Home On the Role of Sales Taxes for Efficient Compensation of Property Loss Under Strict Liability
Article Open Access

On the Role of Sales Taxes for Efficient Compensation of Property Loss Under Strict Liability

  • Florian Baumann and Tim Friehe EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: November 22, 2023
Become an author with De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

When a victim loses property due to an injurer’s wrongful act, it must be decided whether the damages award should include the sales taxes associated with the lost property’s replacement. This is especially acute when the victim can make other use of the damages award than replacement. This paper compares regimes that differ in how they treat sales taxes, focusing on possible distortions of consumption and care choices. We find that regimes that include sales taxes in damages awards only when incurred to replace the lost property (as, for instance, the German Civil Code does) induce suboptimal consumption and care incentives. Distortions of care incentives also depend on the nature of care expenditures (monetary or non-monetary).

JEL Classification: H24; K13

1 Introduction

Compensating victims of wrongful acts is an essential objective of tort law for its own sake (e.g. Cooter 1991). In addition, in the standard unilateral care model, full compensation of victims induces efficient care on the part of the injurer (e.g. Visscher 2009). Very much in this spirit, for instance, Section 249 (1) of the German Civil Code states that: “A person who is liable in damages must restore the position that would exist if the circumstance obliging him to pay damages had not occurred.” Often, the injurer does not directly restore the victim’s position but instead pays a monetary transfer, i.e. a damages award.[1]

In principle, the victim is free to use the compensatory transfer for any purpose and is not obliged to establish the pre-accident condition (e.g. Schäfer and Ott 2022, p. 294). However, in seeming contrast to this general principle, Section 249 (2) Sentence 2 of the German Civil Code establishes a link between the use and the amount of the compensatory transfer: “When a thing is damaged, the monetary amount required under Sentence 1 only includes value-added tax if and to the extent that it is actually incurred.” For example, if the victim’s car were wrecked as a result of an accident, the victim would get compensated for the relevant sales tax when the victim buys a substitute car of less or equal value but not when the victim chooses to buy a bicycle instead. Similar considerations can be found in other jurisdictions as well; see, for example, the Lousiana Supreme Court in State Farm v. Berthelot, 98–1011 (La. 4/13/99), WL 213023 (La.) and Section 1323 of the Austrian Civil Code (discussed by, for instance, Achatz 2004).

This paper analyzes the social desirability of such a norm and three plausible alternatives. From an economic point of view, the injurer’s care and the victim’s consumption incentives are influenced by how the damages regime treats the sales tax (as this treatment can distort relative prices). Furthermore, with sales taxes as part of the damages award, a difference may occur between private and social losses (a prominent topic in law and economics, starting with Bishop 1982; for a more recent contribution, see, e.g. Dari-Mattiacci and Schäfer 2007). The social loss is minimal for a damages regime stipulating the damages award independently of the victim’s replacement decision. The reason is that this independence avoids distorted consumption choices by the victim. Moreover, at least when injurer care is non-monetary, we argue that efficiency is better served when the sales tax is not included in the damages award, although the victim remains under-compensated. This is intuitive, given that the sales taxes paid for replacement do not represent social harm.

Our analysis highlights three important elements: First, the damages regime’s treatment of sales taxes can induce distortions in victims’ consumption decisions as it influences the relative prices of goods. Second, sales taxes do not constitute social harm. Third, the damages regime’s treatment of sales taxes can distort injurers’ care choices. From an efficiency-guided policy perspective, the first aspect argues for making compensatory transfers independent of how the victim later uses these transfers. According to the second element, damages should not include sales taxes, unless such practice distorts injurers’ care incentives, as indicated by the third element. Such a distortion results when care expenditures are subject to sales-taxes as well.

We contribute to the extensive literature on the economics of tort law (see, e.g. the handbook chapter by Shavell 2007). We are unaware of any analysis regarding whether the socially optimal damages award should include sales taxes when the property is lost due to an accident. This is striking given the practical importance of the issue and the extensive literature on the optimal level of damages (e.g. Baumann and Friehe 2009; 2015; Kaplow and Shavell 1996; Polinsky and Rubinfeld 1988; Shavell 2007). In the preceding literature and starting with Shavell (1987), the inclusion of taxes in damages awards has been discussed regarding lost income (e.g. Dodge 1992, among others). Shavell explains that the level of damages should be equal to the pre-tax income, which is based on the distinction between private and social harm and contrasts with our finding for sales taxes. In the domain of the law & economics of crime, Nussim and Tabbach (2009) discuss incentive effects resulting from how the tax code treats monetary sanctions and litigation expenses.

The rest of the paper is structured as follows: In Section 2, we present our model. The analysis is contained in Section 3. In Section 4, we offer some concluding remarks.

2 Model

We consider a framework with a potential victim and a potential injurer who is subject to strict liability.

2.1 Potential Victim

The well-being of the potential victim can be described by the Cobb–Douglas utility function[2]

(1) U ( x , y ) = x y ,

where x is the amount of some composite consumption good and y is the quality level of the good prone to be lost in an accident. The composite good stands for a basket of goods including all commodities other than the good at risk of an accident which the potential victim consumes. We assume that the quantity of the good at risk of an accident is fixed at one so that only the quality of this good is variable. For example, we may imagine that the potential victim surely needs one car and that y represents the car’s quality.

With both products being sold by competitive firms, the goods’ net prices equal their social (resource) costs and amount to p per unit of good x and 1 for each quality unit of good y. A value-added sales tax is imposed on both goods at rate t. The potential victim has exogenous income m and a good of quality y ̄ . The idea of the endowment with a good of quality y ̄ is that it was purchased at some previous point in time and represents the property value that would be lost in an accident (e.g. the potential victim’s car). The quality level y ̄ may no longer constitute the individual’s optimal quality level, for example, because the quality level y ̄ was purchased when the potential victim was still subject to uncertainty regarding income m. However, due to the frictions created by the sales, tax the potential victim might still prefer keeping the good with quality y ̄ to selling the good (receiving its net value) and replacing it with a good of different quality (paying sales taxes). In the following, we focus on this case in which the potential victim prefers keeping y ̄ and spending m on good x in the case without accident; that is, the case in which y ̄ still is reasonable given income m. Given the Cobb–Douglas utility function, this is the case as long as the resulting expenditures for composite good which equal monetary income m are not to different from the gross value y ̄ ( 1 + t ) of the other consumption good. In consequence, this means that the potential victim only chooses the quality level of the good anew after the property was lost in an accident.

More specifically, the potential victim prefers keeping the quality level when the income lies in some range:

Lemma 1

The individual prefers keeping y ̄ to selling it when m ∈ [m L , m H ], where m L = y ̄ 1 + t t 2 < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) < m H = y ̄ 1 + t + t 2 .

Proof

The individual’s maximized utility when she keeps the good amounts to

(2) U y ̄ = m p ( 1 + t ) × y ̄

as the individual spends m on good x, thereby obtaining m p ( 1 + t ) units of x. The individual’s maximized utility when she sells y ̄ and thereby obtains a budget m + y ̄ to spend on both x and y results at

(3) U * = m + y ̄ 2 p ( 1 + t ) × m + y ̄ 2 ( 1 + t ) .

From a comparison of maximized utility levels, we find that the individual keeps y ̄ (i.e. that U y ̄ U * ) when m ∈ [m L , m H ] where

m L = y ̄ 1 + t t and m H = y ̄ 1 + t + t .

The intuition for the existence of an upper and a lower bound for income m is that the potential victim would want to correct the quality level y either if the current quality level turns out too low given high income m or too high given low income m. The upper and the lower bound on income stem from the fact that, when a Cobb–Douglas utility function can describe the decision-maker’s well-being, optimal consumption results from sharing the budget equally on the different goods consumed. When the income level is either high or low, the levels of x and y will be too imbalanced, meaning adjusting y creates a utility gain. Note that the tax level drives the interval width. In the following analysis, we assume that the income level is from this interval.

Assumption 1

The level of income falls inside the interval [m L , m H ].

2.2 Potential Injurer

The risk-neutral injurer can implement care s ≥ 0 in order to influence the accident probability π(s), where 0 < π < 1 and π′ < 0 < π″. The potential injurer’s costs of care amount to C(s) = s(1 + αt); that is, we assume that a share 0 ≤ α ≤ 1 represents care measures that are monetary and thus also subject to the sales tax.[3] The injurer minimizes the sum of expected liability and care costs and spends the remaining income on some consumption goods.

2.3 Damages

In the event of an accident, the injurer is held strictly liable for the damages amounting to D. Damages always include the net value of property destroyed y ̄ . Concerning the inclusion of sales taxes into the damages awards, we compare four different regimes:

  1. Unconditional compensation of only the market value of the lost property excluding sales taxes: D ( a ) = y ̄

  2. Unconditional compensation of the market value and the sales tax required to replace the good with the same quality: D ( b ) = y ̄ ( 1 + t )

  3. Compensation of the sales tax conditional on the victim repurchasing the same quality level as before:

    D ( c ) = y ̄ ( 1 + t )  if  y = y ̄ y ̄  otherwise .

  4. Conditional compensation of sales taxes to the extent to which it is incurred but capped at y ̄ t : D ( d ) = min { y ̄ + y t , y ̄ ( 1 + t ) }

Scenario (d) represents Section 249 of the German Civil Code, whereas the other scenarios represent possible departures.

2.4 Tax Revenue

Both potential victim and injurer spend their entire exogenous income on some goods. Sales tax revenue is therefore independent of the damages award and of whether an accident occurs.[4]

2.5 Timing

The injurer chooses care s, and Nature determines whether or not an accident occurs. In the event of an accident, the damages award is transferred from the injurer to the victim. Finally, the (potential) victim and the injurer make consumption choices.

3 Analysis

This section considers the victim’s consumption and utility, the injurer’s care incentives, and overall welfare.

3.1 Victim’s Consumption and Utility

In the no-accident state, the potential victim spends m on good x sold at a total price p(1 + t) and obtains utility

U y ̄ = m p ( 1 + t ) × y ̄ .

In the accident state, the victim uses his income m and the compensatory transfer to decide on the consumption quantity x and the quality level y. For the four different damages regimes considered, we obtain the following:

3.1.1 Regime (a)

This case mirrors a situation in which the individual is forced to sell his endowment y ̄ before making purchase decisions. Given the Cobb–Douglas utility function from (1), the victim spends half of total income m + y ̄ on each type of good attaining utility

(4) U ( a ) = ( m + y ̄ ) 2 4 p ( 1 + t ) 2 < U y ̄ .

With m ∈ [m L , m H ], the victim is worse off from the accident. This holds as, from the victim’s perspective, the accident and the subsequent compensation are tantamount to a forced property sale at its net price (an outcome dominated by keeping the property). In terms of utility, the victim remains undercompensated.

3.1.2 Regime (b)

The victim spends half of his budget m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) on each type of good and enjoys utility equal to

U ( b ) = ( m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) ) 2 4 p ( 1 + t ) 2 U y ̄ .

The victim can use the compensatory transfer flexibly, which allows him to attain a higher utility in the accident state than in the no-accident state unless y = y ̄ is the victim’s utility-maximizing choice (in which case utility remains unchanged). In terms of utility, the victim is weakly overcompensated.

3.1.3 Regime (c)

If the victim were not to choose y ̄ as a replacement for the lost property, his maximization problem coincides with Regime (a). Therefore, with m ∈ [m L , m H ], damages regime (c) induces the victim to establish the pre-accident circumstances because U y ̄ > U ( a ) ; that is, the victim prefers to choose y = y ̄ . Consequently, the victim is fully compensated since consumption quantities remain unchanged and the accident-state utility matches the no-accident-state utility,

U ( c ) = U y ̄ .

3.1.4 Regime (d)

This regime ensures a minimum compensatory transfer of y ̄ and a reimbursement of sales taxes incurred up to the level y ̄ t . In that sense, this regime subsidizes the purchase of y up to a level of y ̄ . The victim’s budget constraint displays a kink at y = y ̄ and reads

m + y ̄ = p ( 1 + t ) x + y y y ̄ m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) = p ( 1 + t ) x + ( 1 + t ) y y > y ̄ .

The victim chooses[5]

y ( d ) = m + y ̄ 2 m L m < y ̄ y ̄ y ̄ m < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) 2 ( 1 + t ) y ̄ ( 1 + t ) m m H .

and obtains utility

U ( d ) = ( m + y ̄ ) 2 4 p ( 1 + t ) > U y ̄ m L m < y ̄ U y ̄ y ̄ m < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) U ( b ) > U y ̄ y ̄ ( 1 + t ) m m H .

For all m [ y ̄ , y ̄ ( 1 + t ) ] , the victim sticks to y = y ̄ because of the discontinuous price increase for a higher quality of good y at y ̄ . In this range, the victim obtains the same utility level with an accident as without one and otherwise gets overcompensated in terms of utility.

3.2 Injurer’s Care Incentives

Given the victim’s post-accident decisions, the level of damages in the event of an accident amount to

(5) D ( a ) = y ̄ < D ( d ) = y ̄ + t × min { y ( d ) , y ̄ } D ( b ) = D ( c ) = y ̄ ( 1 + t ) ,

where we use how victims will behave in Regimes (c) and (d), which the injurer is also assumed to anticipate.

The injurer chooses care to minimize the sum of his expected liability and care costs:

C I = s ( 1 + α t ) + π ( s ) D ( i ) , ( i ) = ( a ) , ( b ) , ( c ) , ( d ) .

To do so, the injurer chooses care to equate marginal costs and marginal savings in expected compensatory transfers

(6) ( 1 + α t ) = π ( s ( i ) ) D ( i ) , ( i ) = ( a ) , ( b ) , ( c ) , ( d ) ,

which, using (5) and the curvature of π, gives rise to the following ranking of injurer care levels across regimes

(7) s ( a ) < s ( d ) s ( b ) = s ( c ) .

Compensatory transfers after an accident and the induced care level are lowest in Regime (a) and maximal in Regimes (b) and (c).

3.3 Welfare Comparison of Damages Regimes

Our description of damages regimes identified regime-dependent victim utility and injurer care levels. To assess the welfare implications of the different regimes, we must (i) transform the parties’ utilities to make them comparable and (ii) account for the difference between private and social costs (the former include sales taxes while the latter are relevant for welfare). With sales tax revenue constant across regimes, we can focus on effects on the injurer and the victim. To achieve these objectives, we use a measure of (real) social resource expenditures where one unit of quality of the good y serves as our numeraire (since it has a social cost of one).

In Regime (i), the injurer spends s (i)(1 + αt) on care but s (i) αt constitutes a tax payment and thus no social cost. The social care cost amount to s (i). In the event of an accident, the injurer pays damages equal to D (i). The injurer thereby loses real income in the amount of D (i)/(1 + t) since he would have paid sales taxes equal to tD (i)/(1 + t) on any other taxed expenditure possible for him without damage payment. Taken together, in Regime (i), the injurer incurs a social cost amounting to

S C I , ( i ) = s ( i ) + π ( s ( i ) ) D ( i ) 1 + t .

Next, we translate the change in victim utility into a real resource cost. For this, we use a concept similar to the expenditure function.[6] Again, we account for the difference between private expenditures and social costs created by sales taxes, and focus on the latter. Fundamentally, given the utility function U and since good x has a resource cost of p whereas a unit of quality y a resource cost of one, optimal consumption levels ought to be x = R/(2p) and y = R/2 for any level of resources R. Maximum utility amounts to U = R 2/(4p) and, consequently, (minimum) resource expenditures to achieve the utility level U are given by

R = 2 p U .

In an accident, the victim incurs a social cost amounting to the difference between the utility level U y ̄ and U (i). We express this utility difference by the corresponding difference between R y ̄ and R (i) to have comparability with the injurer’s social cost. Accordingly, expected social costs incurred by the victim are given by

S C V , ( i ) = π ( s ( i ) ) R y ̄ R ( i )

such that the total expected social costs of accidents and care measures in regime (i) amount to

S C ( i ) = S C I , ( i ) + S C V , ( i ) = s ( i ) + π ( s ( i ) ) R y ̄ R ( i ) + D ( i ) 1 + t .

When applied to the victim’s utility levels in the no-accident state and the different regimes, our approach leads to

R y ̄ = 2 m y ̄ 1 + t ; R ( a ) = m + y ̄ 1 + t ; R ( b ) = m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) 1 + t ; R ( c ) = R y ̄

and

R ( d ) = m + y ̄ 1 + t m L m < y ̄ R y ̄ y ̄ m < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) R ( b ) y ̄ ( 1 + t ) m m H .

Using these resource levels, we obtain the following social costs:

S C ( a ) = s ( a ) + π ( s ( a ) ) 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t S C ( b ) = s ( b ) + π ( s ( b ) ) 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t S C ( c ) = s ( c ) + π ( s ( c ) ) y ̄

and[7]

S C ( d ) = s ( d ) + π ( s ( d ) ) × 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t + m + y ̄ 2 2 + t 2 1 + t 1 + t m L m < y ̄ y ̄ y ̄ m < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t y ̄ ( 1 + t ) m m H .

First, consider the different levels of social harm in the event of an accident. The social harm is equal in Regimes (a) and (b) and, with

2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t < y ̄ ,

lower than in Regime (c) and, if m L m < y ̄ ( 1 + t ) , lower than in Regime (d). This is due to the distortion in the victim’s consumption choices in the latter two regimes where, from the victim’s point of view, sales taxes differ for the two goods. This allows us to conclude that Regime (b) dominates Regime (c) in terms of welfare, given that the induced injurer’s care levels are the same in the two regimes, see (7). Similarly, Regime (b) weakly dominates Regime (d) for y ̄ m m H .

Next, we turn to the optimality of care decisions in the remaining Regimes (a), (b), and (d), where the latter is considered for m L m < y ̄ as it is weakly dominated otherwise. With SH denoting social harm in the event of an accident, efficient safety is characterized by

1 = π ( s ) S H

whereas injurer care is determined by (6). The levels of regime-dependent social harm in the event of an accident are ranked as follows:

(8) S H ( a ) = S H ( b ) < S H ( d , m < y ̄ ) < y ̄ .

In other words, the damages award exceeds social harm in all regimes. This implies that care will be inefficient unless the difference in social and private marginal care costs, 1 compared to 1 + αt, perfectly balances this difference between social harm and private damages.

When care is completely non-monetary (i.e. when α = 0) and therefore not subject to the sales tax, the injurer’s care incentives are always excessive. Social and private marginal costs of care are perfectly aligned, but marginal personal benefits of care surpass marginal social benefits. In this case, Regime (a) outperforms Regimes (b) and (d), given the lowest level of social harm and a minor upward distortion in care incentives.

The private marginal costs of care increase in all regimes with the share of monetary precautions that require tax payments. Whereas care incentives remain excessive in Regimes (b) and (d), the injurer may choose lower than efficient care in Regime (a). For high values of α, Regime (a) may be inferior to one of the other regimes.

In summary, we find:

Proposition 1

Suppose that Assumption 1 applies and that all precautions are non-monetary (i.e., that α = 0). In that case, the damages award D ( a ) = y ̄ that denies compensation of the sales taxes outperforms all other regimes in terms of efficiency. In contrast, with a sufficiently large share of monetary precautions (i.e., when α is sufficiently large), Regime (a) can be inferior to Regimes (b) or (d).

The result is interesting in that it establishes that the policy recommendation for the sales tax case may contrast with the policy recommendation for the income tax case in the event of lost earnings. Whereas the income tax constitutes a social loss due to lower production and should be compensated to instill efficient care incentives (Shavell 1987), a property loss redirects spending, and sales taxes incurred when replacing lost property do not constitute social harm.

4 Conclusions

Whenever an accident creates property loss, the level of damages must be assessed, and whether damages should include sales taxes must be decided. In this paper, we investigated several possible regimes that differ concerning how they treat sales taxes. Our analysis includes a regime close to the requirement stated in Section 249 of the German Civil Code, stipulating that damages should consist of the sales tax to the extent that the victim incurs it to replace the lost property.

Our analysis carved out three main aspects that are important for efficiency: (1) possible distortions in the victim’s replacement decision due to the damages regime’s treatment of sales taxes, (2) the observation that sales taxes for replacement do not constitute social harm, and (3) possible distortions of injurer’s care incentives due to the regime’s treatment of sales taxes. Combining the three aspects, not including the sales tax in the damages award, is the most efficient regime, as long as care costs are primarily non-monetary and untaxed. This regime guarantees undistorted victim consumption choices as the damages award is independent of the consumer’s replacement decision and aligns the injurer’s care investments more closely to the efficient one. However, the regime implies less than full victim compensation.


Corresponding author: Tim Friehe, University of Marburg, Public Economics Group, Am Plan 2, 35037 Marburg, Germany; CESifo, Munich, Germany; and EconomiX, Paris, France, E-mail:

Acknowledgment

The authors thank an anonymous reviewer for helpful suggestions on an earlier version. In addition, we gratefully acknowledge helpful comments received from Johannes Rottmann and Hans-Bernd Schäfer.

Appendix

The Victim’s Consumption Choices in Regime (d)

With an income M { m + y ̄ , m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) } and a price for quality q ∈ {1, 1 + t}, the possible interior solutions for the optimal consumer choice are given by

x = M 2 p ( 1 + t ) y = M 2 q .

For M = m + y ̄ and q = 1 the choice is consistent for y < y ̄ . For M = m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) and q = 1 + t the interior solution requires y > y ̄ . This yields

y ( d ) = m + y ̄ 2 if m [ m L , y ̄ )

and

y ( d ) = m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) 2 ( 1 + t ) if m [ y ̄ ( 1 + t ) , m H ) .

In the intermediate range, m [ y ̄ , y ̄ ( 1 + t ) ] , the victim is better off from sticking to the budget line’s kink at y = y ̄ . The levels y ( d ) = ( m + y ̄ ) / 2 and y ( d ) = ( m + y ̄ ( 1 + t ) ) / ( 2 ( 1 + t ) ) are equal to the level y ̄ exactly at m = y ̄ and m = y ̄ ( 1 + t ) , respectively.

Social Harm in Regime (d) for m L m < y ̄

For this constellation, we have

R y ̄ R ( d ) + D ( d ) 1 + t = 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m + y ̄ 1 + t + y ̄ + t m + y ̄ 2 1 + t = 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t + m + y ̄ 1 + t 1 + t 2 1 + t = 2 m y ̄ 1 + t m 1 + t + m + y ̄ 2 2 + t 2 1 + t 1 + t .

Note that 2 + t 2 1 + t > 0 for t > 0 due to 2 + t > 2 1 + t 4 + 4 t + t 2 > 4 + 4 t .

References

Achatz, M. 2004. “Anhang zu §1323.” In ABGB – Kommentar, edited by P. Rummel. Wien: Manz.Search in Google Scholar

Baumann, F., and T. Friehe. 2009. “On the Superiority of Damage Averaging in the Case of Strict Liability.” International Review of Law and Economics 29: 138–42. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.irle.2008.10.001.Search in Google Scholar

Baumann, F., and T. Friehe. 2015. “Optimal Damages Multipliers in Oligopolistic Markets.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 171: 622–40. https://doi.org/10.1628/093245615x14303814418323.Search in Google Scholar

Bishop, W. 1982. “Economic Loss in Tort.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 2: 1–29. https://doi.org/10.1093/ojls/2.1.1.Search in Google Scholar

Cooter, R. 1991. “Economic Theories of Legal Liability.” The Journal of Economic Perspectives 5: 11–30. https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.5.3.11.Search in Google Scholar

Dari-Mattiacci, G., and H.-B. Schäfer. 2007. “The Core of Pure Economic Loss.” International Review of Law and Economics 27: 8–28. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.irle.2007.04.002.Search in Google Scholar

Dodge, J. M. 1992. “Taxes and Tort.” Cornell Law Review 77: 143–88.Search in Google Scholar

Friehe, T., and A. Tabbach. 2014. “Judgment Proofness and the Choice Between Monetary and Nonmonetary Care.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 170: 249–74. https://doi.org/10.1628/093245614x13783876326544.Search in Google Scholar

Kaplow, L., and S. Shavell. 1996. “Accuracy in the Assessment of Damages.” The Journal of Law and Economics 39: 191–210. https://doi.org/10.1086/467347.Search in Google Scholar

Mas-Colell, A., M. D. Whinston, and J. R. Green. 1995. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Miceli, T. J., and K. Segerson. 2003. “A Note on Optimal Care by Wealth-Constrained Injurers.” International Review of Law and Economics 23: 273–84. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.irle.2003.09.004.Search in Google Scholar

Nussim, J., and A. Tabbach. 2009. “Deterrence and Tax Treatment of Monetary Sanctions and Litigation Costs.” International Review of Law and Economics 29: 1–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.irle.2008.01.001.Search in Google Scholar

Polinsky, A. M., and D. L. Rubinfeld. 1988. “The Welfare Implications of Costly Litigation for the Level of Liability.” Journal of Legal Studies 17: 151–64. https://doi.org/10.1086/468125.Search in Google Scholar

Schäfer, H. B., and C. Ott. 2022. The Economic Analysis of Civil Law. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.10.4337/9780857935076.00006Search in Google Scholar

Shavell, S. 1987. The Economic Analysis of Accident Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.4159/9780674043510Search in Google Scholar

Shavell, S. 2007. “Liability for Accidents.” In Handbook of Law & Economics, Vol. 1, edited by A. M. Polisnky, and S. Shavell. North-Holland: Elsevier.10.1057/978-1-349-95121-5_2248-1Search in Google Scholar

Visscher, L. T. 2009. “Tort Damages.” In Tort Law and Economics. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. 2nd ed. Vol. 1, edited by M. G. Faure, 153–200. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2023-07-06
Accepted: 2023-10-01
Published Online: 2023-11-22

© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 23.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/rle-2023-0060/html
Scroll to top button