Startseite First things first: The pragmatics of “natural order”
Artikel
Lizenziert
Nicht lizenziert Erfordert eine Authentifizierung

First things first: The pragmatics of “natural order”

  • Laurence Horn

    Laurence Horn is Professor Emeritus of Linguistics and Philosophy at Yale University. He is the author of A Natural History of Negation (Chicago, 1989; CSLI, 2001) and over 100 papers and handbook entries on negation, polarity, implicature, presupposition, pragmatic theory, word meaning, grammatical variation, and lying. His PhD dissertation (UCLA, 1972) introduced scalar implicature. His six (co-)edited volumes include The Handbook of Pragmatics (Blackwell, 2004; co-edited with Gregory Ward) and Pragmatics, Truth and Underspecification (Brill, 2018; co-edited with Ken Turner). He is an elected fellow of the Linguistic Society of America and edited the Outstanding Dissertations in Linguistics series (Garland/Routledge).

    EMAIL logo
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 29. Mai 2019
Veröffentlichen auch Sie bei De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

Classical rhetoricians dating back to Aristotle sought to define the principles of natural order that determine priority in sequences, especially in linguistic representations. Among the principles with the widest predictive power for the ancients and their modern heirs are those stating that A can be prior to B “with respect to temporal order”, that A can be prior to B with respect to what is “known or less informative” than what comes later, and that A can be prior to B with respect to what is “better” or “more worthy”. But when and how do these ordering principles influence the form of linguistic sequences, and how are conflicts between the principles resolved? What determines the priority between the principles of priority? What makes “natural order” natural? Drawing on over two millennia of scholarship, we explore the pragmatic motivation for the primary ordering principles, and in particular for those affecting the order of logically symmetric but rhetorically asymmetric conjunctions.

About the author

Laurence Horn

Laurence Horn is Professor Emeritus of Linguistics and Philosophy at Yale University. He is the author of A Natural History of Negation (Chicago, 1989; CSLI, 2001) and over 100 papers and handbook entries on negation, polarity, implicature, presupposition, pragmatic theory, word meaning, grammatical variation, and lying. His PhD dissertation (UCLA, 1972) introduced scalar implicature. His six (co-)edited volumes include The Handbook of Pragmatics (Blackwell, 2004; co-edited with Gregory Ward) and Pragmatics, Truth and Underspecification (Brill, 2018; co-edited with Ken Turner). He is an elected fellow of the Linguistic Society of America and edited the Outstanding Dissertations in Linguistics series (Garland/Routledge).

Acknowledgements

“First Things First” was presented at Pragmasophia 2 (Lisbon, 2018). Earlier versions were given at CIL 19 (Geneva, 2013), at the CUNY Pragmatics Workshop: Relevance, Game Theory, and Communication (2014), at AMPRA [American Pragmatics Association] 2 (UCLA, 2014), and the University of Cologne (2016). I thank (better late than never!) the audiences at those presentations (and in particular Istvan Kecskes, Klaus von Heusinger, and Petra Schumacher) as well as Barbara Abbott, Mira Ariel, Betty Birner, Bob Frank, Michael Israel, Paul Kay, Gregory Ward, and Ben Zimmer for judgments, discussion, and encouragement. Empirical work on reverse substitute was supported in part by NSF grant BCS-1423872: The Microsyntax of Pronouns in North American English; thanks to Jim Wood and Raffaella Zanuttini, and other collaborators on the grant. I am indebted to the American Dialect Society e-mail list, the Yale Grammatical Diversity group, and the participants in the University of Geneva winter school (Dec. 2015) in Macolin, Switzerland for data and feedback and to Arnold Zwicky and David Denison for helpful guidance. Thanks to Huber (1974), a work I have not been able to consult, for providing the Section § 4 header. Last but not least (#not least but last), everyone but me is absolved of any errors.

References

Abraham, Richard. 1950. Fixed order of coordinates: A study in comparative lexicography. Modern Language Journal 34. 276–287.10.1111/j.1540-4781.1950.tb06011.xSuche in Google Scholar

Anscombre, Jean-Claude & Oswald Ducrot. 1983. L’argumentation dans la langue. Bruxelles: Pierre Mardaga.Suche in Google Scholar

Aristotle. 1957. Prior and posterior analytics, ed. W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon.Suche in Google Scholar

Aristotle. 1963. Categories and de interpretatione, ed. and trans. J. L. Ackrill. Oxford: Clarendon Press.10.1093/oseo/instance.00258580Suche in Google Scholar

Asher, Nicholas & Alex Lascarides. 2003. Logics of Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Bach, Kent. 1999. The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy 22. 327–366.10.1023/A:1005466020243Suche in Google Scholar

Barker, Stephen. 2003. Truth and conventional implicature. Mind 112. 1–33.10.1093/mind/112.445.1Suche in Google Scholar

Behagel, Otto. 1932. Deutsche Syntax: Eine geschichtliche Darstellung. vol. 4. Heidelberg: C. Winter.Suche in Google Scholar

Benor, Sarah Bunin & Roger Levy. 2006. The chicken or the egg? A probabilistic analysis of English binomials. Language 82. 233–278.10.1353/lan.2006.0077Suche in Google Scholar

Bergen, Benjamin & Madelaine Plauché. 2005. The convergent evolution of radial constructions: French and English deictics and existentials. Cognitive Linguistics 16. 1–42.10.1515/cogl.2005.16.1.1Suche in Google Scholar

Biberauer, Theresa & Michelle Sheehan (eds.). 2014. Theoretical approaches to disharmonic word order. Oxford: Oxford U. Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199684359.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar

Brown, Benjamin. 2014. “But me no buts”: The theological debate between the Hasidim and the Mitnagdim in light of the discourse-markers theory. Numen 61. 525–551.10.1163/15685276-12341341Suche in Google Scholar

Carston, Robyn. 1988. Implicature, explicature, and truth-theoretic semantics. In R. Kempson (ed.), Mental representations: The interface between language and reality, 155–181. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Carston, Robyn. 1993. Conjunction, explanation, and relevance. Lingua 90. 27–48.10.1016/0024-3841(93)90059-6Suche in Google Scholar

Clark, Eve. 1970. How young children describe events in time. In G. Flores d’Arcais & W. Levelt (eds.), Advances in psycholinguistics, 275–284. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Suche in Google Scholar

Cohen, L. Jonathan. 1971. Some remarks on Grice’s views about the logical particles of natural language. In Y. Bar-Hillel (ed.), Pragmatics of Natural Language, 50–68. Dordrecht: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-010-1713-8_3Suche in Google Scholar

Cooper, William & John Robert Ross. 1975. World order. In R. E. Grossman et al. (eds.), Papers from the parasession on functionalism, 63–111. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.Suche in Google Scholar

de Jonge, Casper. 2008. Between grammar and rhetoric: Dionysius of Halicarnassus on language, linguistics and literature. Leiden: Brill.10.1163/ej.9789004166776.i-456Suche in Google Scholar

de Nebrija, Antonio 1492. Gramática de la lengua castellana. http://www.antoniodenebrija.org/libro4.html.Suche in Google Scholar

Denison, David. 2009. Argument structure. In G. Rohdenburg & J. Schlüter (eds.), One language, two grammars? Differences between British and American English, 149–165. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.10.1017/CBO9780511551970.008Suche in Google Scholar

Dionysius of Halicarnassus. 1910. On literary composition. W. Rhys Roberts, ed. & trans. London: Macmillan & Co.Suche in Google Scholar

Dionysius of Halicarnassus. 1937. The Roman antiquities of Dionysius of Halicarnassus, vol. I, E. Cary, trans. Cambridge, MA: Loeb Classical Library.10.4159/DLCL.dionysius_halicarnassus-roman_antiquities.1937Suche in Google Scholar

Dunlop, Casey 2015. Processed meat and cancer—What you need to know. Cancer research UK blog, October 26, 2015. (http://tinyurl.com/nssjnpn).Suche in Google Scholar

Dummett, Michael. 1973. Frege: Philosophy of language. Oxford: Duckworth.Suche in Google Scholar

Ernst, Thomas. 1994. Conditions on Chinese A-not-A questions. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 3. 241–264.10.1007/BF01733065Suche in Google Scholar

Fenk-Oczlon, Gertrud. 1989. Word frequency and word order in freezes. Linguistics 27. 517–556.10.1515/ling.1989.27.3.517Suche in Google Scholar

Firbas, Jan. 1992. Functional sentence perspective in written and spoken communication. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.10.1017/CBO9780511597817Suche in Google Scholar

Frege, Gottlob. 1892. On sense and reference 1952. In P. Geach & M. Black (eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of gottlob frege, 56–78. Oxford: Blackwell.Suche in Google Scholar

Geoffrey of Vinsauf. 1967 [original c. 1200]. Poetria Nova. Translated by Margaret Nims. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.Suche in Google Scholar

Gómez Txurruka, Isabel. 2003. The natural language conjunction ‘and’. Linguistics and Philosophy 26. 255–285.10.1023/A:1024117423963Suche in Google Scholar

Greenberg, Joseph. 1963. Some universals of grammar with particular reference to the order of meaningful elements. In J. Greenberg (ed.), Universals of Language, 73–113. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Grice, H. P. 1981. Presupposition and conversational implicatures. In P. Cole (ed.), Radical pragmatics, 183–198. New York: Academic Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Grice, H. P. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Haiman, John. 1985. Symmetry. In J. Haiman (ed.), Iconicity in syntax, 73–95. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/tsl.6.05haiSuche in Google Scholar

Haspelmath, Martin. 2006. Against markedness (and what to replace it with). Journal of Linguistics 42. 25–70.10.1017/S0022226705003683Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence 1972. On the semantics of logical operators in English. UCLA dissertation.Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Reissue edition, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information, 2001.Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 1991. Given as new: When redundant affirmation isn’t. Journal of Pragmatics 15. 313–336.10.1016/0378-2166(91)90034-USuche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 2000. Pick a theory (not just any theory): Indiscriminatives and the free-choice indefinite. In L. Horn & Y. Kato (eds.), Negation and polarity: Syntactic and semantic perspectives, 147–192. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 2011. Almost forever. In E. Yuasa, T. Bagchi & K. Beals (eds.), Pragmatics and autolexical grammar in honor of Jerry Sadock, 3–21. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/la.176.01horSuche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 2013. I love me some datives: Expressive meaning, free datives, and F-implicature. In D. Gutzmann & H.-M. Gärtner (eds.), Beyond expressives: Explorations in use-conditional meaning, 151–198. Leiden: Brill.10.1163/9789004183988_006Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 2016. Information structure and the landscape of (non-)at-issue meaning. In C. Féry & S. Ishihara (eds.), Oxford handbook of information structure, 108–127. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Horn, Laurence. 2019. Accept new substitutes: An analysis of reanalysis. In C. Condoravdi & T. H. King (eds.), Tokens of meaning: Papers in honor of Lauri Karttunen. Stanford: CSLI.Suche in Google Scholar

Huber, T. E. 1974. Law and order for binomials. Ôbun Ronsô 5. 61–74.Suche in Google Scholar

Jakobson, Roman. 1965. Quest for the essence of language. Diogenes 51. 21–37.10.1515/9783110873269.345Suche in Google Scholar

Kehler, Andrew. 2001. Coherence, reference and the theory of grammar. Stanford: CSLI.Suche in Google Scholar

King, Jeffrey & Jason Stanley. 2005. Semantics, pragmatics, and the role of semantic content. In Z. Szabó (ed.), Semantics versus pragmatics, 111–164. Oxford: Oxford U. Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251520.003.0005Suche in Google Scholar

Law, Ann. 2001. A-not-A questions in Cantonese. University College London Working Papers in Linguistics 13. 295–318.Suche in Google Scholar

Lepore, Ernie & Matthew Stone. 2015. Imagination and convention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198717188.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar

Levelt, Willem J. M. 1981. The speaker’s linearization problem. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Series B 295. 305–315.10.1098/rstb.1981.0142Suche in Google Scholar

Levelt, Willem J. M. 1989. Speaking: From intention to articulation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Lohmann, Arne. 2014. English coordinate constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.10.1017/CBO9781139644273Suche in Google Scholar

Malkiel, Yakov. 1959. Studies in irreversible binomials. Lingua 8. 113–160.10.1016/0024-3841(59)90018-XSuche in Google Scholar

Masini, Francesca. 2006. Binominal constructions: Inheritance, specification, and subregularities. Lingue e Linguaggio 5. 207–232.Suche in Google Scholar

McDonald, Janet, Kathryn Bock & Michael Kelly. 1993. Word and world order: Semantic, phonological, and metrical determinants of serial position. Cognitive Psychology 25. 188–230.10.1006/cogp.1993.1005Suche in Google Scholar

Merin, Arthur. 1999. Information, relevance, and social decisionmaking. In L. Moss, et al. (ed.), Logic, language and computation, vol. 2, 179–221. Stanford: CSLI.Suche in Google Scholar

Miller, Casey & Kate Swift. 1976. Words and women. Garden City: Anchor Books.10.2307/3346175Suche in Google Scholar

Mollin, Sandra. 2012. Revisiting binomial order in English: Ordering constraints and reversibility. English Language and Linguistics 16. 81–103.10.1017/S1360674311000293Suche in Google Scholar

Morgan, Jerry. 1969. On the treatment of presupposition in transformational grammar. CLS 5. 167–177.Suche in Google Scholar

Morris, Charles. 1938. Foundations of the Theory of Signs. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Oesterle, Jean. 1962. Aristotle: On interpretation. Commentary by St Thomas and Cajetan. (ed. and trans.). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Osgood, Charles. 1980. Lectures on language performance. New York: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-642-87289-1Suche in Google Scholar

Peirce, C. S. 1960. Elements of logic. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (eds.), Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. II. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Pinker, Stephen & David Birdsong. 1979. Speakers‘ sensitivity to rules of frozen word order. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 18. 497–508.10.1016/S0022-5371(79)90273-1Suche in Google Scholar

Potts, Christopher. 2005. The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford U. Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199273829.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar

Prince, Ellen. 1992. The ZPG letter: Subjects, definiteness, and information-status. In W. Mann & S. Thompson (eds.), Discourse description: Diverse linguistic analyses of a fund-raising text, 295–326. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/pbns.16.12priSuche in Google Scholar

Quintilian = Quintilianus, Marcus Fabius. Institutio Oratoria. H.E. Butler, trans. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard U. Press, 1920.Suche in Google Scholar

Ray, Debraj ⓡ Arthur Robson. 2018. Certified random: A new order for coauthorship. American Economic Review 108. 489–520.10.1257/aer.20161492Suche in Google Scholar

Roberts, Craige. 2012. Information structure: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics 5 (6). 1–69.10.3765/sp.5.6Suche in Google Scholar

Roelofsen, Floris, Sam van Gool, et al. 2010. Disjunctive questions, intonation, and highlighting. In M. Aloni (ed.), Papers from the 17th Amsterdam Colloquium, 384–394. Berlin: Springer.10.1007/978-3-642-14287-1_39Suche in Google Scholar

Sacks, Norman. 1984. Antonio de Nebrija: Founder of Spanish linguistics. Hispanic Linguistics 1. 19–33.Suche in Google Scholar

Schmerling, Susan. 1975. Asymmetric conjunction and rules of conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, 211–232. New York: Academic Press.10.1163/9789004368811_009Suche in Google Scholar

Sobkowiak, Wlodzimierz. 1993. Unmarked-before-marked as a freezing principle. Language and Speech 36. 393–414.10.1177/002383099303600403Suche in Google Scholar

Stalnaker, Robert. 1974. Pragmatic presupposition. In M. Munitz & P. Unger (eds.), Semantics and philosophy, 197–214. New York: New York University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Strawson, P. F. 1952. Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen.Suche in Google Scholar

Tai, James. 1985. Temporal sequence and Chinese word order. In J. Haiman (ed.), Iconicity in syntax, 49–72. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/tsl.6.04taiSuche in Google Scholar

Urmson, J. O. 1959. Philosophical analysis: Its development between the two wars. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Ward, Gregory & Julia Hirschberg. 1991. A pragmatic analysis of tautological utterances. Journal of Pragmatics 15. 507–520.10.1016/0378-2166(91)90109-BSuche in Google Scholar

Weil, Henri. 1991 [1844]. De l’ordre des mots dans les langues anciennes comparées aux langues modernes. Reprinted Paris: Didier erudition.Suche in Google Scholar

Wedgwood, Daniel 1999. Approaches to weight, information and word order. In E. Chisarik & I. Sitaridou (eds.), Proceedings of the Eighth University of Manchester Postgraduate Conference in Linguistics. Downloadable at http://www.lel.ed.ac.uk/~dan/.Suche in Google Scholar

Wilson, Deirdre. 1975. Presupposition and non-truth-conditional semantics. New York: Academic Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Wilson, Deirdre & Dan Sperber. 1998. Pragmatics and time. In R. Carston & S. Uchida (eds.), Relevance theory: Applications and implications, 1–22. Amsterdam: Benjamins.10.1075/pbns.37.03wilSuche in Google Scholar

Winterstein, Gregoire. 2012. What but-sentences argue for: An argumentative analysis of but. Lingua 122. 1864–1885.10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.014Suche in Google Scholar

Wright, Saundra, Jennifer Hay & Tessa Bent. 2005. Ladies first? Phonology, frequency, and the naming conspiracy. Linguistics 43. 531–561.10.1515/ling.2005.43.3.531Suche in Google Scholar

Zwicky, Arnold 2012. Two remarks on reversals. Blog entry, April 28, 2012. http://arnoldzwicky.org/2012/04/28/two-remarks-on-reversals/.Suche in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2019-05-29
Published in Print: 2019-05-27

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Heruntergeladen am 13.10.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/ip-2019-0013/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen