Startseite Why is the Cosmos Intelligent? (1)
Artikel
Lizenziert
Nicht lizenziert Erfordert eine Authentifizierung

Why is the Cosmos Intelligent? (1)

Stoic cosmology and Plato, Philebus 29a9–30a8
  • Ricardo Salles EMAIL logo
Veröffentlicht/Copyright: 4. August 2018
Veröffentlichen auch Sie bei De Gruyter Brill
Rhizomata
Aus der Zeitschrift Rhizomata Band 6 Heft 1

Abstract

The present paper studies a family of Stoic proofs of the intelligence of the cosmos, i. e. of the thesis that the cosmos is intelligent in the strong sense that it is, as a whole, something that thinks. This family, ‘F2’, goes back to a proof, ‘XP’, found in Philebus 29a9–30 a8 and Xenophon Mem. 1.4.8. F2 infers the intelligence of the cosmos, as XP does, from (i) the general idea that our intelligence proceeds from the cosmos, which is the ultimate cause of why we are intelligent, and (ii) the further claim that, since this is so, the cosmos itself must be intelligent. They differ from one another, however, in how they account for (i). In this paper, I present a new reason for why the accounts are different, that complements those given by David Sedley in a recent and important study of Stoic cosmology (Sedley 2007). Based on the analogy between intelligence and the four elements, XP puts forward the idea that the intelligence currently present in us is a portion of cosmic intelligence that has separated from it at some point in the past, and that has travelled from the outside cosmos to us. In contrast, the theory used by F2 to explain the generation of human intelligence is grounded not in the notions of separation and locomotion, but in that of transmission of a state. As I argue in some detail, the separation-locomotion model and the transmission model are not only different from each other, but also logically independent from one another: in general terms, neither entails the other. This transmission model used by the Stoics in a proof of the intelligence of the cosmos, I submit, is a major innovation in ancient cosmological and metaphysical thinking.

References

Bandini, Marco and Dorion, Louise-André (2003): Xénophon. Mémorables. Introduction Générale. Livre I. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Suche in Google Scholar

Bandini, Marco and Dorion, Louise-André (2011): Xénophon. Mémorables. Livre IV. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Suche in Google Scholar

Bett, Richard (2012): Sextus Empiricus. Against the Physicists. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/9781139048811.007Suche in Google Scholar

Broadie, Sarah (2012): Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9780511997815Suche in Google Scholar

Carone, Gabriela R. (2005): Plato’s Cosmology and Its Ethical Dimensions. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9780511734915.002Suche in Google Scholar

Cooper, John (1986): Reason and Human Good in Aristotle. Indianapolis: Hackett.Suche in Google Scholar

Cornford, Francis M. (1935): Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.10.4324/9781315822884Suche in Google Scholar

Cornford, Francis M. (1937): Plato’s Cosmology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul10.4324/9781315822938Suche in Google Scholar

Frede, Dorothea (1993): Plato. Philebus. Indianapolis: Hackett.Suche in Google Scholar

Frede, Dorothea (1997): Platon. Philebos. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Suche in Google Scholar

Furley, David J. (1987): The Greek Cosmologists. Vol. 1: The Formation of the Atomic Theory and its Earliest Critics. Cambridge: CUP.10.1017/CBO9780511552540Suche in Google Scholar

Furley, David J. (1989): Cosmic problems: Essays on Greek and Roman Philosophy of Nature. Cambridge: CUP.Suche in Google Scholar

Gill, Christopher (2013): Marcus Aurelius. Meditations Books 1–6. Oxford: OUP.Suche in Google Scholar

Gourinat, Jean-Baptiste (2016): “La gestation de l’animal et la perception de soi”. In: Gourinat, Jean-Baptiste (ed.), L’Éthique de Stoïcien Hiéroclès. Villeneuve d’Ascq: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion, pp. 15–46.10.4000/books.septentrion.88646Suche in Google Scholar

Laks, André (1983): Diogène d’Apollonie: La Dernière Cosmologie Présocratique. Lille: Presses Universitaires de Septentrion (2nd ed. 2008 in Academia Verlag).Suche in Google Scholar

Lloyd, Anthony C. (1976): ‘The Principle that the Cause is Greater than its Effect’, Phronesis 21, pp. 146–156.10.1163/156852876X00101Suche in Google Scholar

Long, Anthony A. (1982): “Soul and Body in Stoicism”, Phronesis 27, pp. 34–57.10.1163/156852882X00032Suche in Google Scholar

Long, Anthony A. (2003): “Stoicism in the Philosophical Tradition: Spinoza, Lipsius, Butler”. In: Miller, Jon and Inwood, Brad (eds.), Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge: CUP, pp. 7–29.10.1017/CBO9780511498275.004Suche in Google Scholar

Makin, Stephen (1991): “An Ancient Principle about Causation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, NS vol. 91, pp. 135–152.10.1093/aristotelian/91.1.135Suche in Google Scholar

Meijer, P. A. (2007): Stoic theology. Proofs for the existence of the cosmic god and of the traditional gods including a commentary on Cleanthes’ Hymn on Zeus. Delft: Eburon.Suche in Google Scholar

Menn, Stephen (1999): “The Stoic theory of categories”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 17, pp. 215–247.Suche in Google Scholar

Powers, Nathan (2012): “The Stoic argument for the rationality of the cosmos”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43, pp. 245–269.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199666164.003.0009Suche in Google Scholar

Reydams-Schils, Gretchen (2006): “The Roman Stoics on Divine Thinking and Human Knowledge”. In: Gersh, Stephen and Moran, Dermot (eds.), Eriugena, Berkeley, and the Idealist Tradition. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 81–94.Suche in Google Scholar

Salles, Ricardo (2009): “Chrysippus on conflagration and the indestructibility of the cosmos”. In R. Salles (ed.), God and Cosmos in Stoicism. Oxford: OUP, pp. 118–34.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199556144.003.0006Suche in Google Scholar

Salles, Ricardo (2013): “La razón cósmica en el estoicismo y sus raíces platónicas”, Anuario Filosófico 46.1, pp. 49–77.10.15581/009.46.1008Suche in Google Scholar

Salles, Ricardo (2017): “Soul as harmony in Phaedo 85e-86d and Stoic pneumatic theory”. In: Harte, Verity and Woolf, Raphael (eds.), Rereading Ancient Philosophy: Old Chestnuts and Sacred Cows. Cambridge: CUP, pp. 221–239.10.1017/9781108163866.014Suche in Google Scholar

Sambursky, Samuel (1959): Physics of the Stoics. Westport: Greenwood Press.10.1515/9781400859009Suche in Google Scholar

Schofield, Malcolm (1983): “The Syllogisms of Zeno of Citium”, Phronesis 28, pp. 31–58.10.1163/156852883X00031Suche in Google Scholar

Sedley, David (2005): “Les origines des preuves stoïciennes de l’existence de dieu”, Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, issue 4 of 2005, pp. 461–487.10.3917/rmm.054.0461Suche in Google Scholar

Sedley, David N. (2007): Creationism and Its Critics. Berkeley, CA: UCP.10.1525/9780520934368Suche in Google Scholar

Sedley, David N. (2009): “Three kinds of Platonic immortality”. In: Frede, Dorothea and Reis, Burkhard (eds.), Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 145–62.10.1515/9783110216523.2.145Suche in Google Scholar

Sedley, David (2012): “Marcus Aurelius on Physics”. In: van Ackeren, Marcel (ed.), A Companion to Marcus Aurelius. Chichester-Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 396–407.10.1002/9781118219836.ch25Suche in Google Scholar

Theiler, Willy (1925): Zur Geschichte der teleologischen Naturbetrachtung bis auf Aristoteles. Zurich: O. Füssli.Suche in Google Scholar

Wilberding, James (2008): Porphyry. To Gaurus On How Embryos are Ensouled and On What is in Our Power. London: Bloomsbury.Suche in Google Scholar

Wilberding, James (2011): “Porphyry and Plotinus on the seed”, Phronesis 53, pp. 406–432.10.1163/156852808X338346Suche in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2018-08-04
Published in Print: 2018-08-02

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Heruntergeladen am 27.9.2025 von https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/rhiz-2018-0003/html
Button zum nach oben scrollen