Home Inferences about event outcomes influence text-based memory of event outcomes
Article Open Access

Inferences about event outcomes influence text-based memory of event outcomes

  • Xinyan Kou ORCID logo EMAIL logo and Jill Hohenstein
Published/Copyright: October 23, 2024

Abstract

Memory of event outcomes is a topic increasingly discussed in the field of event language and cognition. This study approaches how language influences memory of event outcomes from the under-explored perspective of the verb’s “fulfilment type”, a property formulated in Talmy’s event integration theory. This property indicates the extent to which verbs depict fulfilment of intentions. Through two experiments, we explored how verbs’ fulfilment type properties shape the text-based memory of event outcomes according to their perceived likelihood of intention fulfilment. There are two major findings. First, people tend to have “fulfilment preferences” and infer that intention fulfilment is more likely than intention non-fulfilment. Second, intention-unfulfilled event outcomes tend to be remembered better for event descriptions that trigger no fulfilment perferences. This study contributes to event language and memory research by demonstrating how language-generated inferences can influence established memory of event outcomes.

1 Introduction

Endpoints of events are a cognitively prominent part of event structure in event processing and apprehension (Altmann 2017; Solomon et al. 2015) and tend to be remembered better than other event parts (e.g., Gold et al. 2017; Lakusta and Landau 2012). However, studies examining how language might influence memory of event results are scarce (Santin et al. 2020; Santin, van Hout et al. 2021). It is well-known that inferences can shape memory (e.g., Gallo 2010; McDermott and Chan 2006). Integrating the three lines of research above, the present study examines how language-generated inferences might affect memory of event outcomes from the perspective of the ‘fulfilment type’ concept (Talmy 2000b: 262–268).

In what follows, Section 2 introduces the concept of fulfilment type in relation to existing literature and discusses how it might generate inferences about event outcomes. Section 3 reviews literature on pragmatic inferences, language, and memory. Section 4 presents two experiments examining how verbs generate inferences about event outcomes (Experiment 1) and how such inferences might shape text-based memory of event outcomes (Experiment 2). The main findings are discussed in Section 5, and Section 6 concludes.

2 Fulfilment type

The fulfilment type concept formulated in the event integration theory (Talmy 2000b: Ch 3) classifies action verbs into four types: intrinsic-, moot-, implied-, and attained-fulfilment verbs, which differ in two aspects: (1) whether the verb inherently specifies an intention (i.e., canonical goal associated with the action); (2) how likely that intention is fulfilled. Table 1 illustrates.

Table 1:

Four fulfilment types.

Fulfilment type Intention specified? Intention fulfilled? Example
Intrinsic-fulfilment No n/a kick
Moot-fulfilment Yes Uncertain hunt
Implied-fulfilment Yes Implied wash
Attained-fulfilment Yes Yes kill

Given the scarcity of literature on fulfilment type, this section discusses this concept in relation to existing frameworks. Section 2.1 explains the notions of event outcome, fulfilment type, and intention fulfilment in connection with several terms in event literature. We then discuss fulfilment type in relation to two particularly relevant notions: manner/result verbs (Section 2.2) and telicity (Section 2.3).

2.1 Intention fulfilment, event outcomes, and relevant terms

To situate this study with respect to existing event literature, we compare ‘event outcomes’ – the focus of the present study – with the following concepts: ‘event boundary’ (e.g., Zacks et al. 2009), ‘event ending/endpoint’ (e.g., von Stutterheim et al. 2012), ‘event completion/cessation’ (Sakarias and Flecken 2019), and ‘event result’ (e.g., Santin et al. 2021; Santin, van Hout et al. 2021).

2.1.1 Event boundary

Our brain processes the activities happening around us by segmenting them into meaningful chunks (e.g., Gerwien and von Stutterheim 2018; Radvansky and Zacks 2014). For instance, in a laundry folding scene, the largest meaningful unit is the complete process of laundry being folded up, while a small meaningful unit could be the act of picking up a sleeve (Zacks et al. 2009). It is generally assumed that event boundaries are marked by change in general (Gerwien and Stutterheim 2018Zacks and Tversky 2001: 9–10). According to the Event Segmentation Theory (e.g., Radvansky and Zacks 2014), event boundaries are detected “whenever an ongoing change in one or multiple participants … has progressed to the extent that it becomes hard … to predict what will happen next” (Santin, van Hout et al. 2021: 625; Zacks et al. 2007). For example, when someone reaches for a cup, it is predictable that the event is bounded by the physical contact between the person’s hand and the cup; however, once that contact is made, it becomes unpredictable what would happen next. Thus, an event boundary is perceived.

In the current study, the intention denoted by a verb can be conceptualised as a potential event boundary. To illustrate, dirty laundry’s becoming clean marks the boundary for washing. Intention fulfilment would thus be comparable to the reaching of event boundaries.

2.1.2 Event cessation/completion (Sakarias and Flecken 2019)

The notion of event cessation/completion is closely associated with the concepts of resultative/non-resultative events. According to Sakarias and Flecken (2019: 1), “[r]esultative events show objects that undergo a visually salient change in state during the course of the event (e.g., peeling a potato), and non-resultative events involve objects that undergo no, or only partial state change (e.g., measuring a box)”. For resultative events, ‘ceased/completed events’ go all the way along their natural trajectories. For example, a potato-peeling event is ceased/completed when the potato is fully peeled. In contrast, ‘ongoing events’ have not reached the end of their natural trajectories. For example, a potato-peeling event is ongoing when the peeling is still happening. When it comes to non-resultative events, cessation simply means stopping. Notably, Sakarias and Flecken’s criterion for determining whether events are resultative or non-resultative is rooted in visual salience of the result.

In our study, intentions denoted by verbs are not necessarily visually salient. By our standards, some of the non-resultative event examples above can have canonical goals (e.g., measure denotes the goal of obtaining measurements). However, the common ground between intention fulfilment and event cessation/completion is that an intention is fulfilled when the relevant (resultative) event ceases/completes.

2.1.3 Event result (e.g., Santin et al. 2021; Talmy 2016)

Santin et al. (2021) argued that it is unclear whether Talmy’s notion of event result refers to telicity (Garey 1957) or the change/translocation the affected object undergoes (cf. affectedness in Beavers 2011 and directed change in Croft 2012) following a particular activity. We discuss telicity in Section 2.2, so we focus only on change/translocation here. To illustrate, the event result in I killed the bug is that the bug died (change); the event result in I ran into the room is that the agent ended up inside the room (translocation).

In the current study, an event result is a fulfilled intention. For example, the result for washing events would be the laundry’s becoming clean. Notably, event results specifically refer to occurred change/translocation. In that sense, when intended goals are unfulfilled, no event results are achieved.

2.1.4 Event ending/endpoint (e.g., Ji and Papafragou 2020; Santin, van Hout et al. 2021; von Stutterheim et al. 2012)

The endpoint of an event is the final phase of an event. This notion refers to an element in event structure, often discussed in relation to event starting points (e.g., Lakusta and Landau 2012) and midpoints (e.g., Gold et al. 2017). Namely, event endpoints are not defined in terms of change or whether change happens or not. Thus, there is no necessary correspondence between intention fulfilment and event endpoints. When an event ends, an intention can be either fulfilled or unfulfilled (e.g., I washed the shirt – it became clean / it didn’t become clean); however, when an intention is fulfilled, the event often also reaches its endpoint (e.g., one seldom continues washing when the laundry has become clean; although one can theoretically continue washing after intention fulfilment, it is more reasonable not to in real life).

2.2 Fulfilment type versus manner/result verbs (and relevant concepts)

As the fulfilment type notion concerns the likelihood of intention fulfilment denoted by the verb, a relevant concept is manner/result verbs and manner/result complementarity in verb meaning (e.g., Rappaport Hovav and Levin 2010). Result verbs (e.g., clean) denote the result of an action but cannot denote manner information; manner verbs (e.g., wash) specify how an action is conducted but cannot denote what result is achieved. It is argued that a verb root can only denote either manner or result information, not both (e.g., Rappaport Hovav and Levin 2010). Major disagreements about manner/result complementarity come from Croft (2012) and Goldberg (2010), but their proposals disagree with manner/result complementarity to different extents.

For Croft (2012), ‘result’ can be split into ‘directed change’ (change in one particular dimension) and ‘undirected change’ (change in multiple unspecified dimensions). It is inaccurate to claim that manner verbs do not denote any change – for example, activities denoted by wash do entail some change in the affected object. The real distinction between manner/result verbs is that manner verbs do not denote ‘directed change’, while result verbs do. To illustrate, clean denotes the directed change from dirty to clean, while wash denotes undirected changes that might involve the relevant object becoming soaked and undergoing miscellaneous shape changes as it is agitated by the agent. Therefore, if result is taken to mean directed change, then manner/result complementarity holds; if result is taken to mean undirected change, manner/result complementarity would not hold. Thus, Croft (2012) is not a rebuttal per se to manner/result complementarity – he only placed a stricter definition on what counts as result.

Scholars who disagree with manner/result complementarity in the strict sense (directed change) presented counter-examples that encode both manner and directed change such as schuss, verbs of cooking (e.g., fry, stew; Goldberg 2010), and cutting and breaking verbs (e.g., slice; Chen 2007). Goldberg (2010) argued from the perspective of Frame Semantics that the only constraint on verb meaning is the Conventional Frame Constraint: “For a situation to be labeled by a verb, the situation or experience may be hypothetical or historical and need not be directly experienced, but it is necessary that the situation or experience evoke a cultural unit that is familiar and relevant to those who use the word” (Goldberg 2010: 50). Thus, when a conventional frame features both manner and directed change, it would be possible for both to be incorporated in a verb’s meaning.

Let us now relate Talmy’s fulfilment type to the frameworks above. Talmy (2000b: 261–278) did not define whether ‘intention fulfilment’ is directed or undirected change, but it more likely refers to directed change, because directed changes are arguably more likely than undirected changes to be conventionally received as intended goals. Further, intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs would be semantically classified as manner verbs, and attained-fulfilment verbs as result verbs (Kou and Hohenstein 2024). Thus, the fulfilment type notion basically argues that some manner verbs point to intended results (i.e., moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs) and can even imply intention fulfilment (i.e., implied-fulfilment verbs).

Frame Semantics makes more accessible the argument that some manner verbs can imply intention fulfilment. In real life, manner and result are often associated in the mind. Human activities are primarily goal-oriented (Landau and Lakusta 2012; Zwaan and Radvansky 1998). Indeed, manner verbs often point to canonical goals (e.g., Pederson 2008; Rappaport Hovav and Levin 2010). Recall that Talmy (2000b: 262–268) argued that intrinsic-fulfilment verbs do not inherently denote specific intentions while moot-/implied-(/attained)-fulfilment verbs do. In light of Frame Semantics, this would suggest that intrinsic-fulfilment verbs do not evoke specific conventional frames linking the pertinent manners and results (e.g., kick is not associated with any specific goal), while moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs do (e.g., hunt is associated with the goal to arrest, wash is associated with the goal to clean).

While Frame Semantics provides the potential for manner verbs to be associated with result, why would some manner verbs imply no intention fulfilment? As intrinsic-fulfilment verbs are argued to independently denote no intention (Talmy 2000b: 262–264), the discussion here is mainly confined to moot- and implied-fulfilment verbs. Specifically, why would implied-fulfilment verbs imply intention fulfilment, while moot-fulfilment verbs would not? Two factors seem to contribute to this variation: (1) directness of causation between the activity and the result associated with the verb, and (2) the task difficulty of the event denoted by the verb.

First, the directness of causation (e.g., Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1994) between the causing and caused subevents in the event denoted by the verb can influence the outlook for intention fulfilment. This is reminiscent of the ‘idealised causative event’, which features direct manipulation of an entity by an agent (Lakoff and Johnson 1980: 69–71). Anticipating the verbs examined in the present study (Table 2), it is easy to see that moot-fulfilment verbs mostly denote mental efforts[1] as they are verbs of searching (e.g., explore, investigate, hunt, seek) and verbs of obtaining (e.g., demand, request), following Levin’s (1993) verb classes. In contrast, implied-fulfilment (and intrinsic-fulfilment) verbs often denote activities involving physical manipulation. Thus, while implied-fulfilment verbs primarily involve direct causation in the events they denote, moot-fulfilment verbs often involve indirect causation. Indirect causation often features no physical contact (e.g., Ammon 1980) or transmission of physical force (Croft 2012: 198; Talmy 2000a: 409–470) between the agent and the object. The lack of physical contact and force transmission can lead to the impression that the agent has little control (e.g., Smith 1978) over how the event unfolds, thereby lowering the likelihood of intention fulfilment. Indirect causation can also involve a third party (apart from the agent and the object) who serves as an ‘intervening cause’ and is fully independent of the agent (Wolff 2003). Thus, it is not up to the agent whether intention can be fulfilled, which weakens the prospect for intention fulfilment. To illustrate, when demanding something, there is often someone other than the agent who determines whether the demanded objected can be obtained. Summarising, indirectness of causation might explain why moot-fulfilment verbs trigger no fulfilment preferences.

Table 2:

Verbs used in this study.

Intrinsic-fulfilment verb Corresponding attained-fulfilment verb Moot-fulfilment verb Corresponding attained-fulfilment verb Implied-fulfilment verb Corresponding attained-fulfilment verb
pull pluck explore discover rinse cleanse
push close demand obtain iron smooth
turn tighten request get wipe polish
twist remove call reach study learn
kick open chase catch mop dry
tap crack ponder solve sponge absorb
roll flatten investigate reveal wash clean
strike damage race overtake filter purify
pound break hunt arrest hoover remove
press seal seek find comb detangle
squeeze extract examine locate saw cut
spray kill pester annoy sieve separate

A further contributor to whether a verb implies intention fulfilment is task difficulty. Understandably, if a goal is more difficult to achieve, it is less likely to be achieved. The events described by different verbs naturally differ in task difficulty. For example, hunting activities are generally more difficult than washing activities. The event scenarios described with moot-fulfilment verbs tend to be relatively difficult, which might dim the outlook for intention fulfilment.

2.3 Fulfilment type versus telicity

Fulfilment types concern whether intention fulfilment (akin to change, more details below) happens in causative events, which is reminiscent of verbs’ lexical aspect, i.e., “a semantic category that concerns properties of eventualities … expressed by verbs … [such as] the presence [or absence] of some end, limit or boundary in the lexical structure of … verbs” (Filip 2012: 722). A well-known aspectual system is Vendler’s (1967) classification along three dimensions: stative/dynamic, durative/punctual, and telic/atelic. A crossing of these features yields four aspectual categories: states (stative/durative/atelic, e.g., know), activities (dynamic/durative/atelic, e.g., walk), accomplishments (dynamic/durative/telic, e.g., clean), and achievements (dynamic/punctual/telic, e.g., break). Arguably, telicity (e.g., Garey 1957) is the most relevant to fulfilment type. To enunciate the distinction between fulfilment type and telicity, we show below that intention fulfilment readings are not influenced by means that can alter (a)telicity.

It is well-known that the (a)telicity of an expression can be altered by the specificity of quantity in the direct object. Telic expressions often have direct objects that are specified for quantity (e.g., I ate two apples ; Verkuyl 1993); this specific quantity imposes an endpoint in time for the event. For example, in I ate two apples, when the two apples are fully consumed, eating stops in time. When the direct object is unspecified for quantity – I ate apples, eating could last forever when there is an endless number of apples available for consumption. If fulfilment type was the same concept as telicity, whether an event expression denotes intention fulfilment would similarly hinge on the quantity of the direct object. However, the shift from quantity-specific to quantity-unspecific direct objects would not alter the outlook for intention fulfilment (e.g., quantity-specific: I killed a person → certain that the person died; quantity-unspecific: I killed people → still certain that people died). Conversely, quantity-specific direct objects can make some atelic expressions telic. For example, while run is atelic, run two miles is telic, as two miles can ‘measure out’ (Tenny 1994) or delimit running by imposing an endpoint on it. This shift does not pertain to intention fulfilment; quantity-specific direct objects cannot turn an event with uncertain intention fulfilment into an event with certain intention fulfilment (e.g., quantity-unspecific: I investigated cases → intention fulfilment uncertain; quantity-specific: I investigated two cases → intention fulfilment still uncertain).

Such disconnection between intention fulfilment readings and the specificity of quantity of the direct object is because telicity and fulfilment type essentially concern different types of event endpoints. For telicity, an event is bounded by a point in time where an event can no longer proceed; for fulfilment type, an event boundary is a change in state. Thus, in the apple-eating scenario, when there is an indefinite number of apples that can be consumed, eating theoretically never stops. In contrast, for fulfilment type, no matter whether there is a definite or indefinite number of apples available for consumption, when apples are eaten, they are eaten, and change has occurred (to however many apples).

2.4 Section summary

A verb’s fulfilment type represents the likelihood of intention fulfilment (i.e., how likely is a resultative event completed/event result obtained/event boundary reached when the event ends). On this note, we introduced event outcomes as the focus of the present study. An event outcome can be a fulfilled intention or an unfulfilled intention. In event descriptions, verbs with different fulfilment types can trigger intention-fulfilled or intention-unfulfilled inferences for event outcomes. To illustrate, while I washed the shirt might encourage an intention-fulfilled reading (i.e., the shirt became clean), I hunted the fugitive might give a dimmer outlook for intention fulfilment (i.e., the fugitive gets arrested).

Although intention fulfilment is somewhat analogous to path in the well-studied Motion event domain, we do not find equivalent concepts to fulfilment type in motion verbs. This is because manner-of-motion verbs do not point to canonical paths (e.g., run does not denote any canonical path and can thus combine with various paths, such as run into/along/up/etc.; cf. Gerwien and von Stutterheim 2018) in the same way as many manner-of-action verbs point to canonical goals (e.g., wash inherently denotes the goal to clean). When one wishes to mention path while using manner-of-motion verbs, one obligatorily employs path satellites (e.g., run into ) or switches to a path verb (e.g., enter), which would lead to unambiguous path information. For instance, in I ran into / entered the room, it is certain that the agent ended up inside the room – there is no uncertainty regarding that path. Given this, we are not in a position to discuss likelihood of path in Motion events, as path is either non-existent (e.g., I ran) or 100 % certain (e.g., I ran into / entered the room). In contrast, manner-of-action verbs often independently denote canonical goals (except for intrinsic-fulfilment verbs) and can imply the obtainment of that goal (e.g., Kou and Hohenstein 2024; Lee and Kaiser 2021; Rappaport Hovav and Levin 1998; Talmy 2000b). This is what enables the discussion of the likelihood of intention fulfilment for manner-of-action verbs. To illustrate, in I washed the shirt, we can discuss how likely the shirt became clean; in I hunted the fugitive, we can discuss how likely the fugitive was arrested.

Such likelihood is in nature language-generated inferences. The present study concerns how such inferences might influence memory of event outcomes. To our knowledge, there is no study directly exploring this topic, so we review below research on three relevant areas, namely, the interplay between language, inferences, and memory.

3 Language, inferences, and memory

Sections 3.1 and 3.2 respectively give direct and indirect evidence showing that inferences influence memory. As the current investigation focusses on memory of event outcomes, Section 3.3 specifically reviews explorations into memory of event endings.

3.1 The Deese-Roediger/McDermott paradigm and the pragmatic inference paradigm

Previous memory research has reported robust memory errors induced by pragmatic inferences, mainly through two experimental paradigms. The first is the Deese-Roediger/McDermott paradigm (Deese 1959; Roediger and McDermott 1995). In this paradigm, participants study lists of semantically associated words (e.g., bed, pillow, rest, awake, nap) and later recall whether a related but non-presented target word (e.g., sleep) is on the list. The target words are often falsely recalled or recognised by participants despite their absence during encoding (e.g., Deese 1959; Gallo 2010; Roediger and McDermott 1995). The presented words activate a certain domain in which the non-presented word is related to, so the non-presented word is inferred to be on the list, via relational processing (Maraver et al. 2021).

The second paradigm linking memory and inferences is the pragmatic inference paradigm (see Maraver et al. 2021 for a review). In this paradigm, participants study texts that can generate inferences (e.g., The karate champion hit the cinder block implies The karate champion broke the cinder block). Participants often misremember the inferred version of the studied material, rather than the original version (e.g., Barclay et al. 1984; Bartlett 1932; McDermott and Chan 2006).

These paradigms provide direct evidence that language-generated inferences can influence memory of previously encountered language input. While this line of research explicitly ascribes memory errors to inferences, there are other areas of memory research that do not explicitly discuss memory distortion in relation to inferences but nonetheless can be interpreted as related to inferences, as Section 3.2 illustrates.

3.2 Memory studies relevant to language-generated inferences

The following studies do not directly focus on inferences, but they are somewhat relevant as they study language-generated expectations that could be regarded as inferences. These studies can serve as indirect evidence that inferences affect memory.

First, language can influence memory of previously observed scenarios (e.g., Loftus 1975; Loftus et al. 1978). In Loftus (1975), participants viewed videos of road accidents and answered questions containing either misinformation about a non-existent barn (How fast was the white sports car going when it passed the barn while traveling along the country road?) or neutral information (How fast was the white sports car going while traveling along the country road?). Participants who received misinformation believed that they saw a barn in the video significantly more than those who received neutral information did. Further, spatial memory can be influenced by prepositions denoting spatial orientation (e.g., Feist and Gentner 2007). When ambiguous spatial images (e.g., a block balanced on the edge of a building) were described with spatial prepositions (e.g., The block is on the building), participants tended to remember the images as prototypical spatial relationships represented by the prepositions (e.g., block further away from the edge of the building). Moreover, language can influence memory of the temporal duration of events (Wang and Gennari 2019). Participants viewed videos featuring moving geometric shapes (e.g., a red rectangle moving upwards), each video labelled as either a ‘long event’ (e.g., A Chinese lantern rising up into the sky) or a ‘short event’ (e.g., A fire rocket launched into the sky). When participants recalled the length of the videos, videos described as long events were believed to last longer, compared to when the same videos were described as short events.

3.3 Language and memory of event endings

Having reviewed literature showing that memory can be influenced by inferences, we are in a better position to ask the specific question in the current study: to what extent do inferences influence memory of event outcomes? Since there seems to be no existing study on this issue, we review below previous investigations into memory of event endings.

Research into language and memory of event endings started in the motion domain with von Stutterheim et al. (2012). Languages differ as to the availability of grammatical means for expressing ongoing motion (e.g., imperfective or progressive aspect). For languages with grammatical means to express ongoingness (‘[+aspect] languages’, e.g., English, Arabic), it is not necessary to express path endings in ongoing motion events (e.g., A car is driving along a road (to a village)). For languages without grammatical means to encode ongoingness (‘[-aspect] languages’, e.g., German), path endings are much more often expressed (e.g., Ein Auto fährt zu einem Dorf ‘A car drives to a village’) (e.g., von Stutterheim et al. 2012). von Stutterheim et al. (2012) asked native speakers of seven [+aspect]/[−aspect] languages to watch videos depicting completed motion (e.g., a car reaches a village) and ongoing motion (e.g., a car drives towards a village in the distance). Participants either described or were prevented from describing the events during video display, and their eye gazes at the objects at path endings (e.g., a village house) were tracked. Later, participants viewed still images of the videos with the objects at path endpoints removed and recalled what the objects were. Speakers who typically mentioned path endpoints tended to remember endpoint objects better, compared to speakers who normally left out path endpoints in event descriptions, but significant difference was only detected when participants verbalised the events and between the most typical [-aspect] language (German) and the most representative [+aspect] language (Arabic). When participants were prohibited from verbalising the events, no language effects on memory were detected. In short, a linguistic highlight on path endpoints benefited memory of path endpoints. Although von Stutterheim et al. (2012) detected a language effect on memory of path endpoints, the study might not be very relevant to the present investigation. We examine memory of event outcomes, namely whether some intention has been fulfilled; in the context of von Stutterheim et al. (2012), this information would translate into whether the agents actually reached the path endpoints. Thus, we target a different aspect of events.

More pertinent to the present study are investigations into memory of event endings in the domain of state change. Sakarias and Flecken (2019) explored the impact of the Estonian case marking for full/partial state change on memory of event outcomes, contrasting it with a language without such differentiation (Dutch). In Estonian, objects take obligatory grammatical markers to reflect whether a relevant state change happens partially (e.g., kartuli-t, ‘potato.partitive’, a potato half peeled) or in full (e.g., kartuli, ‘potato.accusative’, a potato fully peeled). Native speakers of Estonian and Dutch viewed videos of causative events with visually salient state changes (e.g., peeling a banana) and without (e.g., polishing glasses), among which half reached the final state (‘ceased’) and the other half did not (‘ongoing’). Half of the participants described the videos shortly after viewing, while the other half were prevented from verbalising them via a distractor task. A subsequent recognition task examined participants’ memory of whether state change was fully or partially achieved. In the verbal condition, Estonian speakers outperformed Dutch speakers, but the non-verbal condition elicited the opposite pattern. Importantly, memory of Dutch speakers did not vary in verbal and non-verbal conditions, suggesting that the memory differences detected above were driven by the distinctions between verbal and non-verbal conditions for Estonian speakers. This shows that the Estonian full/partial case marking enhances memory accuracy when language is involved and weakens memory performance when language is absent, showcasing language effects on memory.

Two similar studies are Santin et al. (2020) and Santin, van Hout et al. (2021). Focussing on native speakers of Dutch, Chinese, and Spanish, the authors explored how verb semantics would influence memory of event endings. The materials and experimental paradigm in these two studies closely followed Sakarias and Flecken (2019), but Santin and colleagues further explored whether or not participants’ event descriptions entailed state change. Participants’ memory of event endings was overall enhanced by verbalisation, but verb semantics did not significantly influence memory.

As shown, research often reports that verbalising events affects event representation (e.g. Gennari et al. 2002; Sakarias and Flecken 2019). Verbalising specific event components often leads to memory enhancement for those elements. When verbalising is prohibited, language effects on memory are less frequently detected. However, as we explicitly present event expressions in all trials in the memory experiment (Section 4.2.4), the verbal/non-verbal contrast is not pertinent here. This is because our study is not designed to investigate how verbs’ fulfilment types would influence encoding of event outcomes. Rather, we focus on how verbs’ fulfilment types would trigger inferences about event outcomes, which would in turn influence previously established memory of event outcomes.

The rationale for our memory study might look clearer if we draw an analogy in motion event language and memory research in the Talmyan tradition. If this study was conducted in the motion domain, we would present event descriptions lexicalising manner and path and ask how the relevant manner information later presented impacts memory of path. An imaginary stimulus would read: I walked and then I entered the room [change-occurred outcome] / remained outside the room [no-change outcome]. At recall, participants would be cued with manner information I walked and recall whether the agent entered the room or not. This design does not make sense in the motion domain, because manner-of-motion verbs do not inherently point to canonical paths, so manner-of-motion verbs alone are not theoretically expected to generate inferences about path and modulate memory of previously encountered paths. However, this design would make sense in the current context of fulfilment type, as manner-of-action verbs can point to canonical intentions and imply intention fulfilment. Therefore, when one reads about manner in the absence of event outcome information, one can infer whether there is intention fulfilment based on the manner verb.

3.4 Section summary

The aforementioned studies indicate that memory can be distorted when language introduces inferences about the memorised content (e.g., how long an activity should last, what spatial relation should be described by a preposition). Indeed, recall is argued to be a constructive process, whereby beliefs and world knowledge can be integrated with established memory (e.g., Barclay et al. 1984; Bartlett 1932).

At this point, let us revisit Santin et al. (2020) and Santin, van Hout et al. (2021). To some extent, these studies also approached event language from the perspective of inferred event outcomes. The authors asked participants to produce descriptions for events and judged whether those descriptions entailed change in the affected objects. Why did they not detect a language effect on memory of event endings, though? This is possibly because those event descriptions were not in a position to trigger inferences for the participants who produced the event descriptions and later did the recall task, because those participants clearly observed whether change took place in the video stimuli and thus did not have to make inferences about event outcomes. Therefore, although verb semantics can trigger inferences about whether change happened, it was not in a position to do so in Santin et al. (2020) and Santin, van Hout et al. (2021). Had participants encountered those event descriptions at recall in the absence of event ending information, their recall might have been modulated by language.

4 The present study

The present study empirically explores to what extent the verb’s fulfilment type might generate inferences about event outcomes and how those inferences might affect memory of event outcomes. As discussed in Section 2, verbs with different fulfilment types would evoke varying degrees of certainty of intention fulfilment. For example, I hunted the fugitive would generate a weak inference for a successful arrest, but I washed the shirt would lead to a stronger inference for the laundry to become clean. If one reads about an event’s outcome and is later exposed to inferences about the event’s outcome, the inference might interfere with previously established memory of event outcomes. Specifically, we ask (1) whether verbs of different fulfilment types would generate different inferences for event outcomes, and (2) whether inferences about event outcomes would shape memory of previously encountered event outcomes. These research questions are respectively explored with a likelihood rating task (Experiment 1) and a memory task (Experiment 2).

Participants in both experiments were monolingual British English speakers aged 18 to 50 with normal/corrected-to-normal vision and without neurological/psychiatric disorders recruited via Prolific (www.prolific.co). Participation was remote via the online experiment builder Gorilla (www.gorilla.sc), and each participant received a small monetary reward upon completion. All statistical analyses were performed in R (version 4.1.2, R core team).

4.1 Experiment 1

Experiment 1 explores whether events described with verbs with different fulfilment types could generate inferences about event outcomes. If so, there is reason to expect such inferences to affect memory of (text-based) event outcomes (to be investigated in Experiment 2). Notably, the semantic contrast between attained-fulfilment verbs and intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs might encourage the impression that the former suggest intention fulfilment, while the latter suggest non-fulfilment. This is not necessarily the case, as the lack of semantic entailment of intention fulfilment does not necessarily imply non-fulfilment of intention. Thus, it is necessary to empirically explore how events described with intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs are perceived in terms of event outcomes in language use.

There are studies investigating verbs from the perspective of certainty of event outcomes (e.g., Chen 2018; Esposito 2021; Lee and Kaiser 2021; Wright 2014). The research method is fairly straightforward – by asking native speakers to read event descriptions and judge the acceptability or likelihood of different outcomes. Following this approach, the present experiment is a likelihood estimation task investigating the default event outcome readings for different event descriptions so as to gauge the inferences about event outcomes.

4.1.1 Participants

Seventeen participants were recruited,[2] among whom 1 (5.88 %) was excluded due to lack of attention. Data from the remaining 16 (94.12 %) participants (Age: M = 30.56 years, range = 20–49 years; 8 females) was used.

4.1.2 Materials

This experiment used event descriptions featuring 72 English verbs, consisting of 12 intrinsic-fulfilment verbs, 12 moot-fulfilment verbs, 12 implied-fulfilment verbs, and 36 attained-fulfilment verbs (Table 2). The verbs had their fulfilment types identified through the diagnostic procedure formulated in Kou and Hohenstein (2022), with more details presented in Appendix 1.

The attained-fulfilment verbs matched the intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs in the sense that they could describe the same scenes. There can be multiple ways to describe the same event (e.g., Garnham 1981: 560; Gentner and Loftus 1979). In the current context, an event description can explicitly signal intention fulfilment or leave it to inference. To illustrate, the scene of someone tightening the lid of a leaking jar can be described as I pressed (intrinsic-fulfilment) / sealed (attained-fulfilment) the jar lid. Thirty-six event scenarios were constructed to match the verbs above, yielding 72 descriptions. Each description contained two background sentences, one laying out the scene and the other specifying the relevant intention, and an action sentence containing the target event verb (attained- vs. intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment); these sentences were then followed by two outcomes – intention-fulfilled and intention-unfulfilled, for which participants were asked to give likelihood ratings. For verbs paired with the same scene, the event description was kept identical except for the verb in the action sentence. An example scene is presented below with the verb pair press (intrinsic-fulfilment) and seal (attained-fulfilment):

Background: A jar was leaking. I needed to secure it.

Action: I pressed (intrinsic-fulfilment) / sealed (attained-fulfilment) the jar lid.

Intention-fulfilled outcome: The jar stopped leaking.

Intention-unfulfilled outcome: The jar was still leaking.

The grammatical subjects for the action sentences were I to avoid introducing personal qualities that might influence judgments (e.g., Esposito 2021; Wright 2014).[3] We present full stimuli in Appendix 2 and their naturalness ratings in Appendix 3.

4.1.3 Experiment design

Each participant read 36 event scenes, of which 18 were described by intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs (6 per fulfilment type) and the other 18 by attained-fulfilment verbs. Each participant only saw each scene once.

4.1.4 Procedure

Each participant read 36 event scenarios, randomised for order, and rated how likely the intention-fulfilled and intention-unfulfilled outcomes were by dragging sliders from 0 % (very unlikely) to 100 % (very likely). To avoid biases of what the likelihood should be, the default values of all sliders were set to 50 % (Liu and Conrad 2018). To avoid biases for any type of event outcome, the intention-fulfilled and intention-unfulfilled outcomes were randomised for position in terms of which appeared above the other. The task lasted approximately 8 minutes.

4.1.5 Data analysis

In total, 1,152 likelihood ratings were collected, 4 (0.35 %) of which were excluded as they were made under 2000 ms,[4] indicating lack of attention, leaving 1,148 data points.[5] A linear mixed-effects regression (lmer(), lme4 package, Bates et al. 2015) was performed to predict likelihood estimation (0–100 %) on Fulfilment Type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained) and Outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled), with Participant and Scene as random effects. Regression was performed on all possible combinations of fixed effect factors, and presented below is the best-fit model with the lowest AIC. Post-hoc analysis was conducted via contrasting the estimated marginal means (emmeans(), emmeans package, Lenth 2022) of different groups with Bonferroni-adjusted p values and Cohen’s d for effect sizes (eff_size(), emmeans package, Lenth 2022).

4.1.6 Results

Table 3 summarises the mean likelihood ratings by outcome and fulfilment type.

Table 3:

Means and standard deviations for likelihood ratings by outcome and fulfilment type.

Fulfilment type of event verb Intention-fulfilled outcome Intention-unfulfilled outcome
Mean (%) SD (%) Mean (%) SD (%)
Intrinsic 65.33 30.55 38.59 30.95
Moot 53.40 27.46 51.84 27.74
Implied 74.38 26.02 27.79 26.69
Attained 83.47 23.69 19.48 26.17

Table 4 reveals significant fixed effects of both fulfilment type and outcome as well as a significant interaction between the two.

Table 4:

Linear regression model for likelihood estimation by fulfilment type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained) and Outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled).

Random effects:
Groups Name Variance Std.Dev.
Scene number (Intercept) 0.00 0.00
Participant (Intercept) 0.56 0.75
Residual 710.8 26.7
Number of obs: 1,148 Groups: participant, 16 Scene number, 36
Fixed effects:
Estimate Std. error df t-Value Pr(>|t|) Signif.
(Intercept) 65.33 2.73 798.41 23.95 <0.000 ***
Moot −11.93 3.87 1,125.36 −3.08 0.002 **
Implied 9.04 3.85 1,125.09 2.35 0.019 *
Attained 18.14 3.14 1,125.09 5.77 <0.000 ***
Intention-unfulfilled −26.74 3.85 1,125.09 −6.95 <0.000 ***
Moot : Intention-unfulfilled 25.18 5.47 1,125.09 4.60 <0.000 ***
Implied : Intention-unfulfilled −19.84 5.44 1,125.09 −3.65 <0.001 ***
Attained : Intention-unfulfilled −37.25 4.44 1,125.09 −8.38 <0.000 ***
  1. Signif. codes: 0 ‘***’ 0.001 ‘**’ 0.01 ‘*’ 0.05 ‘.’ 0.1 ‘’.

Post-hoc analysis was conducted (Table 5). For events described with intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs, intention-fulfilled outcomes produced higher likelihood ratings than intention-unfulfilled outcomes did. In contrast, moot-fulfilment verbs did not elicit significantly different ratings between intention-fulfilled and intention-unfulfilled outcomes.

Table 5:

Post-hoc analysis for likelihood estimation.

Contrast Estimate SE df t-Ratio p-Value Cohen’s d (95 % CI)
Intrinsic:

Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 26.74 3.85 1,090 6.95 <0.001 1 (0.72, 1.29)

Moot:

Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 1.56 3.89 1,090 0.40 1.000 n.s. 0.06 (–0.23, 0.34)

Implied:

Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 46.58 3.85 1,090 12.11 <0.001 1.75 (1.46, 2.04)

Attained:

Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 63.99 2.22 1,090 28.80 <0.001 2.4 (2.21, 2.59)

4.1.7 Discussion

The findings set moot-fulfilment verbs apart from intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs. There were ‘fulfilment preferences’ (i.e., intention-fulfilled outcomes deemed more likely than intention-unfulfilled outcomes) for events described with intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs. Although intrinsic- and implied-fulfilment verbs do not semantically entail intention fulfilment, they nevertheless elicited fulfilment preferences for event outcomes. These fulfilment preferences echo previous empirical evidence that manner-of-action verbs often imply goal obtainment (e.g., Chen 2018; Kou and Hohenstein 2024; Lee and Kaiser 2021). For instance, studying Mandarin Chinese single-verb event expressions (i.e., described with monomorphemic verbs, rather than resultative complements), Chen (2018: 148) found that although the verbs under investigation do not semantically entail change and native speakers did accept no-change outcomes as legitimate, the default preference was that change happened. For example, for the expression Zhāngsān xǐ le yí-jiàn yīfu (‘Zhangsan washed a piece of clothing’), native speakers accepted the non-fulfilment outcome (e.g., clothing did not become clean) as legitimate but judged the intention fulfilment outcome (e.g., clothing became clean) as more likely.

Particularly note-worthy is that although intrinsic-fulfilment verbs are semantically unspecified for intention (and thus its fulfilment), there was nevertheless a general tendency to expect the relevant intentions to be fulfilled. Notably, in the fulfilment type framework, the distinction demarcating intrinsic-fulfilment verbs from moot-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs is that intrinsic-fulfilment verbs do not denote specific canonical goals, while the other three types verbs do. Crucially, low specificity of intention does not necessarily equate with low likelihood of intention fulfilment. Whenever verb-external information pins down specific goals, intrinsic-fulfilment verbs might no longer behave differently from moot-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs in terms of specification of intention, thereby gaining the potential to trigger fulfilment preferences.

In contrast, there was neutral expectation with regard to intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled outcomes for moot-fulfilment verbs, with estimations for both types of outcomes averaging at approximately 50 %. This confirms Talmy’s (2000b: 262–268) argument that moot-fulfilment verbs are ambiguous about intention fulfilment, whereas implied- and attained-fulfilment verbs showed preference for intention-fulfilled outcomes, as they theoretically either imply or entail intention fulfilment.

4.2 Experiment 2

With a general understanding of how verbs with different fulfilment types generate inferences about intention fulfilment, we examined in Experiment 2 whether such inferences would impact text-based memory of previously encountered event outcomes. Depending on intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled event outcomes, two predictions were formulated:

Prediction 1: For events with intention-fulfilled outcomes, memory performance would be better if post-encoding event descriptions encourage fulfilment preferences (i.e., contain intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs, compared to moot-fulfilment verbs).

Prediction 2: For events with intention-unfulfilled outcomes, memory performance would be better if post-encoding event descriptions do not encourage fulfilment preferences (i.e., contain moot-fulfilment verbs, compared to intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs).

4.2.1 Participants

A different group of participants took part in Experiment 2. In total, 172 participants were recruited, among which 51 (29.65 %) dropped out, 2 (1.16 %) were automatically timed out by Prolific, and 17 (9.88 %) were rejected for breaching instructions or lack of attention. Data from the remaining 102 participants (Age: M = 36.25 years, range = 20–56 years; 49 females) was used.[6]

4.2.2 Materials

The same 36 event scenes from Experiment 1 were used in the current experiment, but this time each description contained only one outcome, either intention-fulfilled or intention-unfulfilled. In the recall phase, the action sentences were presented to remind participants of the scenes and trigger inferences about event outcomes.

While previous event memory studies often use visual stimuli (e.g., images, videos), the present study employs text-based stimuli due to practical concerns. Although some event scenarios can be easily depicted visually (e.g., I pressed the jar lid. It stopped leaking), there are event scenarios that are not visually salient and thus difficult to depict visually (Sakarias and Flecken 2019). For example, if a video were to be created for the scenario I sprayed the bug. The bug died, it would be difficult to tell whether the bug died or just stopped moving. Furthermore, there are event scenarios that are difficult to condense into a few seconds for the purpose of experimentation. For instance, the scenario I explored the cause of the disease. The cause of the disease became known would be very difficult to condense into a few seconds. If events are depicted in their natural time courses, some videos would be very long and some very short, with great variation in video length likely to affect participants’ responses. If such scenes are condensed, the videos may look very unnatural. Moreover, text-based stimuli could potentially elicit more canonical event representations than visual stimuli can. As noted by Lupyan and Bergen (2016: 415), language activates abstracted prototypical representations, while non-verbal information activates situation-specific/time-specific representations. In that sense, language can potentially trigger more representative, prototypical conceptualisation of events, compared to visual stimuli. Given the reasons above, text-based stimuli were adopted in the current experiment. Future studies can seek more effective strategies to visually present event scenarios that are not visually salient.

4.2.3 Experiment design

A repeated-measures design was adopted to reduce participant variance. Each participant only saw each scene once with either an attained-fulfilment verb or an intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verb and either with an intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled outcome. In total, each participant viewed 36 event scenes (6 trials each for events described with intrinsic-/moot-/implied-fulfilment verbs and 18 trials for events described with attained-fulfilment verbs), half with intention-fulfilled outcomes and the other half with intention-unfulfilled outcomes.

4.2.4 Procedure

Experiment 2 consisted of an encoding phase and a memory test separated by one day. In the encoding phase, participants read 36 event descriptions randomised for order and estimated how much effort was put into the activity to ensure attention.[7] Prior to the task, there were two practice trials to familiarise participants with the task. One day later, participants completed a memory test. They read the action sentences of the scenes (randomised for order) and recalled whether the outcome for each scene was intention-fulfilled or intention-unfulfilled.

While the action sentences appeared both during encoding and at recall, only those appearing at recall can trigger inferences about event outcomes. Note that pragmatic inferences are not generated automatically during reading (Barclay et al. 1984) but rather are only generated to fill in absent information in a discourse (e.g., Cohn 2019). In the encoding phase, outcome sentences explicitly provided information about event outcomes, so participants did not need to make inferences about event outcomes based on the action sentences. Therefore, action sentences only triggered inferences about event outcomes at recall, when explicit information about event outcomes was absent.

To ensure that any findings are indeed based on memory, rather than participants’ biases regarding likely intention fulfilment, a control group of 14 participants took part in the recall phase of Experiment 2 as a standalone task. The task was kept identical to the experimental group, but the wording of the instructions understandably underwent some changes – control group participants were asked to read the event sentences and answer the relevant questions based on their intuition, rather than based on what they “read yesterday”.

4.2.5 Data analysis

Our main interest is in participants’ text-based memory of event outcomes following presentation of different types of verbs, so we only present analyses of effort estimations in Appendix 5. In total, 3,672 memory responses were collected, of which 19 (0.52 %) data points were removed due to lack of attention in the corresponding scenes during encoding, with the corresponding attention-checker questions answered within 1500 ms.[8] In addition, 25 (0.68 %) memory responses were removed because they took less than 100 ms,[9] which was impossibly fast given the task structure. This left 3,628 (98.80 %) valid responses, which were subsequently coded as 1 (correct) and 0 (incorrect).

To examine whether the event verb’s fulfilment type influenced memory of event outcomes, we performed a binomial mixed-effect logistic regression (glmer(), lme4 package, Bates et al. 2015) which predicted memory (correct/incorrect) based on the Fulfilment Type of the event verb (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained), Outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled), and random effects of Participant and Scene. Regression was performed on all possible combinations of fixed effect factors, and presented below is the best-fit model with the lowest AIC. Post-hoc analysis was conducted via contrasting the estimated marginal means (emmeans(), emmeans package, Lenth 2022) of different groups with Bonferroni-adjusted p values and odds ratios (OR) for effect sizes.

For the comparison between experimental/control groups, a binomial mixed-effect logistic regression (glmer(), lme4 package, Bates et al. 2015) was conducted predicting Responses (Yes = intention-fulfilled outcome / No = intention-unfulfilled outcome) on Experimental Condition (experiment/control) with Participant and Scene as random effects.

4.2.6 Results

Table 6 presents the raw counts and proportions of correct recalls in the memory task in events descriptions featuring verbs with each fulfilment type.

Table 6:

Raw counts and proportions of correct recalls by outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled) and fulfilment type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained).

Fulfilment type of verb Intention-fulfilled outcome Intention-unfulfilled outcome
Raw count Proportion Raw count Proportion
Intrinsic 215/305 70.49 % 193/304 63.49 %
Moot 215/303 70.96 % 231/301 76.74 %
Implied 213/298 71.48 % 209/302 69.21 %
Attained 648/907 71.44 % 592/908 65.20 %

The logistic regression model (Table 7) predicting memory accuracy (correct/incorrect) by Outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled) and Fulfilment Type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained) returned a significant interaction between fulfilment type and outcome. No fixed effects were significant.

Table 7:

Logistic regression model for memory accuracy by fulfilment type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained) and outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled).

Random effects:
Groups Name Variance Std.Dev.
Participant (Intercept) 0.212 0.460
Scene number (Intercept) 0.088 0.297
Number of obs: 3,628 Groups: Participant, 102 Scene number, 36
Fixed effects:
Estimate Std. error z-Value Pr(>|z|) Signif.
(Intercept) 0.945 0.154 6.123 <0.001 ***
Moot −0.091 0.205 −0.446 0.656
Implied 0.084 0.204 0.412 0.681
Attained 0.038 0.158 0.239 0.811
Intention-unfulfilled outcome −0.334 0.178 −1.873 0.061 .
Moot : Intention-unfulfilled outcome 0.653 0.261 2.500 0.012 *
Implied : Intention-unfulfilled outcome 0.225 0.256 0.882 0.378
Attained : Intention-unfulfilled outcome 0.026 0.206 0.125 0.900
  1. Signif. codes: 0 ‘***’ 0.001 ‘**’ 0.01 ‘*’ 0.05 ‘.’ 0.1 ‘’.

Post-hoc analysis (Table 8) was conducted to follow up the interaction between Fulfilment Type and Outcome. We first approached the interaction by Outcome. When intention-fulfilled outcomes were given, recall performance for events described by verbs with different fulfilment types did not significantly vary. When intention-unfulfilled outcomes were given, however, post-encoding events described with moot-fulfilment verbs yielded better memory performance compared to post-encoding events described with intrinsic- and attained-fulfilment verbs. Approaching the interaction by Fulfilment Type, for post-event descriptions containing attained-fulfilment verbs, intention-fulfilled outcomes yielded better memory than intention-unfulfilled outcomes did.

Table 8:

Post-hoc estimated marginal means analysis with Bonferroni-adjusted p values for memory accuracy.

Pairwise comparison df z-Ratio p-Value OR (95 % CI)
[Interaction] Fulfilment Type by Outcome

Intention-fulfilled outcome :

 Intrinsic – Moot 1 0.446 1.000 n.s. 1.10 (0.65, 1.85)
 Intrinsic – Implied 1 −0.412 1.000 n.s. 0.92 (0.54, 1.55)
 Intrinsic – Attained 1 −0.239 1.000 n.s. 0.96 (0.64, 1.44)
 Moot – Implied 1 −0.846 1.000 n.s. 0.84 (0.49, 1.43)
 Moot – Attained 1 −0.803 1.000 n.s. 0.88 (0.58, 1.33)
 Implied – Attained 1 0.289 1.000 n.s. 1.05 (0.69, 1.58)

Intention-unfulfilled outcome :

 Intrinsic – Moot 1 −2.714 0.040 0.57 (0.33, 0.97)
 Intrinsic – Implied 1 −1.563 0.708 n.s. 0.73 (0.44, 1.22)
 Intrinsic – Attained 1 −0.421 1.000 n.s. 0.94 (0.64, 1.38)
 Moot – Implied 1 1.199 1.000 n.s. 1.29 (0.75, 2.21)
 Moot – Attained 1 2.995 0.017 1.65 (1.07, 2.52)
 Implied – Attained 1 1.583 0.681 n.s. 1.28 (0.86, 1.91)

[Interaction] Outcome by Fulfilment Type

Intrinsic:

 Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 1 1.873 0.061 n.s. 1.40 (0.98, 1.98)

Moot:

 Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 1 −1.671 0.095 n.s. 0.73 (0.50, 1.06)

Implied:

 Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 1 0.592 0.554 n.s. 1.11 (0.78, 1.60)

Attained:

 Intention-fulfilled – Intention-unfulfilled 1 2.959 0.003 1.36 (1.11, 1.67)

For the comparison between experimental/control groups, significant differences were found between experiment and control groups, suggesting that the findings do reflect memory rather than participants’ biases regarding likely intention fulfilment. More details are given in Appendix 4.

4.2.7 Discussion

In Experiment 2, participants read event descriptions with intention-fulfilled or intention-unfulfilled outcomes and recalled one day later whether event outcomes were intention-fulfilled or intention-unfulfilled.

Overall, memory accuracy was high, possibly due to the cognitive prominence of event endpoints over starting points (e.g., Lakusta and Landau 2012) and midpoints (Gold et al. 2017). Had we queried about event beginnings or processes, overall memory accuracy might have decreased. Also, intention fulfilment can be regarded as the reaching of an event boundary (more in Section 5), and information at event boundaries is relatively salient in memory (Gerwien and von Stutterheim 2018). A further reason is that memory of event outcomes might not have been greatly swayed by verbal semantics (Santin, van Hout et al. 2021), especially considering that the distinctions between the four fulfilment types are subtle. Moreover, the one-day interval might be too short for adults to lose the original trace of memory.

Revisiting the specific predictions for memory performance (Section 4.2), Prediction 2 was attested, but Prediction 1 was not. Language effects were detected only for intention-unfulfilled outcomes but not for intention-fulfilled ones. We discuss this further in Section 5.

5 General discussion: inferences about event outcomes influence memory of text-based event outcomes

In this study, we explored whether memory of event outcomes is influenced by event verbs’ fulfilment types (Talmy 2000b: 262–268), a property concerning the likelihood of intention fulfilment. We first conducted a likelihood estimation task (Experiment 1), which detected different degrees of certainty of intention fulfilment for verbs with different fulfilment types. Next, we showed through a memory task (Experiment 2) how previously established text-based memory of event outcomes would be susceptible to inferences about event outcomes.

Before attributing the experimental findings to fulfilment types, recall that task difficulty has been mentioned as a potential contributor to the likelihood of intention fulfilment in events (Section 2.2) and thus memory performance. Although no task difficulty rating was conducted for our stimuli, the amount of effort involved when an intended goal is fulfilled in the effort estimation task (Experiment 2) can readily index task difficulty. The means of the effort estimations for events with intention-fulfilled outcomes were calculated and merged with the likelihood rating and memory data. Next, we performed a linear mixed-effects regression and a logistic regression respectively predicting likelihood estimation and memory accuracy on Outcome (intention-fulfilled/intention-unfulfilled), Fulfilment Type (intrinsic/moot/implied/attained), and Task Difficulty (0–100 %), with Participant and Scene as random effects. The models returned task difficulty as an insignificant effect on likelihood estimations and memory accuracy (Appendix 6). Thus, the event verb’s fulfilment type is arguably the main contributor to likelihood ratings and memory performance.

A limitation of the present study is that we focussed only on event expressions with single-verb phrases in the past simple, while there are many possible ways to describe events (e.g., progressive -ing). We aim to explore more event expression structures in future projects. Further, we only examined memory of text-based stimuli; future investigations can explore whether the same language effects would apply to visual memory. Despite these limitations, let us see what insights this study may offer.

We found that inferences about event outcomes can affect memory of previously encountered event outcomes. Events described with intrinsic-, implied-, and attained-fulfilment verbs were often perceived to lead to intention fulfilment; in contrast, events described with moot-fulfilment verbs were neutral in this regard. Events described with moot-fulfilment verbs led to particularly accurate memory of intention-unfulfilled outcomes. This dovetails into our predictions that events described with moot-fulfilment verbs would behave distinctively from those described with other types of verbs in terms of memory performance. Additionally, intention-fulfilled outcomes tend to be remembered better than intention-unfulfilled ones for events described with attained-fulfilment verbs.

Memory in general is a constructive process (e.g., Barclay et al. 1984), and original memory traces can be altered by new information introduced post-encoding (e.g., Loftus et al. 1978). Based on this understanding, inferences about event outcomes elicited by verbs of different fulfilment types might influence previously formed memory of event outcomes. When one learns about an event’s outcome, that memory is established. If one later receives a relevant event description that triggers inferences about the event’s outcome, one’s previously established memory might be altered. Specifically, if one receives a description containing an intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verb, one would be inclined to think that the event had an intention-fulfilled outcome. In contrast, if one receives an event description containing a moot-fulfilment verb, one would not have such an inclination.

Let us first focus on events described by moot-fulfilment verbs. The memory advantage for intention-unfulfilled outcomes with such verbs dovetails into their lack of fulfilment preferences. Recall that events described with moot-fulfilment verbs did not exhibit fulfilment preferences, while events described with all the other fulfilment types did (Experiment 1). A possible reason for the memory variation between moot-fulfilment verbs and the other types of verbs lies in the premise for language to influence memory post-encoding. It is well-established that memory can be updated by new information introduced at retrieval (e.g., Bartlett 1932; Loftus et al. 1978), a phenomenon known as retroactive interference (Keppel 1968). However, a premise for retroactive interference to take effect might be that the newly introduced information should be capable of updating the relevant event schema. According to the Event Segmentation Theory, event schemata are updated when they reach event boundaries (e.g., Zacks 2020), so it is only when the newly introduced event reaches its boundary that it can be committed to memory and interfere with the original event stored in memory. In the current context, the reaching of event boundaries is tantamount to intention fulfilment; this means that the event expression introduced at recall should be able to conjure up an intention-fulfilled impression for the new language input to interfere with the original event established in memory. Events described with moot-fulfilment verbs leave event outcomes uncertain and thus might not be able to update event schemata per se. In contrast, events described with intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs generally yield fulfilment preferences, so they were able to update the previously established event schema, thereby blurring the memory traces for the original intention-unfulfilled outcomes.

Another mechanism behind the recall advantage for intention-unfulfilled outcomes for events described with moot-fulfilment verbs is related to the perception and retrieval of intended goals. Research shows that failed intention information is remembered better than fulfilled intentions (Radvansky and Curiel 1998; i.e., Zeigarnik effect, Zeigarnik 1927). Following this view, the relevant intentions involved in the event scenarios should be remembered better when intention-unfulfilled outcomes were given than when intention-fulfilled outcomes were given. Thus, unfulfilled intentions could be better retrieved at recall, which could in turn lead to better memory of the corresponding intention-unfulfilled outcomes. This boost in memory would potentially apply to all event verbs, but why did it only appear for moot-fulfilment verbs? Again, this might be because events described with moot-fulfilment verbs did not effectively update the representation of event outcomes at recall and thus the recall advantage could take effect.

Turning to events described with attained-fulfilment verbs, we found that intention-fulfilled event outcomes were recalled better than intention-unfulfilled ones. It is understandable why intention-fulfilled event outcomes would have a memory advantage over intention-unfulfilled ones, given Santin and colleagues’ (Santin et al. 2020; Santin, van Hout et al. 2021) finding that the endings of ceased, resultative events (akin to intention fulfilment) were remembered better than ongoing, non-resultative events (akin to intention non-fulfilment). This probably also has to do with the idea that working memory only becomes updated when an event boundary is reached (Zacks et al. 2007). However, why was the memory advantage for intention-fulfilled outcomes over intention-unfulfilled outcomes only significant for events described with attained-fulfilment verbs? That these event expressions should elicit a memory advantage for intention-fulfilled outcomes is hardly surprising as events described with attained-fulfilment verbs elicited the highest likelihood ratings for intention-fulfilled outcomes (Table 3), which invites the conclusion that this memory advantage of intention-fulfilled outcomes is due to the very strong fulfilment preferences associated with the pertinent event expressions. This echoes von Stutterheim et al.’s (2012) finding that cognitive contrast was only observed for the most representative [+aspect] and [-aspect] languages (Arabic vs. German), suggesting that cognitive contrasts rely on not only the presence/absence of specific linguistic attributes, but also the strength of their presence/absence.

Further, why was the language effect detected only for events with intention-unfulfilled outcomes, but not for intention-fulfilled ones? Cognitively salient event information is naturally remembered better and is thus less susceptible to the influence of language. For instance, path in motion events is often remembered better than manner cross-linguistically because path is more cognitively salient than manner (e.g., Papafragou et al. 2002; ter Bekke et al. 2019). In the current experiment, only memory of intention-unfulfilled events was subject to language influence, while memory of intention-fulfilled outcomes was equally accurate across different language conditions. Could it be that intention-fulfilled outcomes are more cognitively central and prototypical than intention-unfulfilled outcomes? Santin et al. (2020), Santin, van Hout et al. (2021), and Sakarias and Flecken (2019) found that memory of event endings was generally more accurate for change-occurred events (akin to events with intention-fulfilled outcomes) than for no-change events (akin to events with intention-unfulfilled outcomes), as changes in the state of the object are salient in event representation (Altmann and Ekves 2019). Moreover, events described with intrinsic-/implied-/attained-fulfilment verbs all yielded better memory of intention-fulfilled outcomes than for intention-unfulfilled outcomes. These observations show that intention-fulfilled outcomes are likely to be more cognitively prominent than intention-unfulfilled ones, leading to varied malleability in their memory.

Summarising, the present study showed that the inferences about event outcomes can influence previously established memory of text-based event outcomes, echoing the argument that the “[r]etrieval of an experience from memory is usually a reconstruction of biased world knowledge” (Rumelhart and Norman 1973: 450). Events described by moot-fulfilment verbs had no fulfilment preferences and thus did not blur memory of intention-unfulfilled outcomes; events described by attained-fulfilment verbs exhibited strong fulfilment preferences and thus encouraged people to think that they previously saw intention-fulfilled outcomes. Although the present study is a single-language investigation, the findings might not be specific to English. Recall that Chen’s (2018) examination of Mandarin (monomorphemic) verbs yielded similar findings to the fulfilment preferences discovered in the current study, even though the explicit lexicalisation of intention fulfilment in Mandarin would require the use of satellites (e.g., xǐ-jìng ‘wash-clean’). Future research can test whether the current findings have cross-linguistic generalisability.

6 Conclusion

This study contributes to event language and memory research from the perspective of fulfilment type (Talmy 2000b: 262–268). We found fulfilment preferences for events described with intrinsic-, implied- and attained-fulfilment verbs, but not for those described with moot-fulfilment verbs. This distinction in turn affected memory performance for intention-unfulfilled event outcomes. These findings invite the conclusion that language-generated inferences about event outcomes have an impact on memory of previously encountered event outcomes.


Corresponding author: Xinyan Kou, Department of Foreign Languages, College of Humanities and Development, China Agricultural University, Beijing, China, E-mail:

  1. Data availability: All data, stimuli, R codes, and appendices are available at https://osf.io/k4sm3/.

References

Altmann, Gerry T. M. 2017. Abstraction and generalization in statistical learning: Implications for the relationship between semantic types and episodic tokens. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 372. 20160060. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0060.Search in Google Scholar

Altmann, Gerry T. M. & Ekves Zachary. 2019. Events as intersecting object histories: A new theory of event representation. Psychological Review 126(6). 817–840. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000154.Search in Google Scholar

Ammon, Mary S. H. 1980. Development in the linguistic expression of causal relations: Comprehension of features of lexical and periphrastic causatives. California: University of California, Berkeley PhD dissertation.Search in Google Scholar

Barclay, Craig R., Michael P. Toglia & Dolores S. Chevalier. 1984. Pragmatic inferences and type of processing. American Journal of Psychology 97(2). 285–296. https://doi.org/10.2307/1422601.Search in Google Scholar

Bartlett, Frederic C. 1932. Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Bates, Douglas, Martin Mächler, Ben Bolker & Steve Walker. 2015. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software 67(1). 1–48. https://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v067.i01.Search in Google Scholar

Chen, Jidong. 2007. “He cut-break the rope”: Encoding and categorizing cutting and breaking events in Mandarin. Cognitive Linguistics 18(2). 273–285. https://doi.org/10.1515/cog.2007.015.Search in Google Scholar

Chen, Jidong. 2018. “He killed a chicken, but it didn’t die”: An empirical study of the lexicalization of state change in Mandarin monomorphemic verbs. Chinese Language and Discourse 9(2). 136–161. https://doi.org/10.1075/cld.17007.che.Search in Google Scholar

Cohn, Neil. 2019. Being explicit about the implicit: Inference generating techniques in visual narrative. Language and Cognition 11(1). 66–97. https://doi.org/10.1017/langcog.2019.6.Search in Google Scholar

Croft, William. 2012. Verbs: Aspect and clausal structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Deese, James. 1959. On the prediction of occurrence of particular verbal intrusions in immediate recall. Journal of Experimental Psychology 58. 17–22. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0046671.Search in Google Scholar

Esposito, Lewis. 2021. An experimental and distributional investigation of two “non-culminating accomplishments” in Mandarin. Proceedings of Linguistic Society of America 6, 689–700.10.3765/plsa.v6i1.5004Search in Google Scholar

Feist, Michele I. & Dedre Gentner. 2007. Spatial language influences memory for spatial scenes. Memory & Cognition 35(2). 283–296.10.3758/BF03193449Search in Google Scholar

Filip, Hana. 2012. Lexical aspect. In Robert I. Binnick (ed.), The Oxford handbook of tense and aspect, 721–751. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195381979.013.0025Search in Google Scholar

Gallo, David A. 2010. False memories and fantastic beliefs: 15 years of the DRM illusion. Memory & Cognition 38(7). 833–848. https://doi.org/10.3758/mc.38.7.833.Search in Google Scholar

Garey, Howard B. 1957. Verbal aspects in French. Language 33. 91–110. https://doi.org/10.2307/410722.Search in Google Scholar

Garnham, Alan. 1981. Mental models as representations of text. Memory & Cognition 9(6). 560–565. https://doi.org/10.3758/bf03202350.Search in Google Scholar

Gennari, Silvia P., Steven A. Sloman, Barbara C. Malt & W. Tecumseh Fitch. 2002. Motion events in language and cognition. Cognition 83. 49–79. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(01)00166-4.Search in Google Scholar

Gentner, Dedre & Elizabeth F. Loftus. 1979. Integration of verbal and visual information as evidenced by distortions in picture memory. American Journal of Psychology 92(2). 363–375.10.2307/1421930Search in Google Scholar

Gerwien, Johannes & Christiane von Stutterheim. 2018. Event segmentation: Cross-linguistic differences in verbal and non-verbal tasks. Cognition 180. 225–237. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.07.008.Search in Google Scholar

Gold, David A., Jeffrey M. Zacks & Shaney Flores. 2017. Effects of cues to event segmentation on subsequent memory. Cognitive Research: Principles and Implications 2(1). 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1186/s41235-016-0043-2.Search in Google Scholar

Goldberg, Adele E. 2010. Verbs, frames and constructions. In Malka Rappaport Hovav, Edit Doron & Ivy Sichel (eds.). Syntax, lexical semantics and event structure, 39–58. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199544325.003.0003Search in Google Scholar

Ji, Yue & Anna Papafragou. 2020. Midpoints, endpoints and the cognitive structure of events. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 35(10). 1465–1479. https://doi.org/10.1080/23273798.2020.1797839.Search in Google Scholar

Keppel, Geoffrey. 1968. Retroactive and proactive inhibition. In Theodore Dixon & Deryck Horton (eds.), Verbal behavior and general behavior theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Search in Google Scholar

Kou, Xinyan & Jill Hohenstein. 2022. Fulfillment types in Realization events: Definition, distinctions, and diagnostics. Lingua 169. 103204. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2021.103204.Search in Google Scholar

Kou, Xinyan & Jill Hohenstein. 2024. Manner, result, and intention: Implications for event typology from a cognitive account of verb semantics based on fulfilment types. Language and Cognition. 1–26.10.1017/langcog.2023.72Search in Google Scholar

Lakoff, George & Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Search in Google Scholar

Lakusta, Laura & Barbara Landau. 2012. Language and memory for motion events: Origins of the asymmetry between source and goal. Cognitive Science 36(3). 517–544. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1551-6709.2011.01220.x.Search in Google Scholar

Lee, Sarah H.-Y. & Elsi Kaiser. 2021. Does hitting the window break it? Investigating effects of discourse-level and verb-level information in guiding object state representations. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 36(8). 921–940. https://doi.org/10.1080/23273798.2021.1896013.Search in Google Scholar

Lenth, Russel V. 2022. emmeans: Estimated marginal means, aka least-squares means. R package.version 1.7.3.Search in Google Scholar

Levin, Beth. 1993. English verb classes and alterations: A preliminary investigation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Search in Google Scholar

Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1994. A preliminary analysis of causative verbs in English. Lingua 92. 35–77. https://doi.org/10.1016/0024-3841(94)90337-9.Search in Google Scholar

Liu, Mingnan & Fred G. Conrad. 2018. Where should I start? On default values for slider questions in web surveys. Social Science Computer Review 37(2). 089443931875533. https://doi.org/10.1177/0894439318755336.Search in Google Scholar

Loftus, Elizabeth F. 1975. Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology 7. 560–572. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0285(75)90023-7.Search in Google Scholar

Loftus, Elizabeth F., David G. Miller & Helen J. Burns. 1978. Semantic integration of verbal information into a visual memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning & Memory 4(1). 19–31. https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.4.1.19.Search in Google Scholar

Lupyan, Gary & Benjamin Bergen. 2016. How language programs the mind. Topics in Cognitive Science 8. 408–424. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12155.Search in Google Scholar

Maraver, Maria J., Lapa Ana, Leonel Garcia-Marques, Carneiro Paula & Raposo Ana. 2021. Imagination reduces false memories for everyday action sentences: Evidence from pragmatic inferences. Frontiers in Psychology 12. 668899. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.668899.Search in Google Scholar

McDermott, Kathleen B. & Jason C. K. Chan. 2006. Effects of repetition on memory for pragmatic inferences. Memory & Cognition 34(6). 1273–1284. https://doi.org/10.3758/bf03193271.Search in Google Scholar

Papafragou, Anna, Christine Massey & Lila Gleitman. 2002. Shake, rattle, ‘n’ roll: The representation of motion in language and cognition. Cognition 84(2). 189–219. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(02)00046-x.Search in Google Scholar

Pederson, Eric. 2008. Event realisation in Tamil. In Penelope Brown & Melissa Bowerman (eds.), Crosslinguistic perspectives on argument structure: Implications for learnability, 331–355. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.Search in Google Scholar

Radvansky, Gabriel A. & Jacqueline M. Curiel. 1998. Narrative comprehension and aging: The fate of completed goal information. Psychology and Aging 13(1). 69–79. https://doi.org/10.1037/0882-7974.13.1.69.Search in Google Scholar

Radvansky, Gabriel A. & Jeffrey M. Zacks. 2014. Event cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199898138.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Beth Levin. 1998. Building verb meanings. In Miriam Butt & Wilhelm Geuder (eds.), The projection of arguments: Lexical and compositional factors, 97–134. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Search in Google Scholar

Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Beth Levin. 2010. Reflections on manner/result complementarity. In Malka Rappaport Hovav, Edit Doron & Ivy Sichel (eds.), Lexical semantics, syntax, and event structure, 21–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199544325.003.0002Search in Google Scholar

Roediger, Henry & Kathleen B. McDermott. 1995. Creating false memories: Remembering words not presented in lists. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition 21. 803–814. https://doi.org/10.1037//0278-7393.21.4.803.Search in Google Scholar

Rumelhart, David E. & Donald A. Norman. 1973. Active semantic networks as a model of human memory. In Proceedings of the third international joint conference on artificial intelligence. Stanford University.Search in Google Scholar

Sakarias, Maria & Monique Flecken. 2019. Keeping results in sight and mind: General cognitive principles and language-specific influences in the perception and memory of resultative events. Cognitive Science 43. 1–30. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12708.Search in Google Scholar

Santin, Miguel, Hobbelink Ciara, Flecken Monique & Angeliek van Hout. 2020. Resultative event representations in Dutch children and adults: Does describing events help memory? In Megan M. Brown & Alexandra Kohut (eds.), Proceedings of the 44th annual Boston University conference on language development, 508–521. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Search in Google Scholar

Santin, Miguel, Yanqiu Shao, Emma Verhoeven, Jack Hoeksema, Monique Flecken & Angeliek van Hout. 2021a. What the fuzz is an event result? Affectedness and telicity in the meaning of verbs across languages. In Paper presented at architectures and mechanisms for language processing conference 21 Paris, France. 2–4 September.Search in Google Scholar

Santin, Miguel, Angeliek van Hout & Monique Flecken. 2021b. Event endings in memory and language. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 36(5). 625–648. https://doi.org/10.1080/23273798.2020.1868542.Search in Google Scholar

Smith, Carlota. 1978. Jespersen’s “move and change” class and causative verbs in English. In Mohammad A. Jazayery, Edgar C. Palomé & Werner Winter (eds.), Linguistic and literary studies in honor of Archibald A. Hill, Volume 2: Descriptive linguistics, 101–109. The Hague, Paris & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.Search in Google Scholar

Solomon, Sarah, Nicholas Hindy, T. M. Altmann Gerry & Sharon Thompson-Schill. 2015. Competition between mutually exclusive object states in event comprehension. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 27(12). 2324–2338. https://doi.org/10.1162/jocn_a_00866.Search in Google Scholar

Talmy, Leonard. 2000a. Toward a cognitive semantics, Volume I: Concept structuring systems. Massachusetts: The MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6847.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Talmy, Leonard. 2000b. Toward a cognitive semantics, volume II: Typology and process in concept structuring. Massachusetts: The MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6848.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Talmy, Leonard. 2016. Properties of main verbs. Cognitive Semantics 2(2). 133–163. https://doi.org/10.1163/23526416-00202001.Search in Google Scholar

Tenny, Carol. 1994. Aspectual roles and the syntax-semantics interface. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.10.1007/978-94-011-1150-8Search in Google Scholar

ter Bekke, Marlijn, Asli Özyürek & Ercenur Ünal. 2019. Speaking but not gesturing predicts motion event memory within and across languages. In Ashok Goel, Colleen Seifert & Christian Freksa (eds.), Proceedings of the 41st annual Meeting of the cognitive science society (CogSci 2019), 2940–2946. Montreal, QB: Cognitive Science Society.Search in Google Scholar

Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Linguistics in philosophy. New York, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.10.7591/9781501743726Search in Google Scholar

Verkuyl, Henk J. 1993. A theory of aspectuality: The interaction between temporal and atemporal structure (Cambridge Studies in linguistics 64). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511597848Search in Google Scholar

von Stutterheim, Christiane, Martin Andermann, Mary Carroll, Monique Flecken & Barbara Schmiedtová. 2012. How grammaticalized concepts shape event conceptualization in language production: Insights from linguistic analysis, eye tracking data, and memory performance. Linguistics 50(4). 833–867. https://doi.org/10.1515/ling-2012-0026.Search in Google Scholar

Wang, Yaqi & Silvia Gennari. 2019. How language and event recall can shape memory for time. Cognitive Psychology 108. 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogpsych.2018.10.003.Search in Google Scholar

Wolff, Phillip. 2003. Direct causation in the linguistic coding and individuation of causal events. Cognition 88. 1–48. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(03)00004-0.Search in Google Scholar

Wright, Tony A. 2014. Strict vs. flexible accomplishment predicates. Texas: The University of Texas at Austin PhD dissertation.Search in Google Scholar

Zacks, Jeffrey M. 2020. Event perception and memory. Annual Review of Psychology 71. 165–191. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-010419-051101.Search in Google Scholar

Zacks, Jeffrey M. & Barbara Tversky. 2001. Event structure in perception and conception. Psychological Bulletin 127. 3–21. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.127.1.3.Search in Google Scholar

Zacks, Jeffrey M., Shawn Kumar, Richard A. Abrams & Ritesh Mehta. 2009. Using movement and intentions to understand human activity. Cognition 112(2). 201–216. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2009.03.007.Search in Google Scholar

Zacks, Jeffrey M., Nicole K. Speer, Khena M. Swallow, Todd S. Braver & Jeremy R. Reynolds. 2007. Event perception: A mind-brain perspective. Psychological Bulletin 133(2). 273–293. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.133.2.273.Search in Google Scholar

Zeigarnik, Bluma. 1927. Über das Behalten von erledigten und uneredigten Handlungen. Psychologische Forschung 9. 1–85. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf02409755.Search in Google Scholar

Zwaan, Rolf A. & Gabriel A. Radvansky. 1998. Situation models in language comprehension and memory. Psychological Bulletin 123(2). 162–185. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.123.2.162.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2023-04-23
Accepted: 2024-09-10
Published Online: 2024-10-23
Published in Print: 2024-11-26

© 2024 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 28.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/cog-2023-0053/html
Scroll to top button