to be nothing more than the physical limits on technology, combined with the will to enhance and empower humanity. Those limits are very broad indeed: we can build “an infinity of devices,” eliminate the pain of labor, improve our bodies, and perhaps overcome “the infirmity of old age” (DM 6, AT 62). We may someday transcend death.

But first, we must transcend birth – overcoming the unfortunate fact that we were not born with the full use of our reason (DM 2, AT 13).[4] One can jettison one’s entire past, including one’s culture and education, by insisting on “clear and certain knowledge of all that is useful for life” (DM 1, AT 4) and recognizing that no transmitted learning offers any such knowledge. Having performed excellently at one of the finest schools in Europe, the Cartesian persona concludes that he still knows nothing. Then, “I took the liberty of judging all others by myself and of thinking that there was no doctrine in the world such as the one I had been seeking” (DM 1, AT 5).

The world-transforming method of gaining certain and useful knowledge is revealed to the narrator of the Discourse when he is secluded in a warm, womb-like room, from which he will emerge with a remedy for the dependency and fallibility of his thoughts. The method is deceptively simple: admitting only what is indubitably true, one must break problems down to their simplest elements; reassemble them, imposing an arbitrary order if need be; and ensure that no step has been left out (DM 2, AT 18–19). Complex wholes are reduced to clear and distinct parts – which, at least for natural objects, are comprehensible mathematically. Nature must be spelled out, as it were, into its basic constituents. Then, these constituents can be reassembled – or rewritten into different formations.

The Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) were published under Descartes’ own name, in Latin, and dedicated to the Faculty of Theology at the University of Paris. This text is Descartes’ attempt to gain ecclesiastical and academic approbation for his revolutionary vision. Under the guise of a treatise on the soul and God, it insinuates the secular message that the human will, using mathematical tools, can comprehend and control nature. (We cannot plausibly claim that Descartes was an atheist, but theoretically proving the existence of God is far from living a life of faith.)

Although Descartes’ own name presides over the text, and its narrator is presumably the same person as the one whose condensed autobiography was presented in the Discourse, the persona here is more obviously impersonal. Many commentators refer to him as the Meditator – not René Descartes in particular, for his train of thought is supposed to be one that any rational being can follow. We learn nothing about him personally except that he is wearing a dressing gown and sitting by the fireplace (M 1, AT 18). Of course, even these details bespeak a certain amount of security, health, property, education, and leisure. It can be argued, then, that this persona is not as universal as he pretends to be. If one happens to belong among those who are treated as subrational “sub-persons,” one may not have the luxury of doubting the existence of the external world, a world that subjects one to various forms of abuse. Instead, one may doubt one’s own existence and wonder whether one has any reality aside from the hostile projections of one’s oppressors.[5]

Even the privileged Meditator admits that it is not easy to affirm the supremacy of self-consciousness. In order to reinforce that supremacy and show that one’s own intellect can master one’s senses, he takes a piece of wax, “fresh from the honeycomb,” and brings it near the fire (M 2, AT 30). He finds that all its sensible properties change, yet he still knows that it is the same wax. He concludes that the essence of the wax is known through intellect alone: it is simply an infinitely mutable volume (M 2, AT 31). This is true not only of wax, but of all res extensa. In this way, the liquefaction of the wax is an emblem of the Cartesian comprehension and transformation of all material nature. At the same time, it draws attention to the intellect as the indispensable faculty of the res cogitans.

The Meditator requires memory to compare the molten wax to its former solid state, and thus to establish the supremacy of the intellect. The reliability of memory becomes a major source of anxiety for the Cartesian persona. If one is unable to remember every step in one’s own reasoning clearly and distinctly, how can one have confidence in one’s conclusions? Descartes even claims that he must prove the existence of a benevolent God in order to still the fear that memory may be untrustworthy.[6] The need to record unambiguous information reliably and to access the record efficiently and accurately is thus implied in the Cartesian project. Among the Cartesian “infinity of devices” are the information-processing machines that surround us today.[7]

2 The process of liquidation

The modern, self-certain subject analyzes and reshapes the “wax” of nature, presiding over the malleability of matter; it remembers by securely storing and organizing information. This process is manifest today as the liquidation of natural things and organisms into “natural resources”; the liquidation of property into wealth; and the liquidation of integral interpretations into a stream of data.[8] Within the confines of this essay, we can characterize these aspects of liquidation only in sweeping terms, ignoring qualifications and local exceptions.

“Resource” has become the modern term for an entity in general – from time resources to space resources to material resources. “Natural resources” are potentially exploitable assets that are not manufactured by us, but are available for human taking and use. Whether we “develop” these resources or “defend” and “conserve” them, we experience them as pliable, consumable “wax.” “Energy resources” are particularly valuable, as they magnify our power to transform and utilize all resources. Here, “energy” is freed of any subservience to energeia, to some specific kind of actualization; energy is power that can be deployed in any direction, for any willed end.[9]

Likewise, in the modern world, property tends to be “liquidated” into wealth – sheer monetary value that is purpose-neutral.[10] Property – an heirloom, a homestead, an estate – has irreplaceable qualities and makes a claim on us. We belong to it as much as it belongs to us. Modern economies convert this property into “financial resources.” Such resources may take the form of private capital, state-controlled funds, or consumer purchasing power.

Truth, finally, becomes “information resources”: a vast flow of data to be “mined” for useful patterns, its advantages maximized. In traditional premodern communities, truth claims are made and contested against the backdrop of a shared sense of what matters and how to comprehend it. This shared understanding always has its blind spots, but it provides a certain coherence and stability. Now our societies are more disjointed and fluid than ever; they tend to drift apart into subgroups with incommensurable standards of truth. Individuals, corporations, institutions, and governments are driven to accumulate and exploit information to serve their incompatible interests. Remembering means ascertaining data points and keeping them readily available for retrieval and deployment.

There are obvious benefits to liquidation. It loosens confining structures; it liberates us from local conditions that limit us to a narrowly defined natural environment or tradition. Modernity has fostered health, mobility, and an abundance of knowledge and technology. But by the same token, it tends to obliterate the local conditions that we have transcended. Inherited ways of life and ancient ecosystems are easily wiped away by the forces of liquidation.

Amidst this process, what is left of humanity beyond “human resources” who can be plugged into the system of liquidation as needed? What does it mean to be a self now, if the self has drifted free of its former ties to history and nature? The Cartesian persona suggests that the modern self must be impersonal: a calculating, manipulating agent implementing a plan that every sufficiently disciplined mind can adopt, following a method that every sufficiently intelligent mind can understand.

Of course, this has not been the only modern conception of the self: there is the self as the sentiment of one’s own existence and desire for liberation (Rousseau), or as creative passion (Romanticism), or commitment to an uncertain way of existing (Kierkegaard). These are all, arguably, reactions to Cartesianism, and they all arguably share certain modern assumptions with Descartes: for example, the Kierkegaardian leap of faith is anticipated in Descartes’ point that when one is lost in the woods, one must choose a direction and stick to it (DM 3, AT 24–25). But now we will look to the Socratic persona, as crafted by Plato, for an alternative understanding of self, memory, and world, which nevertheless emerges from a situation that is comparable to that of Descartes: a traditional world that has been disrupted by rationalism.

3 The Socratic persona

Let us begin with Socrates’ end – for Socrates is mortal, and his personal mortality is essential to his persona. The story of his trial and execution is an indispensable crisis, a profound and illuminating trauma, not only for Plato but for subsequent Western culture.

Socrates, like Descartes, has a moment in which he recognizes his own ignorance (Apology 21d). But Descartes assumes that if he, as an academically proficient young man, knows nothing, then nobody does: he can judge all others by himself. Socrates, in contrast, sets out to learn from others and concludes empirically that everyone he has interrogated is unwittingly ignorant. They are not all completely ignorant: the craftsmen know how to make things, but they wrongly assume that they also know greater things – the meaning and purpose of their own actions (Apology 22d). We could take this as a criticism of the technical expertise, without reflection on appropriate ends, that Descartes prizes. Furthermore, Socrates’ project of interrogation never reaches a conclusion. He keeps examining himself and others and means it very literally when he says that “the unexamined life is not worth living” (Apology 38a). If he is forbidden to question, he might as well die.

Socrates’ death is depicted in the Phaedo. On the surface, his message in this dialogue again has similarities to Descartes’. Socrates cheerfully insists that he will transcend death, for the soul is immortal, thanks in part to its participation in reasoning, logismos (66a). What matters is not the person of Socrates, but logos, and logos will continue after his disappearance, as long as his friends keep participating in it.

But Socrates’ arguments do not seem to cheer his friends’ hearts. They all break down in unmanly tears (117d), feeling that they are losing an irreplaceable individual. The Socratic persona, despite Socrates’ reasoning, is very personal indeed.

What is more, his reasoning for the immortality of the soul is far from solid. Every argument in the Phaedo is flawed, and his final argument may be the most sophistical of all. The soul, argues Socrates, is essentially alive. A dead soul, like cold fire, is a contradiction in essences. It follows that the soul is deathless (athanatos). And if what is deathless is indestructible, then the soul is indestructible; “if not, we need another logos” (106d). The fallacy that his friends are unwilling to notice is that being essentially “deathless” does not mean being indestructible. Even though there can be no cold fire, a fire can be extinguished, leaving only cold ashes. Likewise, though there can be no dead soul, a soul may be destroyed and leave only a corpse behind. To “be dead” is not really to be at all, but to have ceased being.

What the clear and distinct logos offers us is not the immortality we crave – an indefinite prolongation of our existence in time – but an atemporal conceptual relationship. The concept of the soul is “deathless” only by virtue of being lifeless. The concept of the soul does not participate in death, but Socrates’ soul, and each of our souls, is irremediably vulnerable to dying.

This is why Socrates’ last argument is so unsatisfying, and why it is not actually his final logos; it is followed by a logos as mythos, a tale about the migration of souls to the higher, ethereal regions (107d–114c). This is not a story that can be proved true, but it is one that is worth the risk of faith (114d), because it does more than abstract logic can to satisfy our desires for a meaningful, purposive cosmos – a desire that cannot be fulfilled by the proto-Cartesian physics of the rationalist philosopher Anaxagoras (97b–99c).

Socrates’ penultimate message is that “we owe a cock to Asclepius” (118a). This utterance may be taken as the morbid teaching that life is a disease,[11] or perhaps he is drawing attention to a subtle healing that has taken place for all the participants in his final dialogue. We should note that he pays some homage, in this saying, to his own religion and culture in a way that may be more sincere than Descartes’ pretense of piety.

But Socrates saves his most essential message for last. Immediately after his gratitude to a god, he utters his ultimate parting words: mē amelēsēte. This plural imperative double negative is hard to translate into English, although other languages can mirror it well (in Spanish, no descuidéis). Do not fail to care, he advises his friends.[12] The phrase is sometimes translated loosely as “don’t forget.”

But what is forgetting? What is remembering? In the Theaetetus, Socrates experiments with wax as a model for memory: we have a block of wax in our souls, which may be abundant or meager, clean or dirty, hard or soft. On this wax, we imprint sensations and judgments. But this model fails because, as Socrates points out, it cannot account for mistakes in judgment that are not just mismatches between imprints and perceptions, but occur within the soul itself (196b–c). More broadly, the concept of memory as information recording and retrieval forgets the activity of the self who is recording and retrieving – and self-remembrance, care for the soul, is the crucial form of recollection.

The model of memory as an aviary, which replaces the wax block model, is more mobile: instead of static impressions, we have fluttering, elusive cognitions. But both models fail for similar reasons. The aviary model represents errors in judgment as occurring when one reaches into one’s mental birdcage and seizes the wrong bird. But the false judgment is neither the bird itself nor the seizing of it, but rather the soul’s judgment that one has the right bird – and this judgment is presupposed by the aviary model rather than explained by it (200a–c). Again, the mind’s activity resists being represented as a mindless thing. Truth, error, and remembering do not occur in objects, but in “the self itself.”[13]

The self is not an impersonal cognitive system, but an individual who is faced with the challenge of understanding oneself in relation to other individuals, in a concrete situation. Context matters.[14] Socrates makes this point indirectly when, earlier in the Theaetetus, he tells the story of how Thales, studying the sky, fell into a well and was mocked by a Thracian servant girl (174a). The persona of Thales, and the whole passage, are usually interpreted as Plato’s praise of the otherworldliness of “the philosopher.” But the careful reader will note that “the philosopher” is quite unlike Socrates himself: “the philosopher” does not know his way to the marketplace (173c), never attends parties (173d) (unlike Socrates in the Symposium), and cares only about Man while remaining oblivious to particular human beings (174b) – whereas what Socrates wants to know, first of all, is which individual young Athenians are most promising (143d). Most absurdly, Socrates, who is keenly aware of his own ignorance, says that “the philosopher” does not even know that he doesn’t know (173e).

The key to this absurdity is simple. One must remember the context – Socrates’ concrete situation and interlocutor. He is speaking to Theodorus, an astronomer and mathematician – a proto-Cartesian – who is rather clueless about human contexts. Theodorus does not even know who his prize student’s father is (144b). He is a theorist, but he dislikes the rough-and-tumble of philosophical debate (162b, 165a, 169a); he would much rather hear Socrates praise the abstract type of “the philosopher” (177c). Theodorus, like many readers, fails to understand that the figure of “the philosopher” with whom he identifies is a fool who forgets himself. He is oblivious to his own oblivion.

Perhaps the more Socratic persona in Socrates’ fable is not Thales, but the Thracian girl.[15] Socrates is quietly laughing at the self-oblivion into which theorists can fall. Of course, Socrates honors reason, and he does his utmost to understand. He does not laugh at the desire to know, but at the failure of self-knowledge that besets those who try to live as if theorizing were all there is to living.

Socrates theorizes, then, but he is not simply a theorist. He remains a loyal member of his community even as he transcends the community’s prejudices.[16] He is also a mortal, who never cavalierly assumes, like Theodorus, that “we have plenty of time” (172c). The precious, leisurely space of philosophical discourse, where ideas can be revisited and arguments can be reconsidered, opens up within an interval that may, at any moment, face the conclusive singularity of death.[17]

4 The project of undismembering

Socrates’ ultimate imperative double negative – mē amelēsēte – can be rendered still more loosely: Undismember!

Socratic remembering resists the process of dismembering to which we all tend to fall prey. The careless, dismembered self contradicts itself and does not care to try to resolve the contradictions; it fails to become its own friend (Republic 443d) and feels no responsibility to make an effort to do so. It has drunk more deeply from the River Carelessness (Amelētēs), on the plain of Oblivion (Lēthē), than was required (Republic 621a).

This dismembering is fundamentally unintentional. We are not intentionally so careless as to let ourselves lie about the most important things to what is most important in ourselves (Republic 382a) – to deceive our own faculty of logos about the good. When it comes to the good, everyone wants truth and knowledge, not semblance and opinion (Republic 505d). How terrible it would be to live one’s life in confusion about its ultimate purpose. No one would choose such a life!

Nevertheless, for Socrates, most people do live in such confusion – not through an intentional choice, but through lack of intention and the failure to choose. They fail to care because they assume that they are already in possession of the truth, that the truth about the good is something obvious. Life, for instance, may seem to be for the sake of pleasure or knowledge – but just a few simple questions reveal that such dogmas hover over an abyss (Republic 505b–c). Socrates does not proffer an answer to the question of the good; in fact, he denies that he knows it (506c). However, he insists that everything depends on attaining this knowledge (505a). He insists that we should care.

The dismembered self fails to understand that it misunderstands what matters most. Why are we normally so careless, so disjointed, so inconsiderate when it comes to what is most important? Maybe we fail to discover it because we have not been moved to search for it.[18] Some unforeseeable encounter – an encounter with a singular individual, such as Socrates himself – might move us to seek. But for this, we must become movable. Socrates meets persona after persona who fails to take a hint, who remains unmovable. Is there a responsibility to become capable of responding?

These are the kinds of questions implied in the so-called “Platonic theory of recollection.” To comprehend anamnēsis, we must not stop at the mythology of reincarnation or the metaphysics of eternal forms, but grasp how the demand to undismember oneself challenges each of us to gather together one’s own soul.

Can Platonic recollection help us confront the Anthropocene? The answer may well seem to be no. Modern liquidation has unleashed an irreversible transformation that is confronting us with truly new phenomena. In contrast, it seems that Plato advocates a return to the immemorial.[19] To pursue the wax metaphor: Platonic recollection is like a film played backwards, in which Descartes’ molten wax would regain its firm, hexagonal structure and then be reintegrated into a living beehive. But just as films in reverse represent practically impossible violations of entropy, there is no going back from modern liquidation. Modern science, instead of contemplating eternal forms and sempiternal cycles, has actively intervened in nature and provoked a chain of events that is comparable to the irreversible, irreparable complications of human action.[20] Planet Earth can no more be restored to a set of inviolate ecosystems than human plurality can be formed into the hive-like “just city” fantasized by Plato in the Republic.

But Socratic undismembering is more than Platonist recognition of eternal forms. Here, we are touching on the questions of whether Socrates is Platonic and whether Plato is Socratic. I would argue that Plato does continue in Socrates’ footsteps, and that he is not a Platonist, even in the Republic: consider that the “just city” is primarily an analogue to the just soul (592a–b), which is ultimately confronted with the unanswered question “What is the good?” and the riddle of our ignorance about this matter that matters most. Plato is not reducible to Platonism, and Platonic recollection is not reducible to Platonist knowledge of the forms. Socratic–Platonic undismembering is not simply a return to and preservation of the timeless, but is a care for the temporal self that draws attention to our oblivious self-deception.

If this is the case, then undismembering is a potentially fruitful resistance to modern liquidation. Liquidation implicates modern humanity in a self-certainty that misunderstands itself and a remembering that forgets itself. Socrates urges us to become alert to the need to counter this oblivion.

5 An ontology of the incomprehensible

Can we go farther and construct an ontology, a theory of being, that takes up the lessons Socrates indirectly teaches us through images such as the wax block and personae such as Thales and the servant girl? On the face of it, this seems impossible. Thales and Theodorus are theorists, Platonism is a theory, Cartesianism is a theory, but Socratism is no theory. It is a negative or doubly negative stance (undismember!). Socrates knows that he knows nothing, and his devotion to the imperative “Know yourself” does not yield an epistemology or ontology, but a questioning self-concern. This care for the self might hold us back from reckless decisions, like Socrates’ daimonion (Apology 40a), but how can it positively tell us what to do or believe?

One might also suspect that an ontology of the unprecedented – and we find ourselves in an unprecedented epoch – is a contradiction in terms. Philosophical theorizing looks backward (Hegel), but life must be lived forward (Kierkegaard) – and this truth now applies more clearly than ever not only to human life, but to all life on our planet. The ideal of knowledge as a deductive system closes us off to the novelty and surprise of existence, which may offer us strange, unexpected principles.[21] Just as there can be no recollection of the future, there can be no ontological system of the new.

All the same, a nonsystematic consideration of being may leave room for what exceeds what we have been able to grasp so far. “Not all that is incomprehensible fails to be.”[22] In fact, if we take Pascal’s dictum in a radical sense, a certain incomprehensibility is even crucial to being. The very sense of being indicates the excess that challenges sense: that is, we recognize something as existing, as real, precisely insofar as it adds to, or even contravenes, our established interpretations. Ontology, then, should not limit itself to explicating what it means to be, but should investigate experiences in which meaning is challenged by what we cannot comprehend, at least not yet.[23]

This ontology of the incomprehensible would trace inadequacies, surprises, breakthroughs, and breakdowns; moments when we are blindsided and when we are blind to what lies before our eyes; failures to see and failures to look; times when we are caught by the unpredictable, the barely suspected, the reconfigurations that come upon us and force us to rethink what is.

Such experiences bring us face to face with the question of our own being – who we are. They challenge us to care about caring, to undismember, to reintegrate. Socrates’ unabated awareness of his own ignorance encourages the attempt to gather oneself in the face of one’s incomprehension; Descartes’ confidence in his own knowledge excludes a confrontation with the incomprehensible and thus with one’s own being.

Elsewhere, I have made a case for resisting the liquidating trends of the Anthropocene by reviving the “eidetic eros,” the philosophical quest for essences – not in a reductive fashion that traces all phenomena back to a single universal, but in a pluralistic spirit that is ready to discover new and diverse entities in their distinctive integrities.[24] This eidetic eros can coexist with Socratic undismembering, which reminds us that we lack understanding of essences. While this may seem paradoxical, we should remember that eros is precisely an experience of absence (Symposium 200e).[25] We desire what we do not have. We yearn for the fulfillment that is promised by our glimpses of integrity. The search for new essences has to be driven by a Socratic, erotic sense of lack.

If being is uncomprehended, then certainty is not a sign of success, but a warning that one has failed to do justice to being. A mark of ontological justice would be desire – the desire to approach what is only intimated, what we catch sight of just as it escapes our grasp. We honor being by approaching it, not by reaching it. To arrive at the origin is to destroy it. Neither the ultimate truth nor the whole can be known – not even one’s own true and whole self. But truth and wholeness can be kept in view by desire, by care, by the unfinished project of becoming wise.

A Socratic experience of the failure of figures of thought – the wax block, the just city, and many more – develops our ability to think while keeping us mindful of our limits and open to the new. It makes it possible for us to loosen our attachment to the figure of Descartes’ wax and become alert to possibilities that may arise on the margins of the global process of liquidation – as-yet-incomprehensible possibilities that may be paths to undismembering.

  1. Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.

References

Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958.Search in Google Scholar

Arendt, Hannah. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New ed. New York: Harcourt, 1966.Search in Google Scholar

Blumenberg, Hans. The Laughter of the Thracian Woman: A Protohistory of Theory, translated by Spencer Hawkins. New York: Bloomsbury, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Bordo, Susan. “The Cartesian Masculinization of Thought.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 11:3 (Spring 1986), 439–56.10.1086/494250Search in Google Scholar

Carson, Anne. Eros the Bittersweet: An Essay. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986.10.1515/9780691249247Search in Google Scholar

Davis, Michael. “The Self Itself: On Beginning Plato’s Alcibiades I.” Unpublished paper.Search in Google Scholar

Descartes, René. Oeuvres de Descartes, edited by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. Paris: Léopold Cerf. Vol. VI (1902) and vol. VII (1904).10.5962/bhl.title.39750Search in Google Scholar

Gustafson-Barrett, Charlie. “The Lógos of Agency (Or the Agency of Lógos): On Plato’s Ion.” The Review of Metaphysics 73 (Sept. 2019), 3–29.10.1353/rvm.2019.0007Search in Google Scholar

Kierkegaard, Søren. Philosophical Fragments and Johannes Climacus, edited and translated by Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985.Search in Google Scholar

Madison, Laurel A. “Have We Been Careless with Socrates’ Last Words?: A Rereading of the Phaedo.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40:4 (2002), 421–36.10.1353/hph.2002.0072Search in Google Scholar

Marder, Michael. Dump Philosophy: A Phenomenology of Devastation. New York: Bloomsbury, 2020.10.5040/9781350170636Search in Google Scholar

Marder, Michael. Dust. New York: Bloomsbury, 2016.10.5040/9781501317583Search in Google Scholar

Marder, Michael. Energy Dreams: Of Actuality. New York: Columbia University Press, 2017.10.7312/mard18058Search in Google Scholar

Marder, Michael. Pyropolitics: When the World is Ablaze. London: Rowman and Littlefield International, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Mills, Charles W. “Non-Cartesian Sums.” In Blackness Visible: Essays on Philosophy and Race. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998.10.5840/teachphil199417327Search in Google Scholar

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Twilight of the Idols: Or, How to Philosophize with the Hammer, translated by Richard Polt. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997.Search in Google Scholar

Pascal, Blaise. Pensées, edited and translated by Roger Ariew. Indianapolis: Hackett, 2004.Search in Google Scholar

Polt, Richard. “Eidetic Eros and the Liquidation of the Real.” In The Task of Philosophy in the Anthropocene: Axial Echoes in Global Space, edited by Richard Polt and Jon Wittrock. London: Rowman and Littlefield International, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Polt, Richard. “Potentiality, Energy and Sway: From Aristotelian to Modern to Postmodern Physics?” Existentia 11 (2001), 27–41.Search in Google Scholar

Polt, Richard. Time and Trauma: Thinking Through Heidegger in the Thirties. London: Rowman & Littlefield International, 2019.10.5840/heideggercircle20195324Search in Google Scholar

Spiegelberg, Herbert, ed. The Socratic Enigma: A Collection of Testimonies through Twenty-four Centuries. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2022-03-22
Accepted: 2022-04-08
Published Online: 2022-04-29

© 2022 Richard Polt, published by De Gruyter

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Articles in the same Issue

  1. Topical issue: Kant’s Transcendental Dialectic: A Re-Evaluation, edited by Michael Lewin and Rudolf Meer
  2. Introduction to the Topical Issue “Kant’s Transcendental Dialectic: A Re-Evaluation”
  3. Between Old and New Teleology. Kant on Maupertuis’ Principle of Least Action
  4. The Faculty of Ideas. Kant’s Concept of Reason in the Narrower Sense
  5. For a Dialectic-First Approach to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason
  6. On the Concept of Real Use of Reason
  7. Where Do All These Ideas Come From? Kant on the Formation of Concepts Under the Guidance of Pure Reason
  8. Kant on the Status of Ideas and Principles of Reason
  9. The Collective Unity of Reason in the First Critique
  10. Determining and Grounding: The Twofold Function of the Transcendental Dialectic
  11. Towards a Unity of Theoretical and Practical Reason: On the Constitutive Significance of the Transcendental Dialectic
  12. Meillassoux’s Reinterpretation of Kant’s Transcendental Dialectic
  13. Semantic Anti-Realism in Kant’s Antinomy Chapter
  14. Reason, Its Real Use, and the Status of Its Ideas and Principles: Response to Caimi, Gava, and Lewin
  15. Topical issue: Conceptual Personae in Ontology, edited by Carlos A. Segovia
  16. Conceptual Personae in Ontology
  17. Socratic and Cartesian Personae: Undismembering and Liquidation
  18. Nietzsche’s Ariadne: On Asses’s Ears in Botticelli/Dürer – and Poussin’s Bacchanale
  19. The Mythical Absolute: The Fiction of Being
  20. Rivalry and Philosophy after Deleuze’s Reversal of Platonic Participation
  21. Rethinking Dionysus and Apollo: Redrawing Today’s Philosophical Chessboard
  22. The Witching Body: Ontology and Physicality of the Witch
  23. Topical issue: Ethics and Politics of TV Series, edited by Sandra Laugier
  24. Taking TV Series Seriously
  25. 1. Moral Education and the Limits of Ethics
  26. Fleabag’s Pedagogy of the Gimmick
  27. The Feelings We Feel: Care and Community in Mister Rogers’ Neighborhood
  28. Violence, Wars, and the Possibility of Ethical Life in an Apocalypse: A Kantian Reading of The Walking Dead
  29. On the Fear of the Void and Killing Babies in Pascal, Nabokov, and Game of Thrones
  30. 2. Technological Imagination
  31. Posthumanist Solidarity: The Political and Ethical Imaginations of Artificial Intelligence from Battlestar Galactica to Raised by Wolves
  32. The Dialogic Expansion of Garcia’s We: Chronotopes, Ethics, and Politics in The Expanse Series
  33. Ethics and Technology: An Analysis of Rick and Morty
  34. 3. Ontology and Genres
  35. Rewatching, Film, and New Television
  36. From Episodic Novel to Serial TV: The Handmaid’s Tale, Adaptation and Politics
  37. Series Under Threat
  38. New Screen Economies and Viewing Paradigms: The Ethics of Representation in Delhi Crime
  39. 4. TV Series as Political Weapons
  40. Television Series as Critical Theories: From Current Identitarianism to Levinas. American Crime, The Sinner, Sharp Objects, Unorthodox
  41. Black Earth Rising and Queen Sono: A Critical Decolonial Analysis
  42. Diversity, Identity, Oppression: The Construction of “Blackness” in Dear White People
  43. The Handmaid’s Tale: Reproductive Labour and the Social Embeddedness of Markets
  44. 5. Security Series
  45. The Bureau and the Realism of Spy Fiction
  46. The Veteran Reintegrated in You’re the Worst and One Day at a Time
  47. Topical issue: Home and Exile - Feminist Philosophy in Thought, History and Action: A Multi-Disciplinary Approach, edited by Nicole des Bouvrie and Laura Hellsten - Part II
  48. A Bite of the Forbidden Fruit: The Abject of Food and Affirmative Environmental Ethics
  49. A Phenomenological Look at the Orgasm Gap
  50. Home and Exile – Dancing in the Mess of Contradictions
  51. Selfhood in Question: The Ontogenealogies of Bear Encounters
  52. Epistemology, Political Perils and the Ethnocentrism Problem in Feminism
  53. Regular Articles
  54. Attentional Structure and Phenomenal Unity
  55. Divergences and Convergences of Perspective: Amerindian Perspectivism, Phenomenology, and Speculative Realism
  56. Second-Order Recursions of First-Order Cybernetics: An “Experimental Epistemology”
  57. On Truth and Lie in the Object-Oriented Sense
  58. “It’s Time for a Rent Strike”: COVID-19 Rent Strikes and the Absence of State Care
  59. Adversarial Democracy and the Flattening of Choice: A Marcusian Analysis of Sen’s Capability Theory’s Reliance Upon Universal Democracy as a Means for Overcoming Inequality
  60. The “Slicing Problem” for Computational Theories of Consciousness
Downloaded on 17.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/opphil-2022-0206/html
Scroll to top button