Startseite Extending the Private Language Argument
Artikel Öffentlich zugänglich

Extending the Private Language Argument

Meaning-making and the material context for signification
  • Marcin Trybulec

    Marcin Trybulec (b. 1980) is an Assistant Professor at Maria Curie-Skłodowska University. His research interests include epistemology of cognitive artefacts, literacy theory, and philosophy of language and communication. His publications include “How the ‘Extended Mind’ thesis helps to solve a fundamental dilemma of literacy theory” (2013), “Bridging the gap between writing and cognition” (2013), “External representations reconsidered: Against reification of cognitive extensions” (2017), “Rationality in the material world” (2018).

    EMAIL logo
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 21. November 2019
Veröffentlichen auch Sie bei De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

The paper poses the question of how the use of external artifacts contributes to the stabilization of meaning and thought. On the basis of the private language argument and the problem of objective meaning, I argue that Wittgenstein’s considerations regarding meaning-making should be sensitive to how materiality bears on the interactions with semiotic artifacts produced in speech and writing. The distributed language perspective and the concept of languaging (Cowley 2011, 2007; Steffensen 2011) is then linked to a metacognitive theory of writing (Goody 1977; Olson 1994, 2016) to clarify how social and material settings contribute to the lived experience and metalinguistic awareness that is essential to meaning-making. It is argued that, if material characteristics of symbolizations change metalinguistic awareness, the interpretation of the private language argument partly depends on the types of external artifacts the private linguist is allowed to exploit. The frameworks of distributed language and the theory of writing thus shed new light on the private language argument by making it even more radical than has previously been assumed.

1 Introduction

The main character in Molière’s The Bourgeois Gentleman, Mr. Jourdain, takes philosophy lessons where, to his surprise, he discovers that he has spent his life speaking prose. He says to his philosophy teacher: “For more than forty years I have been speaking prose without knowing anything about it, and I am much obliged to you for having taught me that” (Molière 2001 [1670], act II, scene IV). On the one hand, this ludicrous statement discloses Mr. Jourdain’s ignorance. On the other, it suggests that philosophical thinking about language is biased by how literacy practices are imposed on ordinary talk in interaction. This bias is challenged by a distributed perspective that highlights the dynamic, bodily, and interactive nature of common linguistic acts (Kravchenko 2009; Linell 2004; Steffensen 2011). Those taking a distributed view pay special attention to languaging as an aspect of social coordination (Cowley 2009, 2019) that permeates the whole of language. Tracing languaging to interaction and dialogue is entirely compatible with Wittgenstein’s concepts of meaning as use and his focus on language games.

While this is clear, what is less obvious is how the dialogical and interactive nature of languaging, in turn, bears on considerations about private language. In the private language argument, it is convincingly shown that the mental contents required by linguistic meanings can only be stabilized by a historical and social process. Wittgenstein questions two deep philosophical assumptions: First, he denies that private mental states (i.e. sensations) are self-intelligible. Second, he doubts that the process of meaning-making arises from the individual activity of linking expressions with sensations. To grant stable meaning to an expression, he argues, correctness of subsequent usage must draw on a set of external and publicly shared standards. In order to highlight social coordination, the argument can thus be translated into the claim that there is no meaning-making without a history of interacting. In this way, Wittgenstein’s thought experiment showcases the radical view that a person who lacks socially acquired routines and skills cannot secure the identity of his own thoughts and meanings (Wittgenstein 1953).

However, it seems that Wittgenstein tacitly allows his imagined private linguist to freely create expressions which exhibit consistent modes of use. In other words, he unthinkingly takes for granted that such a person could track their identity over time. If Wittgenstein has good reasons to doubt that, without social context, there is no stability of semiotic relation and mental images, why not push the argument further? Why assume that a private linguist’s expressions can have stability? This might be possible if the private linguist recorded marks in his notebook – as is indeed suggested in Wittgenstein’s argument (Wittgenstein 1953: 92–94). Taking it to the extreme, Wittgenstein might be said to proceed like Mr. Jourdain’s philosophy teacher. In presenting his case he tacitly invites the reader of the Investigations to take for granted that a private linguist is a literate person.

In what follows, I slightly change the parameters of Wittgenstein’s thought experiment. I do so by proposing a private linguist who lacks the literacy skills that are needed to write marks in a notebook. Changing the settings of the private language argument opens up interconnected questions. How does the process of meaning-making change if the private linguist lacks an educated adult’s awareness of language and thought? How could s/he ensure that s/he attends to the same aspect of her/his vocalization in subsequent repetitions of original act of vocalizing? I will argue that considering the materiality of signification – i.e. differences between talk in interaction and writing – can clarify philosophical debate about private language. I examine a general question posed in distributed language framework: How do artifacts impact on the cognitive dynamics of language use? (Cowley 2007, 2019). Later, I refine this general problem by linking the idea of a language stance (Cowley 2011) to a metacognitive theory of writing (Olson 1994, 2016). By so doing, I translate it into a new question: How do material artifacts for signification contribute to the stabilization of meaning and thought?

The paper defends the thesis that philosophical analysis of private language should consider both empirical data and theoretical arguments concerning the materiality of languaging. Accordingly, I briefly introduce the private language argument around the philosophical controversy over the objectivity of linguistic meaning. Next, I use the concept of language stance (Cowley 2011) to indicate areas of discussion about private language that have standardly been overlooked. I will argue that interpretations of private language usually assume that the difference between a stable record and a transient vocalization is inessential in meaning-making, therefore the question about the materiality of signification is left unexplored. Finally, I use the metacognitive theory of writing (Olson 1994, 2016) in detailed explanation of what investigation of materiality can add to standard views of the private language argument. I claim that the metacognitive theory of writing explains that if a private linguist is not a literate person, s/he has limited awareness of autonomous and stable linguistic units and she cannot use this awareness to establish her own private expressions. By linking the concept of the language stance (Cowley 2011) to a metacognitive theory of writing (Olson 1994, 2016) I argue that it is unthinkable that a private linguist could secure the stability of his own vocalizations, and therefore the private language argument should be supplemented by considerations regarding the stability of expressions used in the process of meaning-making. The aim of the paper is not to criticize the private language argument, but to highlight the fact that the argument changes depending on the types of languaging one considers as paradigmatic.

2 The problem of objective meaning and private language argument

One of the basic problems in the philosophy is: “How can linguistic meaning exist?” On this issue, there are two opposing perspectives. The first is represented by a philosophy that appeals to an ideal language in which meaning consists of a relation between a linguistic sign and an abstract or real – material or mental – object to which the sign refers. The important thing is that the object (e.g. a mental image) exists independently of words or signs associated with it. In this appoach, the meaning of a linguistic expression is logically prior to its use (Devlin 1997; Prechtl 1999). Since meaning is conceived independently of the use of a sign, a competent language user must necessarily possess prior knowledge about the relation which holds between a sign and its referent.

The second perspective on linguistic meaning is a pragmatically oriented philosophy of language (Prechtl 1999). Criticism of an ideal language starts by demonstrating that the descriptive function of language – treated as essential in modern philosophy – is merely a case of use. Thus, for Wittgenstein (1953), Malinowski (1923), and Austin (1975) the descriptive function of language is an extremely specialized form of use that is typical of highly literate cultures. In fact, the ideal language view also adopts the often-criticized code model of language. Here criticism focuses on how code models reduce dynamic linguistic meaning to static knowledge of a connection between a mental image and corresponding linguistic pattern that is allegedly independent of use in actual situations (Kravchenko 2009; Love 2007; Sperber and Wilson 1996; Steffensen 2011). One of the key arguments against the concept of objective meanings introduced by pragmatically oriented views of language thus builds on the observation that meaning is fundamentally dependent on situational and social context. For these philosophers, therefore, linguistic meaning is unthinkable without instances of use (Prechtl 1999).

Debate between the philosophy of ideal language and its pragmatic rival is usually pursued in purely philosophical terms. Those on both sides of the debate typically draw on conceptual analysis and thought experiments. Empirical data are taken to be of secondary importance. In what follows, I show the contrary. In using the example of the private language argument, I show how developments in psychology and linguistics can both expand and clarify this philosophical debate. I use empirical data to draw an analogy between the situation of the private linguist and that of a baby learning to speak. This interpretative procedure enables the tacitly accepted assumption that private linguist is a literate person to be highlighted. The concept of language stance and metacognitive theory of writing can explain why the assumption of literacy of a private linguist matters. Before I present the main argument, I will sketch two standard approaches to private language. Description of the standard interpretations of private language is not aimed to argue for or against Wittgenstein’s view, but simply helps indicate that in these cases discussion on materiality of signification is left unexplored.

Wittgenstein's private language argument has both wide and narrow interpretations (Glock 1996; Prechtl 2004). The interpretations offer different angles on the private language argument. While the first reading addresses the identity of two mental images in time and the problem of stable memory, the second shows the absurd consequences of invoking a private rule. Both interpretations, however, agree that private language is impossible because of the lack of external and shared criteria for identifying both mental images and rules that link a mental picture to an expression

2.1 The problem of a private linguist’s stable memory

In a wide reading of the argument, the focus falls on the nature of the relation between internal mental experience and external linguistic behavior. Wittgenstein regards some external and shared symbols as indispensable to determining the content of private beliefs and, just as importantly, how identity can be maintained over time. He asks whether anyone who is deprived of an ability to externalize thoughts could ever determine whether the content of a thought at time (t1) was identical to the content of supposedly the same thought at a later time (t2)?

What is the criterion for the sameness of two [mental] images? [...] Before I judge that two images which I have are the same, I must recognize them as the same. And when that has happened, how am I to know that the word “same” describes what I recognize? Only if I can express my recognition in some other way, and if it is possible for someone else to teach me that “same” is the correct word here. (Wittgenstein 1953: 117, emphasis added).

Wittgenstein indicates that the mere externalization of thought is actually far from being sufficient to determine how, if at all, thoughts change over time. In fact, if one is to judge the identity of two mental images it is essential that they be externalized and shared by others. To highlight this point, Wittgenstein considers a case where a private linguist invents an arbitrary expression “X” that stands for a feeling S. Having done so, he keeps a diary of the feeling’s subsequent appearances. Every time he experiences S, therefore, he writes the phrase “X” in the diary. The problem is self-evident: in all but the first use of the invented phrase, he has no means of ascertaining that he correctly applies the expression “X” to the original sensation of S. The alleged private linguist would wonder: “I impress on myself the connexion between the sign and the sensation. – But ‘I impress it on myself’ can only mean: this process brings it about that I remember the connexion right in the future. But in the present case I have no criterion of correctness” (Wittgenstein 1953: 92, emphasis added).

It is impossible for the private language creator to be sure whether, at two points of time, his own experience Z is the same. This is because, in such a case, there is no external standard for correct recognition of the experiences’ identity. He may be convinced of having an accurate memory of the original feeling but, if this is so, “whatever is going to seem right to me is right” (Wittgenstein 1953: 92). No mere impression is sufficient for a relation of identity. Wittgenstein stresses that struggling to verify the identity of two mental images without reference to publicly available artifacts is akin to measuring a ruler with itself or, indeed, checking the credibility of a newspaper by comparing two copies of the same issue. If one had an excellent eidetic memory, one might preserve the original mental picture as the basis for making justified judgments about the identity of subsequent experiences. This would be like superimposing two photographic pictures in order to determine whether or not they differ. Since memory does not work that way, the original mental image cannot be accepted as a golden standard for recognizing identity. It is concluded, therefore that an external, publicly available criterion of identity is necessary to stabilize and objectify mental images. The moral of the story about the private linguist’s diary is that mental contents can only be co-constructed by acts amenable to public evaluation. On this view any appeal to mental content that is independent of social coordination is mere philosophical illusion (Candlish and Wrisley 2014).

2.2 Why a private linguist cannot follow a rule

The second, narrow interpretation of Wittgenstein’s argument pursues the issue of rule-following. While the wide interpretation challenges the intelligible use of the signs of a private language, the narrow interpretation maintains that there is no way in which private signs can be created. The argument boils down to answering the question of why it is impossible to follow a rule when a person is separated from other people and thus deprived of access to a public language (Kenny 2005). By definition, a private language consists of “sounds which no one else understands but which I 'appear to understand'” (Wittgenstein 1953: 94). For others, therefore, a private language is unintelligible. The key point here is that the language would also be unintelligible to the inventor. Why is that? In order to make sense of a sign – Wittgenstein claims –it needs to be used according to some kind of rule. The person who aims to invent a private language – the argument goes – must begin by defining the first word. Defining the first word in a private language would entail creating a stable conventional relation between an expression “X” and some mental event S. What would grant the stability of this conventional relation in the expression’s subsequent uses? For this to be possible, a private linguist would subsequently have to use the original conventional relation to link the expression “X” to the mental event Z by drawing on a rule allowing him or her to judge the correctness of each use of the expression. If the expression “X” once refers to S and on other occasions to mental states A, B or C..., “X” would be meaningless even for its alleged user. Therefore, if a private language user is to make sense of a sign, he or she must necessarily conform with a rule because only such conformity can ensure stability of the original relation between the expression and the mental state in the sign’s subsequent use (Candlish and Wrisley 2014; Glock 1996).

Wittgenstein argues that the idea of the private rule does not make sense. For the rule to be private, he argues, no publicly shared criterion can be used in judging whether or not the rule is being followed. However, without external criteria for following a rule, the only possible standard is a person’s private conviction. On such a view, a person’s internal conviction about rule-following becomes indistinguishable from actual rule-following. This conclusion leads to entrapment in a category mistake because, by definition, following a rule belongs to a different epistemic and ethical category than thinking that a rule is being obeyed. In other words, Wittgenstein’s argument suggests that when a private language user thinks that he follows the rule, he would follow the rule and that this would hold regardless of whether or not he actually follows the rule. The result is plainly absurd. If, by definition, the private linguist cannot draw on shared rules, social coordination, and external artifacts, nobody – not even a private linguist – can know whether a rule is actually being followed or whether the meaning applied to an expression in a given situation is correct (or not). In this case, private language is unintelligible for its user. There is no way to ascertain that the meaning he applies to the expression “X” in a particular situation is the same as the original meaning of this expression. In consequence, a private language user cannot possibly know what an expression he utters actually means. For this reason, not only the use but also the invention of a private language expression appears to be impossible (Glock 1996; Prechtl 2004).

Wittgenstein reflects upon two aspects of meaning-making: he both challenges the internal mental picture and appeals to a semiotic relation between a mental picture and its expression (Candlish and Wrisley 2014; Glock 1996). The third aspect of meaning-making – the materiality of signification is left unexplored. Apparently, any difference between a stable record and talk in interaction is assumed inessential in meaning-making. The difference is neglected because it is assumed that our engagement with materiality can be left out. For instance, while discussing possible uses of private expressions, Wittgenstein’s analysis depends almost exclusively on literacy practices such as keeping a diary, checking a timetable or calendar, or looking at a watch. This applies in spite of the fact that he attempts to define a private language in terms of speech sounds (Wittgenstein 1953: 92–94). Accordingly, three interconnected considerations of private language come to the fore: memorizing mental images, creating a stable practice of using a sign, and the need for an external, independent standard for individual impressions. Given that problems of memorization, stability, externality, and independency drive discussion about distinct semiotic and cognitive functions of speech and writing (Kravchenko 2009; Olson 1996; Trybulec 2013, 2017), one can ask whether considering different modes of presenting linguistic patterns (or even “kinds of linguistic activity”) brings new insight on the private language argument. Wittgenstein seems to take a graphic mode of signification as a core of linguistic practice. In so doing, he leaves the distinction between talk in interaction and writing aside. This is because the materiality of signification is considered insignificant. If one acknowledges fundamental differences between graphic and vocal meaning-making, a new question emerges. How, if at all, is the private language argument affected by taking the materiality of linguistic activity seriously?

3 Radicalizing the private language argument

My hypothesis is that the problems diagnosed by Wittgenstein in relation to mental images and rule-following have parallels with ones bearing on a private linguist’s vocalizations. If a spoken language environment is the proper context for his thought experiment, then the position of the preliterate private linguist is more difficult than the situation of the person keeping a diary. First, as noted, Wittgenstein shows that a private linguist cannot know either whether his original mental image changes over time or whether a rule he introduces comes to be used consistently. In parallel, I will now argue that the private linguist could not secure the identity of an oral expression of a mental image. In short, what Wittgenstein argues for linguistic meaning would also apply to linguistic form. If this is so, it follows that skepticism about rule-following and memorizing a mental image should be extended. One must ask: What is the source of identity of expressions uttered by private linguist? Taking this question seriously radicalizes standard interpretations of the private language argument. In pursuing this approach, I show how a distributed perspective on language emphasizes Stephen Cowley’s (2011) concept of a language stance and how this relates to David Olson’s (1994, 2016) metacognitive theory of writing.

3.1 Can a private linguist take a language stance?

Those who take a distributed language perspective concur that culture distinguishes human behavior from that of other animals. While animal behavior can be described as biomechanical process, human coordination requires additional explanations that depend on skills with cultural practices and artifacts (Cowley 2007, 2019). Although this may seem quite obvious, the statement’s consequences challenge commonsense views of language and cognition. They fit Wittgenstein’s critique of private language in tracing meaning-making to real-time social coordination that creates shared meaning spaces. This view rules out any possibility that the meaning of linguistic expressions derives from stable or private mental images. Indeed, if mental images or sensations are not self-intelligible, how can we seem to make sense of them? Both Wittgenstein and those taking a distributed language perspective trace mental phenomena and their meaning to sharable practices of coordination that arise from continuous coupling between producing expressions and generating reactions. Shareability is thus essential to meaning-making. On such a view, it is inconceivable that an individual could ever identify mental states without reference to the cultural and material resources that become familiar during socialization.

Wittgenstein’s private language argument leaves aside how children are socialized into hearing sound as meaningful patterns. If the socialization of hearing is addressed, one is bound to ask how a private linguist could grant identity to his own vocal expressions? In approaching this issue, I treat the situation of the private linguist as analogous to that of a baby learning to speak. A private linguist, like an infant early in semiotic development, cannot secure the meaning of expressions without shared practices that provide external criteria for correct vocalizations. Just like an infant deprived of participation in social routines, a private linguist could not know what s/he is referring to in naming ambiguous and fluid impressions or feelings. Moreover, without following a social rule, he or she could not use an ostensive definition to create a meaningful relation between expression and mental content. So, what is learned from comparing the situation of an infant to that of a private linguist? In early development, infants lack the ability to recognize a fluent stream of speech as consisting of meaningful and stable patterns. Learning to hear continuous vocalizations in terms of discrete patterns is necessary for granting identity to any vocalization. Cowley (2011) denies that physical resemblance is sufficient for recognizing the identity of what adults can hear as two vocalizations of the “same” pattern. This is because utterances are ambiguous, rather as are pictures in a Rorschach test. For example, in the first card of the Rorschach test the observer can recognize a moth or a cat or some other living or imaginary creature. However, this does not mean that the picture really contains a figure of a moth or a cat or indeed of any other shape. While there are more and less common associations, there is no one correct interpretation. The inkblot itself contains no figure and, for this reason, perceiving an inkblot derives from personal and cultural associations that allow one to project distinctive features of some entities on the inkblot (Cowley 2011). Further evidence for the claim that pictures do not contain ready-made objects can be drawn from the case of a Necker cube. The observer of this wireframe drawing, which lacks any visual cues that determine whether its front consists of a lower-left or upper-right square, constantly switches between different views and, by so doing, produces the illusion of a moving image. The point is that the physical structure of the Necker cube is not, of itself, sufficient to determine the correct interpretation of what is seen.

Cowley (2011: 11–15) argues that, like picture perception, speech perception draws on ambiguous stimuli. In both cases the process of construction is needed to perceive genuinely ambiguous stimuli in relation to relevant features. Figures and shapes perceived in pictures – like a moth or a cat in a Rorschach test – are not objects in any standard sense because they lack existence independently of the perceiver. Cowley (2011) uses Gibson’s term “a virtual object” to distinguish between regular objects and patterns constructed in the flow of perception. A moth in the Rorschach test or a particular view of the Necker cube are thus virtual objects.

The same applies to hearing a continuous and ambiguous stream of linguistic vocalization as a verbal pattern. On this view, the virtual objects are irreducible to the physical structure of sounds. Depending on how a person’s attending and hearing have been socialized, various objects will be identified. For Cowley, this is central to learning to hear virtual objects as part of vocalizing. The process of training a special attitude toward talk in interaction aimed at mastering a kind of listening that enables infants to discover virtual objects in the flow of vocalizations is called taking a language stance. Just as in the case of interpreting ambiguous figures, no pre-linguistic child could know in advance how to correctly map patterns onto features of vocalization. In fact, an infant cannot even realize that there are relevant features, since one and the same vocalization can be heard around different acoustic patterns. To discover regularities and stable patterns in speech, babies have to develop a special way of attending to speech sounds. Learning to hear vocalizations in terms of the language stance arises from attending to virtual objects.

Progress in recognizing virtual objects depends on participation in a rich environment of social routines. Since this presupposes a history of enacting social interactions, taking a language stance is a genuinely social competence (Cowley 2011: 16–18). Language stance can be at times conceived as similar to Dennett’s intentional stance (Dennett 1987). They both are conceptualized in terms of attitudes directed to identify virtual aspects of observed phenomena. Ascribing behavior with beliefs and desires is in a sense analogous to distinguishing virtual patterns in the flow of vocalizations. However, if we agree with Wittgenstein’s private language argument, an intentional stance seems to be groundless without the language stance. As Wittgenstein claims, there are no stable and therefore predictable mental phenomena without social interactions that serve as scaffoldings for the standardization of mental states. A private linguist cannot take an intentional stance just because he would not know to what s/he is referring to in naming ambiguous desires and beliefs. In order to secure stability and predictability of mental states, an intentional stance must be grounded in social coordination that ensures normative standards for taking a language stance.

Why does the language stance matter for the private language argument? In brief, infants have to hear speech sounds in a special way if they are to attribute identity to a caregiver’s vocalizations. This is a necessary condition if children are to gain the skills that are needed for linguistic and many other kinds of social competency. If taking a language stance must derive from engaging in social routines, a private linguist who had no opportunity to enact such a routine would not hear his own vocalizations as stable verbal units. As Cowley (2011) argues, taking a language stance serves as a kind of attention scaffolding that enables an infant to discover the verbal listening needed to recognize virtual objects in the vocalizations of their caregivers and themselves. Something analogous applies to the private linguist who has to distinguish virtual patterns in his/her own vocalizations. Wittgenstein forbids his private linguist basic conventions such as ostensive definition in that this would contaminate the sterile conditions of his thought experiment with remnants of public language. By the same token, the private linguist should also be deprived of the possibility of applying a language stance to his/her own vocalizations. With such a move, however, it would become impossible to produce stable expressions at all.

If the constraint appears too radical, one can consider a private linguist who can take a language stance. However, even under this concession, he would still be unable to use his/her original vocalizations consistently. This is because, in creating an expression to name a mental image, the private linguist would need to produce some kind of simple vocal gesture. At the same time, using a language stance, he will attend to one of many virtual objects that vocal gestures can evoke. How will he attend to this virtual object? He will concentrate his attention on some set of features of the sound experience. As Wittgenstein puts it “I concentrate my attention on the sensation – and so, as it were, point to it inwardly” (Wittgenstein 1953: 92, §258). This is roughly a description of taking a language stance. In the context, however, it serves as the standard criticism of the possibility of private ostensive definition (Wittgenstein 1953: 92).

The necessary condition for future correct use of the vocal gesture is that the private linguist will correctly remember the original virtual object attended to during the first use of the vocal gesture. Without external criteria for correct recall, the private linguist cannot ensure that in subsequent uses of a vocal gesture he will attend to the same virtual object as used in the original act of producing the vocalization. If it is possible for the private linguist to misremember the virtual object that he attended to in the original vocalization, he might not really know what exactly he is saying In the absence of external standards for correct repetition, he could not know what aspects of a vocalization are significant by virtue of referring to his own impression. It follows, therefore, that the private linguist is not only unable to secure the identity and stability of his own impressions and definitions, but is also powerless to ensure the identity of his own expressions.

3.2 Why a private linguist has limited metalinguistic awareness

David Olson’s developmental research provides independent support for Cowley’s (2011) abstract view of the language stance. Olson shows that, during individual development, the emergence of the idea of discrete linguistic units and stable meanings depends on acquiring skills in literacy. How does this bear on the abstract considerations regarding private language? Empirical data provided by a metacognitive theory of writing support the wide interpretation of the private language argument in clarifying the relation between an expression and its internal mental contents. Olson shows that the ability to read and write grants children both a new awareness of language and new ways of conceptualizing how thought relates to expression. If Wittgenstein’s private linguist is assumed to be preliterate, his task of securing stable meaning for private expression will be quite different from that of a literate person. Taking a glance at how children gain new linguistic awareness makes it possible to imagine the linguistic awareness of a preliterate private linguist and, thus, how his/her task would differ from that described by Wittgenstein.

Olson allies with the distributed language perspective in rejecting code models of writing and reading (Cowley 2019; Jarvilehto et al. 2009; Kravchenko 2009). He shows that, when children learn to read, they gain a new competence not only to decode graphic symbols, but also to perceive spoken language in the terms presupposed by use of the writing system. The thesis that writing consists of external objects that are easy to refer to – entities known as words, letters, and sentences – may seem trivial. What is less obvious, however, is Olson’s claim that people without written language have limited metalinguistic awareness. This observation can be illustrated by two interconnected claims of special importance for private language argument. First, the systematic practices of embedding spoken expressions into a stable written record grants preliterate children extended phonological and lexical awareness. Second, literacy practices establish new criteria for the identity of linguistic repetition (Olson 1994, 2013, 2016).

Studies on the development of phonetic awareness supports the thesis that alphabetical writing does not reflect preexisting metalinguistic knowledge but, rather, offers a model that seems to enhance recognition of speech-patterns. For example, to recognize the component parts of syllables and perceive words as composed of distinct sounds that can be represented by letters of the alphabet, elementary knowledge of writing is needed. Thus, in the classic task of manipulating phonemes, where participants are asked to remove the initial consonant “w” from the word “water,” for example, preliterate subjects fail (Morais et al. 1986; Read et al. 1986). Simply, literate and preliterate people segment vocalizations differently. This claim confirms and extends Cowley’s (2011) view of the language stance, since it suggests that recognition of virtual objects in the flow of vocalizations depends not only on language acquisition but also on experience with how materiality can be integrated with linguistic practice. Research on lexical awareness provides more details of this process.

Olson shows that literacy practices are also central to perceiving words as autonomous and objectified individual entities that are susceptible to systematic reflection and definition (Olson 2016: 98–114). More specifically, preliterate children confuse a word with a thing denoted or, in other terms, treat them as tokens that are fully integrated with the world. For example, when asked to say a long word, children often identify a long object by saying, for example, “train.” In studies by Homer and Olson (1999) children from 4–6 years of age were presented with the written expression: "Three little pigs." The experimenter read it aloud, and the child was asked to repeat the sentence in order to ensure that it was understood. Then, for example, one of the words was covered and the child was asked: “What do you think the sentence means right now?” Typically, the answer was: “Two little pigs.” Similar studies were conducted in a range of configurations. When the child was asked to pretend to write “Three little pigs,” the child produced three indefinite marks. When asked to write “One little pig,” one mark was made. The results suggest that, for preliterate children, word-tokens are intertwined with reality and can be exchanged for a real thing in a world. The idea of a word as a conventional symbol that can appear in the flow of vocalizations is to be traced to skills derived from learning to write (Homer 2009; Homer and Olson 1999).

Olson suggests that preliterate children lack a clear concept of "word" as an autonomous lexical unit. According to him, there is no evidence that the concept of “word” is universal (Olson 1994). Rather, it is a construct of literate cultures. As indicated by Chafe (1985) words are not basic units of talk in interaction. Rather, the building blocks of utterance last around two seconds, possess a specific intonation contour, and consist of several – five to seven – items to which a speaker can consciously attend. The acquisition of the term “word” arises with writing and reading skills. What is more, the first concept of a word that children acquire is associated with its graphic form.

Social anthropology further supports the link between literate skills and metalinguistic awareness. In investigation of how memory co-evolved with literate culture, Carruthers (1990) stresses that writing should not be conceived as an external storage system for information that would otherwise be stored in individual memory. The real impact of writing consists in creating new standards for memorizing. For Carruthers, whereas preliterate cultures apply loose standards for memorizing, literate societies treat written record or quotation as a model of correct recall. Jack Goody shows something similar: in preliterate cultures, adults fail to distinguish between literal and paraphrased repetitions of a story. This is not because they fail to remember but, rather, because they do not distinguish between a paraphrase and a verbatim repetition (Goody 1977). Developmental psychology delivers even more detailed evidence for tracing the distinction between literal repetition and paraphrase to literacy. Olson (1994: 126–127) and colleagues designed an experiment to show that preliterate children under the age of 6 find it hard to distinguish paraphrase and verbatim repetition. Child participants viewed a puppet theater scene featuring two characters: Big Bird and Teddy Bear. The scene exhibits a situation where Big Bird says a sentence that Teddy Bear repeats either literally or by using paraphrase. Although children between 4 and 5 years of age correctly identify Big Bird’s intentions and thus correctly and incorrectly paraphrase, only those above the age of 6 correctly perform both the paraphrase task and one using verbatim repetition. Anthropological and psychological data indicates that preliterate participants – adults and children – treat different expressions as identical when they have a similar meaning or express the same intentions. Even basic literacy grants participants new criteria for utterance identity: it separates literal meaning from intended meaning or a paraphrase. Olson shows how new criteria for the identity of expressions emerge from practices with external and stable artifacts.

Why does a metacognitive theory of writing clarify the situation of a preliterate private linguist? First, such a linguist lacks awareness of autonomous and stable linguistic units and he cannot use this knowledge in the process of creating his own private expressions. Without picturing a stable word-object, he could never know what aspects of an expression were relevant for a meaning. Indeed, were he outside a social context, he could not know that stable vocal patterns could be heard at all. These conclusions refine arguments based on considerations about the language stance (Cowley 2011). They are further complemented by the second conclusion from the metacognitive theory of writing where preliterates do not differentiate an expression from its referent. If a preliterate private linguist treated expressions as emblems – like children in Olson’s research – he would systematically mix vocal gesture with the impression it was intended to denote. In the extreme case, the vocalization would merge with the impression by creating an amalgamated semiotic structure whose performative functions create a language of magic (Malinowski 1923). Finally, as Wittgenstein stresses, in the process of meaning-making, to stabilize the identity of meaning and mental content one needs outer criteria. If a metacognitive theory of writing is correct, the same argument applies to identity of expression. Indeed, after gaining some experience with written artifacts, as Olson shows, people begin to apply new criteria for utterance identity. Without these, they are unable to distinguish exact and approximate repetition. A private linguist without literacy skills would be unable to ascertain if the subsequent applications of an expression were literal or approximate repetitions. Therefore, s/he would be unable to assure the stability of his/her own vocalizations.

4 Summary

In his original argument, Wittgenstein claims that, without external criteria for correctness, a private linguist could not establish meaning. Such a person would not know whether s/ he was following a rule or referring correctly to an aspect of a mental state. The argument gains additional support from the evidence above. By linking the concept of the language stance (Cowley 2011) to a metacognitive theory of writing (Olson 1994, 2016) I have argued that there is no external and independent standard whereby one can judge the stability of an original vocal gesture. For this reason, it is unthinkable that a private linguist could know what sounds to utter in subsequent attempts to use the “same” vocalization. I conclude, therefore, that standard skepticism about memory and meaning in private language can be extended. My case is that we should include skepticism about the third element in meaning-making – the stability of expression.

Although this extension might not be possible in the case of a private linguist keeping a diary, one should question treating such a linguist as a literate person. If a private linguist cannot use a basic convention like ostensive definition, why should one allow such a person use of conventional writing systems – be they alphabetical, ideographical, or pictorial? The very idea of representing thoughts by stable written marks seems to presuppose the social process of acquiring literacy skills. Both the metacognitive theory of writing and the distributed perspective suggest that awareness of ready-made linguistic patterns cannot be traced to how innate cognitive abilities contribute to individual development Rather, children by socialization and education come to perceive linguistic expressions as stable entities that are susceptible to exact repetition. According to the conditions of Wittgenstein’s own thought experiment, the private linguist would lack a literate culture’s conceptual tools to refer to his own language. The tacit assumption of his literacy seems to be groundless.

Regardless of issues around a private linguist’s literacy, recognizing skepticism about expression depends on what point of reference is used in examining material contexts of signification. Mainstream explanations of how linguistic meaning exists usually appeal to either the ideal language or the language use. Both perspectives take one mode of linguistic activity as the point of reference for the other modes and appeal to disembodied language use leaving out how people engage with materiality. A distributed language framework offers the alternative: the concept of languaging which can serve as a tool for thinking about heterogenous ways of meaning-making depending on material tools for signification. In abstract terms, languaging is described as a skilled activity drawing on a dynamic synthesis of (1) material engagement with (2) ways of attending to and enacting linguistic patterns (Cowley 2019). If one frames the private linguist’s meaning-making in terms of languaging, one cannot help but think seriously how material grounds for signification bear on the dynamics of the private linguist’s engagement with symbolizations and his/her attitudes toward semiotic objects in the environment. Therefore, the concept of languaging invites observing how a private linguist’s meaning-making changes depending on the types of materiality s/he engages with. While using the concept of languaging, it becomes clear that discussion about private language should be sensitive to the dynamics of linguistic engagement with material grounds for signification as well as the plurality of skilled linguistic actions.

Wittgenstein correctly stresses that publicly shared symbolizations are crucial in granting identity and stability to both mental states and meanings. He left aside, however, how external symbolizations draw on materiality. That is why he may have assumed that recognizing verbal patterns in the flow of vocalizations is somehow akin to recording and reading words in a notebook. As argued in the paper, practices with written symbolizations have different cognitive dynamics than talk in interaction. Written symbolizations are a basic factor in developing the notions of both linguistic stability and the possibility of verbatim repetition. For this reason, the private linguist deprived of literate skills, in struggling to secure meaning for his thoughts and vocalizations, has a far more difficult task than the private linguist allowed to use pen and paper and the whole set of metalinguistic concepts associated with the literate skills.

About the author

Marcin Trybulec

Marcin Trybulec (b. 1980) is an Assistant Professor at Maria Curie-Skłodowska University. His research interests include epistemology of cognitive artefacts, literacy theory, and philosophy of language and communication. His publications include “How the ‘Extended Mind’ thesis helps to solve a fundamental dilemma of literacy theory” (2013), “Bridging the gap between writing and cognition” (2013), “External representations reconsidered: Against reification of cognitive extensions” (2017), “Rationality in the material world” (2018).

  1. Note

    The research is supported by National Science Center, Poland, under the grant Understanding Cognitive Artifacts: Towards the Epistemology of Cognitive Extensions, no. 2017/26/D/HS1/00677.

Acknowledgement

In writing this paper I have benefited considerably from inspiration and support from Stephen J. Cowley. I thank also Zuzanna Rucinska for her insightful criticism on an earlier draft of the paper.

References

Austin, John L. 1975. How to do things with words. Oxford: Harvard University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245537.001.0001Suche in Google Scholar

Candlish, Stewart & George Wrisley. 2014. Private language. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2019 edition). At https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/private-language/ (accessed: 05 November 2018).Suche in Google Scholar

Carruthers, Mary. 1990. The book of memory: A study of memory in medieval culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Chafe, Wallace. 1985. Linguistic difference produced by differences between speaking and writing. In David Olson & Nancy Torrance (eds.), Literacy, language and learning: The nature and consequences of reading and writing, 105–124. Cambridge.Suche in Google Scholar

Cowley, Stephen J. 2007. The cognitive dynamics of distributed language. Language Sciences 29(5). 575–583.10.1016/j.langsci.2007.01.002Suche in Google Scholar

Cowley, Stephen J. 2009. Distributed language and dynamics. Pragmatics & Cognition 17(3). 495–508.10.1075/pc.17.3.01cowSuche in Google Scholar

Cowley, Stephen J. 2011. Taking a language stance. Ecological Psychology 23(3). 185–209.10.1080/10407413.2011.591272Suche in Google Scholar

Cowley, Stephen J. 2019. The return of languaging Toward a new ecolinguistics. Chinese Semiotic Studies 15(4). 483–512.10.1515/css-2019-0027Suche in Google Scholar

Dennett, Daniel. 1998. The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Devlin, Keith. 1997. Goodbye, Descartes: The end of logic and the search for a new cosmology of the mind. New York: Wiley.Suche in Google Scholar

Glock, Hans-Johann. 1996. A Wittgenstein dictionary. Oxford, UK ; Cambridge, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.10.1111/b.9780631185376.1996.00001.xSuche in Google Scholar

Goody, Jack. 1977. The domestication of the savage mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Homer, Bruce D. 2009. Literacy and metalinguistic development. In David R. Olson & Nancy Torrance (eds.), The Cambridge handbook of literacy, 487–500. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511609664.027Suche in Google Scholar

Homer, Bruce D. & David R. Olson. 1999. Literacy and children’s conception of words. Written Language & Literacy 2(1). 113–140.10.1075/wll.2.1.07homSuche in Google Scholar

Jarvilehto, Timo, Veli-Matti Nurkkala & Kyösti Koskela. 2009. The role of anticipation in reading. Pragmatics & Cognition 17(3). 509–526.10.1075/pc.17.3.02jarSuche in Google Scholar

Kenny, Anthony. 2005. Wittgenstein. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Suche in Google Scholar

Kravchenko, Alexander V. 2009. The experiential basis of speech and writing as different cognitive domains. Pragmatics & Cognition 17(3). 527–548.10.1075/pc.17.3.03kraSuche in Google Scholar

Linell, Per. 2004. The written language bias in linguistics: Its nature, origins and transformations. London, New York: Routledge.10.4324/9780203342763Suche in Google Scholar

Love, Nigel. 2007. Are languages digital codes? Language Sciences 29(5). 690–709.10.1016/j.langsci.2007.01.008Suche in Google Scholar

Malinowski, Bronislaw. 1923. The problem of meaning in primitive languages. In Charles K. Ogden & Ivor A. Richards (eds.), The meaning of meaning, 296–336. London: K. Paul, Trend, Trubner.Suche in Google Scholar

Molière. 2001. The Middle Class Gentleman. Project Gutenberg. www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/2992#download (accessed: 01 November 2018).Suche in Google Scholar

Morais, Jose, Paul Bertelson, Luz Cary & Jesus Alegria. 1986. Literacy training and speech segmentation. Cognition 24(1). 45–64.10.1016/0010-0277(86)90004-1Suche in Google Scholar

Olson, David R. 1994. The world on paper: The conceptual and cognitive implications of reading and writing. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Suche in Google Scholar

Olson, David R. 1996. Towards a psychology of literacy: on the relations between speech and writing. Cognition 60(1). 83–104.10.1016/0010-0277(96)00705-6Suche in Google Scholar

Olson, David R. 2013. Writing, the discovery of language, and the discovery of mind. Dialogue and Universalism 23(1). 9–14.10.5840/du201323115Suche in Google Scholar

Olson, David R. 2016. The mind on paper: Reading, consciousness and rationality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781316678466Suche in Google Scholar

Prechtl, Peter. 1999. Sprachphilosophie: Lehrbuch Philosophie. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.10.1007/978-3-476-05029-8Suche in Google Scholar

Prechtl, Peter. (ed.). 2004. Grundbegriffe der analytischen Philosophie. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.10.1007/978-3-476-05070-0Suche in Google Scholar

Read, Charles, Yun-Fei Zhang, Hong-Yin Nie & Bao-Qing Ding. 1986. The ability to manipulate speech sounds depends on knowing alphabetic writing. Cognition 24(1). 31–44.10.1016/0010-0277(86)90003-XSuche in Google Scholar

Sperber, Dan & Deirdre Wilson. 1996. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford; Cambridge, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Suche in Google Scholar

Steffensen, Sune. V. 2011. Beyond mind: an extended ecology of languaging. In Stephen J. Cowley, Distributed language, 185–209. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.10.1075/bct.34.10steSuche in Google Scholar

Trybulec, Marcin. 2013. Bridging the gap between writing and cognition: Materiality of written vehicles reconsidered. Pragmatics & Cognition 21(3). 469–483.10.1075/pc.21.3.03trySuche in Google Scholar

Trybulec, Marcin. 2017. External representations reconsidered: Against reification of cognitive extensions. Avant : Journal of Philosophical-Interdisciplinary Vanguard 7(1). 229–244.10.26913/80102017.0101.0014Suche in Google Scholar

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. (G. E. Anscombe, trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.Suche in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2019-11-21
Published in Print: 2019-11-26

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Heruntergeladen am 25.9.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/css-2019-0028/html?lang=de
Button zum nach oben scrollen