Abstract
In this paper we give a full characterization of Nash implementability of social choice correspondences (SCCs) in allotment economies on preference domains with private values and different types of indifference. We focus on single-peaked/single-plateaued preferences with worst indifferent allocations, single-troughed preferences and single-troughed preferences with best indifferent allocations. We begin by introducing a weak variant of no-veto power, called
1 Introduction
In games and social choice theories, many domain restrictions have been used in order to obtain positive results. In most cases, these results were obtained when special conditions were imposed on preference profiles. For example, limiting the preference of agents to linear orders or allowing some very limited indifference classes simplifies the expression of the conditions considerably, as well as the proofs of results based on restricting the domains of social choice rules. Among these conditions, the well-known notions are single-peaked preferences that were introduced by Black (1948) and single-dipped preferences that were provided by Inada (1964). In addition to these properties, other important conditions have been imposed on preference profiles and they are useful tools that obtain interesting results. [1]
Nevertheless, many authors have considered that some of the conditions imposed on preferences profiles are very strong. Thus, they have tried to relax these conditions to wider classes. For example, the fact that they have only one maximal element in a single-peaked domain, without admitting the indifference of at least one other alternative, is not always considered natural. Hence, many enlargements to this domain have been explored to allow either many best indifferent elements, which are now known as single-plateaued domains, or many worst indifferent elements, which were introduced by Cantala (2004) and they are referred to as outside options. [2] We also cite the extension of the single-dipped preferences domain to a wider class of preferences where agents can express their indifference among multiple worst alternatives, termed single-trouthed preferences, or multiple best alternatives, which were introduced by Manjunath (2011) and Aragón and Caramuta (2011).
The motivation for this article is to study the implications of these extensions in the implementation literature that has a close connection with social choice theory. Before explaining the problematic and providing our contribution in this direction, we start by giving a brief definition of implementation theory. This theory studies the problem of a society that chooses a social choice correspondence (SCC) to represent the social welfare of individuals or desired outcomes and the planner confronts the difficulty of how to implement this rule. This occurs because the planner does not know the exact preferences of individuals regarding these outcomes. Thus, in order to participate with a lower cost (e. g., in the case of the construction of public goods), the agents may falsify their preferences. To ensure that they disclose their true preferences, the planner will organize a non-cooperative game among these individuals. In a given solution context, when the set of equilibrium outcomes of this game coincides with the set of socially desired alternatives, we can say that an SCC is implementable in this given solution context.
To achieve this objective, some conditions should be imposed on the SCCs that the planner hopes to implement. Thus, Maskin (1977, 1999) was the first to show that there is an important connection between the implementability of SCCs and a property now known as Maskin monotonicity. He proved that this requirement is a necessary condition for an SCC to be Nash implementable, and it becomes sufficient together with an additional property called no-veto power. Since this latter requirement fails to be satisfied for many examples of Maskin monotonic SCCs in economic and political applications like, among others, the core correspondence, the individually rational correspondence in voting problems and assignment of indivisible goods, the stable rule in matching problems, and the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence from equal division in private good economies, many studies have proposed either alternative conditions or different mechanisms to overcome this deficiency. For instance, Moore and Repullo (1990), Dutta and Sen (1991), Sjöström (1991) and Danilov (1992) provided full characterizations whereas many other authors proposed either necessary conditions, such as Ziad (1997, 1998), sufficient conditions, such as Yamato (1992) and Doghmi and Ziad (2008a), or different mechanisms like the one recently proposed by Doğan (2015) to implement the no-envy correspondence on general domains of economies.
In relation to the standard domain restrictions with private values of single-peaked and single-dipped preferences, Thomson (1990, 2010), Doghmi and Ziad (2008b), and Doghmi (2013a) tried to apply some of these theoretical results to implement many examples of solutions of the problem of fair division. On single-peaked domain, Thomson (1990, 2010) proved that only the Pareto correspondence can be implemented by Maskin’s theorem (1999). To implement the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence from equal division and their intersection, he applied Yamato’s theorem (1992). For the implementability of the intersections of the Pareto correspondence with the no-envy correspondence, and with the individually rational correspondence from equal division, these tools do not work and hence he appealed to Sjöström’s algorithm (1991). On single-peaked and single-dipped domains, Doghmi and Ziad (2008b), and Doghmi (2013a) applied the results they developed in Doghmi and Ziad (2008a) and they examined the implementability of all these correspondences in an easy way. They proved that only Maskin monotonicity is a necessary and sufficient condition to implement these unanimous solutions.
In these domains of private good economies when we allow different types of indifference between alternatives, the properties used in these previous findings do not always apply, and they are only a few studies which are interested in this topic. To our knowledge, only the recent works of Doghmi (2013b) and Doghmi and Ziad (2013a, 2013b, 2015) are concerned with this issue. They studied Nash-implementability of SCCs when preferences profile are single-plateaued, and single-dipped with best indifferent allocations. Thus, they extended the results of Doghmi and Ziad (2008b), Thomson (1990, 2010), and Doghmi (2013a) on single-peaked and single-dipped domains in considering preference profiles which admit multiple best indifferent elements. However, these studies do not cover preference profiles which contain multiple worst indifferent elements.
Our objective in this article is to fill this gap and to contribute to the understanding of the implications of implementability in these domains of economies which admit different types of indifference between alternatives. We examine in particular the following domains.
Single-peakedness with worst indifferent allocations. This class of preferences extends the standard concept of single-peaked preferences by allowing multiple worst indifferent alternatives. It was introduced by Cantala (2004)[3] and explored recently by Klaus and Bochet (2013) to study the relationship between monotonicity and strategy-proofness.
Single-plateauedness with worst indifferent allocations. This class of preferences contains two types of indifference between alternatives: multiple best indifferent elements and multiple worst indifferent elements when generalizing the well-known domains of single-peaked and single-plateaued preferences.
Single-troughedness. This class of preferences is a natural enlargement of the domain of single-dipped preferences, which requires that each agent is indifferent among several worst alternatives. These worst alternatives are called the “trough”. More recently, Bossert and Peters (2014) examined the notion of single-troughedness in a choice-theoretic setting. [4] This domain of preferences has also been used by Manjunath (2011) to characterize all rules that satisfy unanimity and strategy-proofness properties.
Single-troughedness with best indifferent allocations. This domain is an enlargement of the domain of single-dipped preferences with best indifferent allocations, which was explored recently by Aragón and Caramuta (2011) and Doghmi (2013b), but also an extension of the single-troughed domain examined by Bossert and Peters (2014), and by Manjunath (2011).
In this work we give a full characterization of Nash-implementability of SCCs on these four domains of economies. We introduce a weak variant of no-veto power, namely
The rest of this paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we introduce notations and definitions for the general setup. In Section 3, we introduce a weaker version of no-veto power and we provide a sufficient condition for Nash implementation in general environment. In Section 4, we present our main results on preference domains with private values and indifference; we discuss the challenges for these domains compared to the previous findings, we give a full characterization for Nash implementation, and we study the implementability of various well-known SCCs. In Section 5, we provide a conclusion.
2 Notations and Definitions
Let
A social choice correspondence (SCC)
A mechanism (or a game form) is given by
A Nash equilibrium of the game
A SCC
A central theorem of the implementatability of SCCs is provided by Maskin (1977/1999). It is based on the following properties:
Monotonicity: A SCC
No-veto power: A SCC
Maskin (1977/1999) proved that any Nash implementable correspondence must satisfy Maskin monotonicity and, when the number of agents is at least three, any SCC that satisfies Maskin monotonicity and no-veto power is Nash implementable.
3 A Weak Property of No-veto Power for Sufficiency
Recently, Doghmi and Ziad (2015) provided a full characterization for the implementability of SCCs in private good economies with single-plateaued preferences. They showed that any SCC that has full range is Nash implementable if and only if it satisfies Maskin monotonicity. To derive this result, they provided a new sufficient condition in general environment. Nevertheless, this result of general setup does not apply to domains of economies which admit multiple worst indifferent alternatives. To fill this gap and generalize these results for different types of indifference, we introduce a weak version of no-veto power that covers a large domain of preferences with indifference. To define this property, we start with the following definition.
(Indifferent options subset)
For any agent
Now, we introduce the weak property of no-veto power that we call
(
An SCC
Loosely speaking, the property of
Let
R. | |||
a | c | b | |
b,c,d,e | a | a,d | |
b,d | c | ||
e | e |
a | a,c | b,c | |
d | b,d | a,d | |
e | e | e | |
b | |||
c |
Let
Observation 1:
Proof. For the part (
Concerning the part (
The second property, called
(
An SCC
The next result provides a sufficient condition for an SCC to be Nash implementable. We shall use this result, which differs from the previous findings in the literature, as a principle tool to prove the main result in the next section.
Let
Proof. See appendix.
4 Main Result on Preference Domains with Private Values and Indifference
In this section, we present a model of allotment economies in preference domains with private values and different types of indifference, which generalize single-peaked and single-dipped preference domains. We show that
4.1 Model and Preference Domains
An amount
Single-peaked preferences with worst indifferent allocations: A preference relation
A preference relation
The class of all single-peaked preference relations with worst indifferent allocations is represented by
Single-plateaued preferences with worst indifferent allocations: A preference relation
A preference relation
The class of all single-plateaued preference relations with worst indifferent allocations is represented by
This super-domain is an enlargement of single-peaked, single-plateaued, and Cantala’s preferences (2004), i. e., single-peaked preferences with worst indifferent allocations. It lies between these preferences domains and that of Dasgupta and al. (1979), where there is a top plateau of indifferent best elements with additional plateaus. [7]
Now, we present the inverse configuration of the above preference domains.
Single-troughed preferences: A preference relation
The class of all single-troughed preference relations is represented by
Single-troughed preferences with best indifferent allocations: A preference relation
The class of all single-troughed preference relations with best indifferent allocations is represented by
We denote these four domain restrictions with indifferent allocations by
A feasible allocation for the economy
4.2 The Challenges for the ℜ D R I A Domains Compared to the Previous Findings
Before providing our main result in the next subsection, we discuss here the challenges of the implementability of SCCs on the domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
4.3 Full Characterization for Nash Implementation on ℜ D R I A
To provide a full characterization for an SCC to be Nash implementable on the domain restrictions with indifferent allocations (
Let
The proof of Lemma 1 is omitted because it follows the same reasoning as Lemma 1 in Doghmi and Ziad (2008b).
The following proposition shows that our new property of
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
The proof of this proposition is omitted, it is immediate from Lemma 1. Next, we provide the definition of the full range property.
(Full range)
An SCC
The full range requirement is satisfied vacuously for all SCCs considered in this study on
The following result extends Lemma 2 of Doghmi and Ziad (2015) from single-plateaued preferences domain to a large domain of preferences with indifference.
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
Proof. We consider the domain restriction
By Propositions 1 and 2, we obtain the following corollary.
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
From Theorem 1, Propositions 1–2, and Corollary 1 we give the following result.
Let
In the following proposition, we show that
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
Proof. Let
Situation 1: We consider the domain restriction
i) If
ii) If
iii) If
Situation 2: We consider the domain restriction
i) If
ii) If
Situation 3: We consider the domain restriction
i) If
ii) If
iii) If
iv) If
Situation 4: We consider the domain restriction
i) If
ii) If
iii) If
By Corollary 2 and Proposition 3 we complete the proof of the following main result in this work.
Let
This result also applies to the domains restrictions of single-peaked preferences (
Let
In the next subsection, we provide some applications of Theorem 2 by examining the implementability of some well-known SCCs.
4.4 Examples of Some Monotonic and Nonmonotonic Well-known SCCs under Domain Restrictions with Indifferent Allocations
To apply the result of Theorem 2 to the problem of the fair allocation of an infinite divisible commodity among a group of agents, we introduce a variety of well-known solutions to this problem and we inspect whether these correspondences are implementable on the
4.4.1 Some Well-known Correspondences
We begin by defining the no-envy solution that was introduced by Foley (1967).
No-envy correspondence,
Individually rational correspondence from equal division,
Pareto correspondence,
Pareto indifferent,
In the next definition, we assume that for all agent the share of an allocation
Strong Pareto indifferent,
In addition to these correspondences, we also introduce some solutions produced by intersections. We consider the intersection of the no-envy correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division (
4.4.2 Examples of Monotonic SCCs under Domain Restrictions with Indifferent Allocations ℜ D R I A
In this subsection, we first give examples of SCCs that are monotonic in the unrestricted domains and also monotonic in the current setup, and we second provide exemples of SCCs that are not monotonic in the unrestricted domains, but monotonic and therefore Nash implementable in our context.
4.4.2.1 Examples of SCCs that are monotonic in unrestricted domains
The monotonic SCCs that we examine their implementability are the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence from equal division and their intersection. We give the following observation.
Observation 2: In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
Since the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence and their intersection are monotonic in unrestricted domains, it is trivial that these correspondences are monotonic in our area. Thus, the proof of Observation 2 is omitted.
It follows from Thomson’s results (1990, 2010) and Proposition 8 of Doghmi (2013a) that the no-envy solution, the individually rational correspondence from equal division and (
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
4.4.2.2 Examples of SCCs that are nonmonotonic in unrestricted domains
In Example 2 we show that the
Let
R. | |||
a,b,e,f | c | c | |
d | a,b,e,f | a,b,e,f | |
c | d | d |
a | a | a | |
b,c,e,f | b,c,e,f | b,c,e,f | |
d | d | d |
From the definition of
As mentioned in Subsection 4.4.1, we construct new solutions produced from the intersections of the SPI correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division (
To prove that the (
Now, we consider the same general of economies used in Doğan (2015) and we show in Example 2 that the (
Let
R. | |||
From the definition of (
Finally, the (
In Proposition 4 that follows, we show that the correspondences of
In the private goods economies under domain restrictions with indifferent allocations
Let
4.4.3 Examples of Nonmonotonic SCCs under Domain Restrictions when the Preferences are Single-peaked/single-plateaued with Worst Indifferent Allocations (ℜ s p w i a , ℜ s p l w i a )
The next proposition shows that the Pareto correspondence and its intersections with the no-envy correspondence, and with the individually rational correspondence from equal division do not satisfy Maskin monotonicity. Therefore, they are not Nash implementable in private goods economies when the preferences are single-peaked/single-plateaued with worst indifferent allocations. [11]
In private goods economies, when preferences are single-peaked/single-plateaued with worst indifferent allocations, the Pareto correspondence and its intersections with the no-envy correspondence, and with the individually rational correspondence from equal division do not satisfy Maskin monotonicity, and thus they are not Nash implementable.
Let

The
Note that
4.4.4 Examples of nonmonotonic SCCs under domain restrictions when the preferences are single-troughed/single-troughed with best indifferent allocations (ℜ s t , ℜ s t b i a )
It follows from Proposition 5 of Doghmi and Ziad (2013a) that the Pareto correspondence does not satisfy Maskin monotonicity when we allow multiple worst indifferent allocations. In the following, we show that in contrast to Doghmi’s result (2013a), the intersections of the Pareto correspondence with the no-envy correspondence fail to satisfy Maskin monotonicity when we allow multiple best indifferent allocations, as proved in the following proposition.
In private goods economies, when preferences are single-troughed/single-troughed with best indifferent allocations, the Pareto correspondence and its intersections with the no-envy correspondence, and with the individually rational correspondence from equal division do not satisfy Maskin monotonicity, and thus they are not Nash implementable.
Let

The
Note that
5 Conclusion
In this study, we provided a full characterization of Nash implementation in many restrictive domains by allowing different types of indifference between allocations. First, we extended our characterization from a single-peaked domain to Cantala’s domain (2004) by allowing multiple worst indifferent allocations, where we also implemented some well-known correspondences. Second, in an inverse configuration, we enlarged Doghmi’s characterization (2013a) from a single-dipped domain to a single-troughed domain by providing some examples that support this result. Finally, we generalized our characterization by allowing multiple best and worst indifferent allocations at the same time. These results can be exploited to examine the connection between strategy-proofness and the implementation literature as in Diss et al.(Diss, Doghmi, and Tlidi 2015).
Appendix
Proof. Let
Rule 1: If for each
Rule 2: If for some
Rule 3: In any other situation,
Let us show that
Step 1. For all
Let
Step 2. For all
Let
Case a:
Let
Case b:
There are two subcases:
Subcase
By definition, for all
Next, for any other deviation
Subcase
By the same reasoning used in case
Case c:
Let
Case d:
Acknowledgement
I would like to thank Abderrahmane Ziad for providing many and very useful comments. I am very thankful as well to the participants of GATE Lyon Saint-Etienne Seminar for their valuable remarks. I would also thank two anonymous referees for their remarks and suggestions that have improved the quality of the paper considerably. All remaining errors are mine.
References
Aragón, G. -A., and D. -M. Caramuta. 2011. Single-Dipped Preferences with Indifferences: Strong Group Strategy-Proof and Unanimous Social Choice Functions. Working Paper, Universitat Autnoma De Barcelona.Search in Google Scholar
Barberà, S. 2007. “Indifferences and Domains Restrictions.” Analysis and Kritik 29:146–62.10.1515/auk-2007-0203Search in Google Scholar
Berga, D. 1998. “Strategy-Proofness and Single-Plateaued Preferences.” Mathematical Social Sciences 35:105–20.10.1016/S0165-4896(97)00036-XSearch in Google Scholar
Berga, D., and B. Moreno. 2009. “Strategic Requirements with Indifference: Single-Peaked Versus Single-Plateaued Preferences.” Social Choice and Welfare 32:275–98.10.1007/s00355-008-0323-ySearch in Google Scholar
Berga, D. 2006. “A Note on Strategy-Proofness and Single-Plateaued Preferences.” Working paper.Search in Google Scholar
Bossert, W., and H. Peters. 2013. “Single-Plateaued Choice.” Mathematical Social Sciences 66:134–9.10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2013.01.008Search in Google Scholar
Bossert, W., and H. Peters. 2014. “Single-Basined Choice.” Journal of Mathematical Economics 52:162–168.10.1016/j.jmateco.2013.12.010Search in Google Scholar
Cantala, D. 2004. “Choosing the Level of a Public Good When Agents Have an Outside Option.” Social Choice and Welfare 22:491–514.10.1007/s00355-003-0228-8Search in Google Scholar
Dasgupta, P., P. Hammond, and E. Maskin. 1979. “The Implementation of Social Choice Rules: Some General Results on Incentive Compatibility.” Review of Economic Studies 46:181–216.10.2307/2297045Search in Google Scholar
Danilov, V. 1992. “Implementation via Nash Equilibrium.” Econometrica 60:43–56.10.2307/2951675Search in Google Scholar
Diss, M., A. Doghmi, and A. Tlidi. 2015. “Strategy Proofness and Unanimity in Private Good Economies with Single-Peaked Preferences.” Working paper N° 1528, GATE Lyon Saint-Etienne, available at SSRN 2688465.Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A. 2013a. “Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences.” Games 4:38–49.10.3390/g4010038Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A. 2013b. “Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies When Preferences Are Single-Dipped with Best Indifferent Allocations.” Mathematical Economics Letters 1:35–42.10.1515/mel-2013-0003Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A., and A. Ziad. 2008a. “Reexamination of Maskin’s Theorem on Nash Implementability.” Economics Letters 100:150–2.10.1016/j.econlet.2007.12.009Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A., and A. Ziad. 2008b. “Nash Implementation in Exchange Economies with Singlepeaked Preferences.” Economics Letters 100:157–60.10.1016/j.econlet.2007.12.010Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A., and A. Ziad. 2013a. “On Partially Honest Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies with Restricted Domains: A Sufficient Condition.” The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics 13:1–14.10.1515/bejte-2012-0028Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A., and A. Ziad. 2013b. “Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies with Single-Plateaued Preferences.” Working paper.Search in Google Scholar
Doghmi, A., and A. Ziad. 2015. “Nash Implementation in Private Good Economies with Single-Plateaued Preferences and in Matching Problems.” Mathematical Social Sciences 73:32–9.10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2014.11.002Search in Google Scholar
Doğan, B. 2015. “Nash-Implementation of the No-Envy Solution on General Domains of Economies.” Working paper, available at SSRN 2637965.Search in Google Scholar
Dutta, B., and A. Sen. 1991. “A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for Two-Person Nash Implementation.” Review of Economic Studies 58:121–8.10.2307/2298049Search in Google Scholar
Ehlers, L. 2002. “Probabilistic Allocation Rules and Single-Dipped Preferences.” Social Choice and Welfare 19:325–48.10.1007/s003550100114Search in Google Scholar
Foley, D. 1967. “Resource Allocation and the Public Sector.” Yale Economic Essays 7:45–98.Search in Google Scholar
Gaertner, W. 2001. Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge, University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511492303Search in Google Scholar
Inada, K. I. 1964. “A Note on the Simple Majority Decision Rule.” Econometrica 32:525–31.10.2307/1910176Search in Google Scholar
Klaus, B., and O. Bochet. 2013. “The Relation Between Monotonicity and Strategy-Proofness.” Social Choice and Welfare 40:41–63.10.1007/s00355-011-0586-6Search in Google Scholar
Manjunath, V. 2011. “Strategic and Normative Analysis of Ressource Allocation Problems.” Phd. thesis, University of Rechester, New York.Search in Google Scholar
Maskin, E. 1999. “Nash Equilibrium and Welfare Optimality. M.I.T. Mimeo, 1977.” Published 1999 in the Review of Economic Studies 66:23–38.10.1111/1467-937X.00076Search in Google Scholar
Moore, J., and R. Repullo. 1990. “Nash Implementation: A Full Characterization.” Econometrica 58:1083–100.10.2307/2938301Search in Google Scholar
Moulin, H., 1984. “Generelized Condorcet-Winners for Single-Peaked and Single-Plateau Preferences.” Social Choice and Welfare 1:127–147.10.1007/BF00452885Search in Google Scholar
Sjöström, T. 1991. “On the Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Nash Implementation.” Social Choice and Welfare 8:333–40.10.1007/BF00183044Search in Google Scholar
Thomson, W. 1990. “Manipulation and Implementation to Solutions to the Problem of Fair Allocations when Preferences are Single-Peaked.” mimeo, University of Rochester.Search in Google Scholar
Thomson, W. 2010. “Implementation to Solutions to the Problem of Fair Allocations When Preferences Are Single-Peaked.” Review of Economic Design 14:1–15.10.1007/s10058-009-0092-9Search in Google Scholar
Yamato, T. 1992. “On Nash Implementation of Social Choice Correspondences.” Games and Economic Behavior 4:484–92.10.1016/0899-8256(92)90051-SSearch in Google Scholar
Ziad, A. 1997. “On the Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Nash Implementation.” Economics Letters 56:209–13.10.1016/S0165-1765(97)81902-7Search in Google Scholar
Ziad, A. 1998. “A New Necessary Condition for Nash Implementation.” Journal of Mathematical Economics 29:381–7.10.1016/S0304-4068(97)00014-1Search in Google Scholar
©2016 by De Gruyter
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Research Articles
- On the Rejectability of the Subjective Expected Utility Theory
- Informal Insurance Networks
- Price Reveal Auctions
- The Rationality of Expectations Formation
- Optimal Penalties for Repeat Offenders – The Role of Offence History
- On the Price of Commitment Assets in a General Equilibrium Model with Credit Constraints and Tempted Consumers
- Competition in a Posted-Salary Matching Market under Private Information
- Tenacious Selection of Nash Equilibrium
- Political Support and Civil Disobedience: A Social Interaction Approach
- Predicting Empirical Patterns in Viewing Japanese TV Dramas Using Case-Based Decision Theory
- Sellers’ Implicit Collusion in Directed Search Markets
- University Competition and Transnational Education: The Choice of Branch Campus
- Notes
- On Nash Implementability in Allotment Economies under Domain Restrictions with Indifference
- Building Reputation in a War of Attrition Game: Hawkish or Dovish Stance?
- Profit Tax Evasion under Wage Bargaining Structure
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Research Articles
- On the Rejectability of the Subjective Expected Utility Theory
- Informal Insurance Networks
- Price Reveal Auctions
- The Rationality of Expectations Formation
- Optimal Penalties for Repeat Offenders – The Role of Offence History
- On the Price of Commitment Assets in a General Equilibrium Model with Credit Constraints and Tempted Consumers
- Competition in a Posted-Salary Matching Market under Private Information
- Tenacious Selection of Nash Equilibrium
- Political Support and Civil Disobedience: A Social Interaction Approach
- Predicting Empirical Patterns in Viewing Japanese TV Dramas Using Case-Based Decision Theory
- Sellers’ Implicit Collusion in Directed Search Markets
- University Competition and Transnational Education: The Choice of Branch Campus
- Notes
- On Nash Implementability in Allotment Economies under Domain Restrictions with Indifference
- Building Reputation in a War of Attrition Game: Hawkish or Dovish Stance?
- Profit Tax Evasion under Wage Bargaining Structure