Abstract
In this paper I focus on the relationships between language, definition and being in Antisthenes. I start from Plato’s Sophist 251b–c, in which the reference to the ὀψιμαθεῖς stands out, and I conclude that it is not possible to identify these characters with Antisthenes. The conception of ὀψιμαθεῖς provides for the exclusive legitimacy of identical judgments, exploiting in an eristic sense an evident Eleatic legacy. But this position, rather than concordances, reveals serious opposition to what is surely known to us of the logical and linguistic doctrines of Antisthenes. The most explicit testimony about the relationship between language and being in Antisthenes is handed down by Porphyry, who attributes to Antisthenes the equation λέγειν = λέγειν τι = λέγειν τὸ ὄν. My analysis intends to show that this equation is assumed by Antisthenes through a Socratic mediation and has a double objective: to ensure an objective reference of language, as opposed to Gorgias’ self-referential conception of language, and to nullify the antilogy, which is typical of sophistic argumentation. To it Antisthenes contrasts the ἐπίσκεψις τῶν ὀνομάτων, which is a development of Socratic ἐξετάζειν, and whose aim is to reach, at the end of the examination, no longer just a ὁμολογία, but a definition valid once and for all. Antisthenes is aware that there is a distinction between essence and quality, and with this, he moves a first important step beyond the univocal conception of being proper to Parmenides. The doxography will sum up Antisthenes’ position by describing him as the first philosopher to advance a definition of logos, i. e., definition. He bases his theory of definition on the identification of that attribute which is ἴδιον καὶ οἰκεῖον of the proposed object. Antisthenes coined the phrase τὸ τί ἦν to designate what the predicate is meant to say in a definition, i. e., the proper quality. This expression does not seem to identify the general notion of a predicate as such, but rather to indicate the determination or qualification necessary to actually define the object in question. In the final part of my article, I examine some testimonies that show how, with his theory of definition, Antisthenes is, and was considered already in antiquity, the precursor of the Stoic theory of definition, whose objective is, according to Chrysippus’ formula, to provide the explanation of what is proper (ἰδίου ἀπόδοσις).
References
Allen, R. E. (1983): Plato’s Parmenides, Translation and Analyses. Oxford: Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar
Aubenque, Pierre (1962): Le problème de l’être chez Aristote. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.Search in Google Scholar
Aubenque, Pierre (1987): “Syntaxe et sémantique de l’être dans le Poème de Parménide”. In: Pierre Aubenque (ed.): Etudes sur Parmenide, Vol. II: Problèmes d’interprétations. Paris: Vrin, pp. 102–34.Search in Google Scholar
Barnes, Jonathan ed. (1995): The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Belardi, Walter (1975): Il linguaggio nella filosofia di Aristotele. Rome: K Libreria Editrice.Search in Google Scholar
Benson, Hugh H. (2002): “Problems with Socratic Method”. In: Gary Alan Scott (ed.): Does Socrates have a Method? Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 101–13.10.5325/j.ctv14gpdz4.11Search in Google Scholar
Benson, Hugh H. (2013), “The Priority of Definition”. In: John Bussanich and Nicholas D. Smith (eds.): The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates. London and New York: Bloomsbury Academic, pp. 136–55.Search in Google Scholar
Bluck, R. S. (1961): Plato’s Meno edited with Introduction and Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Brancacci, Aldo (1990): La filosofia del linguaggio di Antistene. Naples: Bibliopolis.Search in Google Scholar
Brancacci, Aldo (2005): “Antisthène et les Stoïciens: la logique”. In: Gilbert Romeyer Dherbey and Jean-Baptiste Gourinat (eds.): La Stoïciens. Paris: Vrin, pp. 55–73.Search in Google Scholar
Brancacci, Aldo (2018): “Socratism and Eleaticism in Euclides of Megara’. In: Alessandro Stavru and Christopher Moore (eds.): Socrates and the Socratic Dialogue. Leiden-Boston: Brill, pp. 161–178.10.1163/9789004341227_009Search in Google Scholar
Brunschwig, Jacques (1988): “La théorie stoïcienne du genre suprème”. In: Jonathan Barnes and Mario Mignucci (eds.): Matter and Metaphysique. Fourth Symposium Hellenisticum. Naples: Bibliopolis, pp. 19–127.Search in Google Scholar
Caizzi, Fernanda (1964): “Antistene”, Studi Urbinati 38, pp. 48–99.Search in Google Scholar
Calogero, Guido (1932): Studi sull’eleatismo. Roma: Tipografia del Senato; (1977): Studi sull’eleatismo. Nuova edizione arricchita di due Appendici. Florence: La Nuova Italia.Search in Google Scholar
Calogero Guido (1967): Storia della logica antica. Volume primo: L’età arcaica. Bari: Laterza.Search in Google Scholar
Calogero, Guido (2019): Le ragioni di Socrate. Introduzione e cura di Aldo Brancacci. Milan-Udine: Mimesis.Search in Google Scholar
Canto, Monique (19932): Platon. Ménon. Traduction inédite, introduction et notes. Paris: GF-Flammarion.Search in Google Scholar
Cassin, Barbara (1980): Si Parménide, Le traité anonyme De Melisso Xenophane Gorgia. Édition critique et commentaire. Lille: Presses Universitaires.Search in Google Scholar
Charles, David (1994): “Aristotle on Names and Their Signification”. In: Stephen Everson (ed.): Language. Companions to Ancient Thought 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 37–73.Search in Google Scholar
Charles, David (2010): “Definition and Explanation in the Posterior Analytics and Metaphysics”. In: Charles (2010a), pp. 286–385.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199564453.003.0009Search in Google Scholar
Charles, David, ed. (2010a): Definition in Greek Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Chiba, Kei (2010): “Aristotle on Essence and Defining-Phrase in his Dialectic”. In: Charles (2010a), pp. 203–51.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199564453.003.0007Search in Google Scholar
Consigny, Scott (2001): Gorgias. Sophist and Artist. Columbia, S.C.: University of South Carolina Press.Search in Google Scholar
Cornford, Francis M. (1935): Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. The ‘Theaetetus’ and the ‘Sophist’ of Plato translated with a Running Commentary. London: Kegan Paul.Search in Google Scholar
Crivelli, Paolo (2007): “The Stoics on Definitions and Universals”, Documenti e Studi sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 18, pp. 89–122.Search in Google Scholar
Crivelli, Paolo (2010): “The Stoics on Definitions”. In: Charles (2010a), pp. 359–423.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199564453.003.0011Search in Google Scholar
Deslauriers, Marguerite (2007): Aristotle on Definition. Leiden-Boston: Brill.10.1163/ej.9789004156692.i-230Search in Google Scholar
Dixsaut, Monique (2002): “Platon et la leçon de Gorgias: pouvoir tout dire de l’être, ne rien pouvoir dire de ce qui est”. In: Monique Dixsaut and Aldo Brancacci (eds.): Platon, Source des Présocratiques. Exploration. Paris: Vrin, pp. 191–217.Search in Google Scholar
Döring, Klaus (1972): Die Megariker: kommentierte Sammlung der Testimonien. Amsterdam: Grüner.Search in Google Scholar
Dümmler, Ferdinand (1882): Antisthenica. Dissertatio inauguralis Bonnensis. Berlin: Typis Hendeliis.Search in Google Scholar
Dümmler, Ferdinand (1889): Akademica: Beiträge zur Literaturgeschichte der Sokratischen Schulen. Giessen: J. Rickersche Buchhandlung.Search in Google Scholar
Fronterotta, Francesco (2001): Methexis. La teoria platonica delle idee e la partecipazione delle cose empiriche. Pisa: Scuola Normale Superiore.Search in Google Scholar
Giannantoni, Gabriele (1990): Socratis et Socraticorum reliquiae. Collegit, disposuit, apparatibus notisque instruxit. 4 Vols. Napoli: Bibliopolis.Search in Google Scholar
Giannantoni, Gabriele (2005): Dialogo socratico e nascita della dialettica nella filosofia di Platone. Edizione postuma a cura di Bruno Centrone. Napoli: Bibliopolis.Search in Google Scholar
Heitsch, Ernst (2004): Platon. Apologie des Sokrates. Übersetzung und Kommentar. 2., durchgesehene Auflage. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Search in Google Scholar
Höistad, Ragnar (1948): Cynic Hero and Cynic King. Studies in the Cynic Conception of Man. Uppsala: Bloms.Search in Google Scholar
Jöel, Karl (1893): Der echte und der Xenophontische Sokrates. Erster Band. Berlin: R. Gaertners Verlagsbuchhandlung.Search in Google Scholar
Kahn, Charles (1966): “The Greek Verb ‘To Be’ and the Concept of Being”, Foundations of Language 2, pp. 245–55.Search in Google Scholar
Kahn, Charles (2005): Plato and the Socratic Dialogue. The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Kneale, William Calvert and Kneale, Martha (1972). The Development of Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1962. Italian Translation: Storia della logica. 1972. Torino: Einaudi.Search in Google Scholar
Kraus, Manfred (1987). Name und Sache. Ein Problem im frürgriechischen Denken. Amsterdam: Grüner.Search in Google Scholar
Le Blond, Jean-Marie (1975): “Aristotle on Definition”, in Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield, and Richard R.K. Sorabji (eds.), Articles on Aristotle (Volume 1: Science), London: Duckworth, pp. 63–79.Search in Google Scholar
Levi, Adolfo (1932): “Le dottrine filosofiche della scuola di Megara”, Rendiconti della r. Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei. Classe di scienze morali, storiche e filologiche (6a Serie) 8, pp. 463–99.Search in Google Scholar
Lévystone, David (2005): “La figure d’Ulysse chez les Socratiques: Socrate polutropos”, Phronesis 50, pp. 181–214.10.1163/1568528054740168Search in Google Scholar
Long, Anthony and Sedley, David (1987–1988): The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139165907Search in Google Scholar
Lo Piparo, Franco (2003): Aristotele e il linguaggio. Cosa fa di una lingua una lingua. Bari: Laterza.Search in Google Scholar
Meijer, P. A (2017): A New Perspective on Antisthenes. Logos, Predicate and Ethics in his Philosophy. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.10.1017/9789048532957Search in Google Scholar
Modrak, Deborah (2003): Aristotle’s Theory of Language and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Modrak, Deborah (2019): “Nominal Definition in Aristotle”. In: Charles (2010a), pp. 252–279.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199564453.003.0008Search in Google Scholar
Montiglio, Silvia (2011): From Vilain to Hero: Odysseus in Ancient Thought. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.10.3998/mpub.2802465Search in Google Scholar
Montoneri, Luciano (1984): I Megarici. Studio storico-critico e traduzione delle testimonianze antiche. Catania: Tipografia Grafica del Libro.Search in Google Scholar
Morpurgo-Tagliabue, Guido (1967): Linguistica e stilistica di Aristotele. Roma: Edizioni dell’Ateneo.Search in Google Scholar
Mourelatos, Alexander D.P. (1973), “Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the Naïve Metaphysics of Things”. In: Gregory Vlastos, Edward N. Lee, Alexander D.P. Mourelatos & Richard Rorty (eds.): Exegesis and Argument. Studies in Greek Philosophy presented to Gregory Vlastos (Phronesis Suppl. Vol.). Assen: Van Gorcum, pp. 16–48.Search in Google Scholar
Mourelatos, Alexander D.P. (1987): “Gorgias on the Function of Language”, Philosophical Topics 15, pp. 135–70.10.5840/philtopics19871527Search in Google Scholar
Muller, Robert (1985): Les Mégariques. Fragments et témoignages. Paris: Vrin.Search in Google Scholar
Natorp, Paul (1903): Platos Ideenlehre. Eine Einführung in den Idealismus. Leipzig: Dürr.Search in Google Scholar
Patzer, Andreas (1970): Antisthenes der Sokratiker: Das literarische Werk und die Philosophie, dargestellt am Katalog der Schriften. Inaugural-Dissertation der Ruprecht-Karl-Universität zu Heidelberg.Search in Google Scholar
Prince, Susan (2015): Antisthenes of Athens. Text, Translations and Commentary. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.10.3998/mpub.5730060Search in Google Scholar
Ramnoux, Clémence (1959) : Héraclite ou l’homme entre les choses et les mots. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Search in Google Scholar
Romeyer-Dherbey, Gilbert (1996): “Entre Ajax et Ulysse, Antisthène”. Elenchos 17, pp. 251–74.Search in Google Scholar
Sainati, Vittorio (1968): Storia dell’Organon aristotelico. Florence: Le Monnier.Search in Google Scholar
Sedley, David (1982): “The Stoic criterion of identity”, Phronesis 27, pp. 255–75.10.1163/156852882X00177Search in Google Scholar
Sedley, David (1985): “The Stoic theory of universals”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 23, Supplement, pp. 87–92.10.1111/j.2041-6962.1985.tb00428.xSearch in Google Scholar
Suvák, Vladislav (2017): “On the Dialectical Character of Antisthenes’ Speeches Ajax and Odysseus”. In: Alessandro Stavru and Christopher Moore (eds.): Socrates and the Socratic Dialogue, pp. 141–60.10.1163/9789004341227_008Search in Google Scholar
Tarrant, Harold (2002): “Elenchos and Exetasis: Capturing the Purpose of Socratic Interrogation”. In: Gary Alan Scott (ed.): Does Socrates have a Method? Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 61–77.10.5325/j.ctv14gpdz4.8Search in Google Scholar
Vogt, Katja Maria (forthcoming): Stoic Definitions Without Forms. In: Peter Anstey, David Bronstein (eds.): Definitions and Essences from Aristotle to Kant (forthcoming).Search in Google Scholar
Whitaker, C. W. A. (1996): Aristotle’s De interpretatione. Contradiction and Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Search in Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, David (2013: “Socratic Philosophizing”. In: John Bussanich and Nicholas D. Smith (eds.): The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates. London and New York: Bloomsbury Academic, pp. 34–67.Search in Google Scholar
Zeller, Eduard (1886): “Über die zeitgeschichtlichen Beziehungen des platonischen Theätet”, Sitzungsberichte der kgl. Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin 2, 1886, pp. 631–647.Search in Google Scholar
Zeller, Eduard (1887): “Über die Unterscheidung einer doppelten Gestalt der Ideenlehre in den platonischen Schriften”, Sitzungsberichte der kgl. Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin 3, 1887, pp. 369–97.Search in Google Scholar
Zeller, Eduard (1892): “Plato’s Mittheilungen über frühere und gleichzeitige Philosophen”, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 5, 1892, pp. 165–84.10.1515/agph.1892.5.2.165Search in Google Scholar
Zeller, Eduard (1920): Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung. II 1: Sokrates und die Sokratiker. Plato und die alte Akademie. Obraldruck der 6. Auflage, mit einem Anhang von E. Hoffmann. Leipzig: O. R. Reisland.Search in Google Scholar
© 2023 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston
Articles in the same Issue
- Titelseiten
- Preliminary Note
- Articles
- The Verb εἰμί and Its Benefits for Parmenides’ Philosophy
- Protagoras on Being: Between ὀρθοέπεια and the Eleatic Legacy
- Gorgias and Plato’s Sophist
- Language, Definition and Being in Antisthenes
- Complete versus Incomplete εἶναι in the Sophist: An unhelpful dilemma
- Senses of Being in Plato’s Timaeus
Articles in the same Issue
- Titelseiten
- Preliminary Note
- Articles
- The Verb εἰμί and Its Benefits for Parmenides’ Philosophy
- Protagoras on Being: Between ὀρθοέπεια and the Eleatic Legacy
- Gorgias and Plato’s Sophist
- Language, Definition and Being in Antisthenes
- Complete versus Incomplete εἶναι in the Sophist: An unhelpful dilemma
- Senses of Being in Plato’s Timaeus