Abstract
International institutions are facing increasing criticism of the legitimacy of their authority. But what does it mean for an international institution to be legitimate? Arthur Applbaum’s latest book provides a convincing new concept of legitimacy, namely, the power-liability view, and a new normative conception, the free group agent account. However, it is not clear how they can be applied to the international level. First, this paper examines how different concepts of legitimacy can be applied to international institutions. Second, it assesses three different conceptions of legitimacy, namely, the service conception, Applbaum’s free group agent account and the autonomy-based conception for the international level. It outlines how on the last conception, international institutions’ legitimacy depends on three different aspects required to protect autonomy: the political power of the institution; its purpose; and its relation to other institutions. Finally, the paper argues that the creation of an international institution should be seen as part of relational legitimacy and that state consent plays an important role to protect the political autonomy of peoples.
1 Introduction
International institutions are currently facing severe scrutiny of their legitimacy. Some commentators even argue that the liberal international order based on multilateralism is perhaps under greater pressure than ever before (Lake, Martin, and Risse 2021). These challenges to international institutions’ legitimacy have different sources, including nationalist and populist movements as well as non-Western states. Whether such critiques have merit is difficult to assess for at least two reasons: first, due to the vast differences in purposes and institutional structures of international institutions; and second, because it is often unclear what is meant by legitimacy beyond the state.
The core topic of legitimacy theories in political philosophy, political science, and jurisprudence has traditionally been the state (Hart 2012; Hobbes [1651] 1962; Kelsen [1960] 2017; Locke [1689] 2003; Rawls 1993; Raz 1986; Rousseau 2002; Weber 1964). Only recently has the issue of legitimacy of international institutions – that is, their legitimate authority or political power – gained traction (e.g. Adams, Scherz, and Schmelzle 2020; Besson 2014; Buchanan and Keohane 2006; Christiano 2012; Scherz 2021; Tasioulas 2010). Yet, there is also still disagreement over key conceptual questions around legitimacy. This is evident, for example, in Arthur Applbaum’s latest book Legitimacy: The Right to Rule in a Wanton World (2019), which presents a novel and convincing concept of legitimacy through a power-liability account that understands the right to rule as a normative power. It also outlines a free group agency account of legitimacy that describes the condition under which rule is legitimate. However, it is unclear whether Applbaum’s approach can be applied to international institutions and whether it is useful for determining appropriate legitimacy standards for them.
The aim of this paper is twofold: First, on the concept level, it shows that conceptualising legitimacy as a normative power is indeed useful for our understanding of the legitimacy of international institutions. The paper does so by first examining different concepts of legitimacy, amongst them Applbaum’s power-liability view. Second, regarding the normative content of legitimacy assessments, it seeks to provide clarity on how different normative legitimacy conceptions can determine legitimacy standards for international institutions. In this regard, it critically engages Raz’s service conception and Applbaum’s free group account. As an alternative to these, it proposes an autonomy-based conception of legitimacy. It argues that this conception relies on three fundamental aspects that need to be included to address the legitimacy of international institutions. These fundamental aspects of legitimacy are: the political power, the purpose, and the institutional relationships of the institution. The paper then illustrates how the creation of an international institution and in particular state consent as a standard for this creation bears on legitimacy assessments of international institutions. This paper contributes to the growing literature on the legitimacy of international institutions by showing how the power-liability concept can be applied to these institutions and what kind of questions arise in doing so. It also provides an autonomy-based conception that shares certain features of Applbaum’s free group agency account but that is better suited for the international realm.
2 The Concept of Legitimacy for International Institutions
How does the concept of legitimacy apply to international institutions?[1] For a long time, applying the concept of legitimacy to international institutions has been seen as a conceptual mistake. The links between legitimacy, coercion, and the absence of coercive means at the international level were the main reasons for this. Since it was assumed that a large degree of obedience results from the coercive power of the state, what needed to be justified was coercion. Yet, as Franck observes, in the international realm law is generally not backed by coercive means. Nevertheless, ‘some, indeed many, international rules of conduct are habitually obeyed by states’ (Franck 1990, 20). Thus, legitimacy can be defined as a normative quality that generates a pull towards compliance which is not motivated by the threat of coercion or short-term self-interest. In fact, this lack of coercive means makes international institutions an interesting and perhaps an even better case through which to study the relevance of legitimacy. On the sociological side of legitimacy, the lack of coercive means explains why international institutions are even more dependent on their perceived legitimacy than state institutions. The critique raised about the legitimacy of international institutions, however, concerns a deeper normative issue, namely, that they are committing a wrong, rather than that they fail to generate certain beliefs and compliance. What this wrong consists of, whether international institutions commit such a wrong, and how it can be alleviated needs to be clarified in order to address questions of normative legitimacy.
So, what needs to be legitimised? What is it specifically about the behaviour of international institutions that needs justification? Legitimacy has often been characterised as the ‘right to rule’. But what exactly does ‘rule’ entail? First, in many traditional accounts of legitimacy, the concept applies to coercion (e.g. Blake 2001; Locke [1689] 2003). The reason why institutions that wield political power need to meet standards of legitimacy is grounded in the fact that this power includes the coercive means to enforce their directives. Legitimacy is thus necessary to justify the prima facie wrong of coercion. Yet, despite the fact that international institutions do not generally exercise coercion, their influence and structures nonetheless face public and academic scrutiny.
The core of some criticisms against international institutions may be better grasped by the second concept of legitimacy as the ‘right to rule’ that applies to practical authority (Raz 1986, 21). Here, the question is whether compliance with an institution’s rules is normatively demanded, irrespective of whether it has the coercive power to enforce them. Authority can be understood as providing content-independent and exclusionary reasons for compliance (e.g. Raz 1986). A reason for an action is content-independent if it is not connected to the content of that action. If an authority commands a particular action, its ‘saying so’ is a content-independent reason for action; other such reasons are promises and requests (Raz 1986, 35ff.). Exclusionary or pre-emptive reasons are second-order reasons that exclude at least some of the first-order reasons against an action. An authoritative directive provides exclusionary reasons that are not added to the reasons for or against the required action but replace some of them (Raz 1986, 46). Specifically, rules and decisions are intended to serve as exclusionary reasons, which is why authority is crucial for political institutions that seek to set binding rules and make decisions for others. Another distinctive feature of legitimacy as it applies to authority is that the right to rule is taken to entail a corresponding duty to obey (e.g. Raz 1986; Tasioulas 2010).
Third, several authors have proposed that legitimacy should be understood in a Hohfeldian (1917) sense as a moral power (right) or, in other words, via a power-liability account instead of a claim right with a corresponding duty to obey. In this view, legitimate authority consists in justified moral power (e.g. Applbaum 2010; Christiano 2012; Enoch 2014; Reglitz 2015) that changes normative relationships of its subjects such as rights and duties. In this case, there is no corresponding duty owed to the government, but rather a liability to have these relationships changed. This power-liability account has recently been elaborated in detail by Applbaum (2019). In his view, this concept of legitimacy falls between the conception of legitimacy as the justified use of coercion and that of legitimate authority as generating a moral duty to obey. He argues that ‘legitimate authority is a moral power (which is more than mere permission) to create moral liabilities (but not necessarily moral duties)’ (Applbaum 2019, 44).
In contrast, Raz’s account of legitimate authority relies on content-independent exclusionary reasons that result in an obligation to obey. One problem is that this seems to overstate what the law can require of its subjects. Some have argued that legitimacy should rather be seen as weighty reasons for compliance and noninterference, not as an obligation (e.g. Buchanan 2010). It is important to clarify what Raz means by obligations: there are, in his view, categorical reasons for action that are protected by exclusionary reasons. This means that at least some of the competing reasons to act differently are excluded, yet others are not. Therefore, exclusionary reasons are not necessarily conclusive reasons. The worry that Buchanan, for example, has regarding this view, namely, that these demands are too stringent – it generates all-things-considered duties instead of pro tanto duties – cannot be supported by the conclusiveness of exclusionary reasons and obligations in turn. Rather, Raz’s account is attractive because it does not describe exclusionary reasons as weighty but as second-order reasons that protect the first-order reason from other competing reasons. This captures more closely how the law is intended to function.
However, the feature of exclusionary reasons themselves can be problematic. First, it is questionable whether the complete exclusion of valid reasons from our deliberation of what to do can be warranted (e.g. Perry 1989). In particular, if we understand citizens as makers not just as passive takers of the law, restricting them to such an uncritical attitude towards the law is problematic.[2] Second, it raises a serious question of which reasons are excluded. On Raz’s account, these are the reasons that the authority was meant to consider for its directive. It seems implausible that the law should cover all moral consideration. This would allow the account to be much more permissive in certain exceptional cases, as it would be responsive to conflicting moral reasons. For example, this would cover attenuating circumstances if someone stole food when they were starving. However, the account still has problems to explain why it is not a moral wrong to jaywalk in a deserted area or to overstay the time of a parking limit (Applbaum 2019, 58f.). In this case, the excluded reasons are not moral but exactly the kinds of reasons of convenience and ordinary preference that are meant to be excluded by the account. Finally, and most importantly, it provides an attribution of morality to fallible political institutions. While Raz argues that states do not have all the authority they claim to have, if states have authority, in this view, this translates into a moral obligation. The power-liability account provides a much more nuanced account of how to allocate morality in our relationship to the state and to others. The main argument that speaks for the power-liability view is the conceptual space it opens up between the political (including legal) and the moral. This allows for justified civil disobedience since it does not conceive of our legal obligations in a legitimate system as (fully) moral (Applbaum 2019, 46).
For Applbaum’s account it is important to specify what is meant by liability. Is it just that one is liable to be punished if one does not comply with legitimate rules? So is it just a positivist understanding of law, in the sense that legal obligations are not connected to morality? No. It is more than just a privilege to create and enforce institutional rules. The power-liability account holds that legitimate authority is the normative power to change normative relationships of those subject to it or, as Applbaum calls it, their moral status (2019, 52). The liability of the subjects means that they have ‘no moral immunity against the loss of legal rights and the subsequent detrimental exercise of privileges by others, or the imposition of legal duties and their enforcement, and this limits the sort of justified complaints the subject can make’ (Applbaum 2019, 49).
There are two important aspects of this that I would like to expand on: First, changing these institutional relationships is an exercise of power that needs to be justified even if it is not coercively enforced, because they affect the available opportunities of their subjects in nontrivial ways (Scherz 2021). In other words, institutional relationships affect moral rights and privileges (Applbaum 2019, 52). Second, legitimate authority, according to this account, creates an institutional obligation but not a moral obligation to obey. Applbaum describes them as not fully or not yet moral. But what does this mean for the appropriate up-take, that is, the behaviour that this demanded from the authority’s subjects? Can we think of political and legal obligations as something other than moral obligations without falling back into a positivist understanding? I take it that the political realm creates normative reasons which are distinct from general morality. If that is the case, the helpful idea of legitimate authority generating content-independence and exclusionary reasons can be upheld. This would mean that political institutions are in fact not supposed to consider all moral reasons. Therefore, political obligations are of normative importance and exclude some other reasons; however, they are not all-things-considered moral obligations but rather pro tanto obligations. To be clear, this is contrary to Raz’s understanding of the obligations that legitimate authority creates. Instead of seeing this as a flaw, it should be embraced as a more nuanced understanding of how we ought to respect political institutions and the rules they produce. First, for public authority to be able to provide their services, they need to be respected and have their rules followed, but not uncritically. Under this conception, citizens are able to question the fairness and justice of laws. Second, this allows for different degrees to which different laws need to be respected. While the pedigree of laws – in particular the respect for fellow citizens in a democracy – creates a general baseline for compliance and no right for complaint in case of punishment, the idea that different (but not all) reasons were meant to be considered by the lawmaker allows for differences in different legal areas. For example, the otherwise perplexing case of moral obligations not to jaywalk dissolves if we consider the underlying reasons for coordination and safety.
Now, which of these concepts of legitimacy is appropriate to assess the legitimacy of international institutions? For international institutions, it is clear that the focus on coercion cannot capture what is normatively problematic in the way they exercise power through rule setting and influencing the available options for their subjects. But does it make a difference whether we understand their legitimate authority as creating a corresponding obligation or a liability? In certain regards, the difference between the two concepts of legitimacy seems not so great: the moral power that is involved in Applbaum’s view is a general power to create and enforce a nonmoral normative order, in other words an entire legal system. This is very demanding – potentially as demanding as being bound by a moral duty to obey.
To assess whether the power-liability account is appropriate for the international level, we need to understand more clearly what it means to have a duty to the institutional system as a whole. First, and most importantly, this conception of legitimacy transforms our understanding of the normativity at stake here. It establishes the limits of political authority. There are moral reasons to respect the bindingness of a political and legal order, as it protects everyone’s freedom; however, the order itself is only legally binding if it is created in a politically legitimate process. Forst (2022) describes this as a principle of transformation that is essential for legitimacy. From a Kantian perspective, it is important to distinguish between this legal form of external laws and the internal moral grounds, so as not to over-moralise the function of laws and politics. The conceptual clarity of understanding legitimacy as a moral power involving the liability of those subjected to it to have their normative relationships changed, not a moral duty to obey, is also useful in the international realm.
Second, for the legitimacy of international institutions, this concept raises the difficult question of what the institutional system as a whole is. This seems much more unclear on the international level than on the domestic one. We tend to think of states as unified institutional structures, while international institutions, such as international law, or international organisations, such as the WTO or the ICC, seem to be much more connected and dependent on other institutions. Here, two issues come to the fore: first, vertically, even though one can delimit certain international organisations by reference to their founding treaties, their member states are an integral part necessary for their functioning, financing, and compliance with the organisation’s rules. Second, horizontally, international institutions and organisations also depend on other international institutions, in particular on international law, such as the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties. In this sense, the system that we are considering in the international sphere is more interconnected and its legitimacy is influenced by the legitimacy of the other parts. Buchanan (2011) has referred to the mutual dependence of member states’ and international institutions’ legitimacy as reciprocal legitimacy. I will call the broader phenomenon of legitimacy interdependency between member states, international institutions, and amongst international institutions themselves relational legitimacy and will return to this issue in Section 2.3.
Similarly, Adams (2023) proposes that we can distinguish different international institutions by ascribing a specific function or purpose to them by using a causal-role theory of functions. He argues that this requires situating them in a broader containing system. In Adams’ view, the state system is the containing system for both states and international institutions. In this sense, international institutions may not actually be so different from domestic ones. This means that we may not be able to separate international institutions strictly from others, but we can still distinguish them as functional systems (which are situated within and connected to others) and attribute a moral duty to these systems.
Beyond the conceptual question that defines what legitimacy is, the normatively more important question pertains to the criteria under which legitimate authority can actually be exercised. In the next section, I will analyse how different normative conceptions of legitimacy that define such criteria, fare on the international level.
3 Different Legitimacy Conceptions: Service, Free Group Agency, Autonomy-Based
International institutions vary widely in their aims and institutional setup. It is therefore not surprising that the allocation of legitimacy standards for international institutions often occurs in a rather unsystematic fashion. Frequently, legitimacy studies focus on a single specific international institution (e.g. Føllesdal and Hix 2006; Howse and Nicolaïdis 2003) or they are minimalist, proposing a baseline level of outputs, human rights, or transparency (e.g. Buchanan and Keohane 2006; Majone 2000; Ratner 2015). This stands in contrast with the legitimacy requirements for domestic institutions, since for states, democracy is generally presumed to be the gold standard (Brinkmann 2023).
Broadly speaking, we can distinguish between two different kinds of legitimacy standards, namely, procedural and substantive (e.g. Ceva and Calder 2009).[3] This distinction also largely overlaps with the well-known distinction of input and output legitimacy for the legitimacy of international institutions (Scharpf 1999). Yet, while some argue that only procedural-input or only substantive-output standards matter, many accounts propose hybrid standards (Brinkmann 2023). We see this in the debate about democratic theory (e.g. Christiano 2004) but also with regard to international institutions. For example, Elsig (2007) argues that the WTO should balance input and output measures. Buchanan and Keohane (2006) propose a complex legitimacy standard for global governance institutions that relies, on the one hand, on minimal moral standards (in particular human rights) and comparative benefits and, on the other hand, on accountability and transparency. However, it remains unclear why a certain institution, for example the WTO, should rely on specific output or input standards. To assign legitimacy standards systematically, not only a clear concept of legitimacy but also a specific normative conception of it is necessary. In the following, I will discuss three different conceptions of legitimacy: first, one of the most prominent conceptions, Raz’s service conception; second, Applbaum’s free group agent account; and third, what I call the autonomy-based conception. The aim is to outline the differences between these conceptions and to evaluate how they can be used on the international level.
3.1 Service Conception
Probably the best-known instrumental legitimacy conception, Raz’s service conception, has recently been characterised not as a purely substantive-output account but rather as a hybrid account that also factors in procedural values. The service conception relies on the so-called normal justification thesis (NJT), according to which a person or institution A has legitimate authority over a subject B if B would better comply with reasons that apply to them if they followed A’s directives than if they did not (Raz 2006, 1014; Raz 1986, 53–69). Generally, the consent of the governed and democratic rule are not essential criteria for legitimacy in this account. However, several authors have recently suggested that the service conception can and indeed should include procedural values as fundamental. For example, Christiano (2008, 252) and Viehoff (2011) argue that the NJT permits taking procedural fairness considerations into account, for example, treating others as equals in democratic procedures. Another important reason why Raz’s conception may include procedural values is the introduction of the independence condition. Raz argues that, in certain cases, it is better to decide for oneself rather than rely on conformity to reason (2006, 1014). This is a somewhat unhappy formulation because in these cases one conforms best to reason by deciding for oneself (Tasioulas 2010, 112n31). Now, one might wonder how this is connected to procedural considerations. It is because the independence condition may not only restrict legitimate authority but also make it dependent on procedures that ensure that individuals can decide themselves, such as consent.
On the international level, Tasioulas (2010), following the Razian account, discusses whether the respect for freedom that the independence condition seeks to protect also applies to self-determination of states under public international law. He argues that self-determination only has value insofar as it protects the interests of the communities’ members. Norms of state sovereignty in public international law can then be understood to protect states’ self-determination. Tasioulas argues, in my view correctly, that such norms are essential to protect the collective self-determination of peoples of other states, which requires a universally binding network of international norms. However, there may also be limits to the legitimate authority of such norms, for example, of international human rights, in matters that should be left to the free choice of states (see Tasioulas 2010, 113; Scherz 2022). This means that certain mechanisms may be necessary to accommodate self-determination in international public law. Tasioulas suggests state consent and democratic procedures for this purpose (2010, 114). This means, again, that the instrumental standards need to be supplemented with procedural ones.
Raz himself (2019) notes that political institutions may be valuable because their very existence creates values, such as democratic citizenship. Yet, supranational institutions seem to generate legitimacy purely on instrumental grounds. Raz further argues that there is a supranational dilemma: effective governance that provides services depends on the loyalty of those governed and their solidarity amongst each other, yet since supranational institutions are perceived as having only instrumental value and do not attract solidarity, even their instrumental success is undermined. So, what are the options for institutions in the international domain? First, Raz argues for the protection of value pluralism in order to ensure sensitivity to ‘the diversity of different cultures and to different legitimate ways of allocating opportunities and processing disputes’ (2019, 80). One way he proposes to enable this is, again, state consent to international agreements. Other methods he suggests include the more aggressive application of subsidiarity; fragmentation leading to checks and balances; and simultaneous interpretive pluralism, for example, the European Court of Human Rights’ margin of appreciation doctrine.
Now, how are we to evaluate this conception and the legitimacy standards it entails? There are two issues I want to highlight in respect of this account. First, if we understand the service conception as a purely instrumental account (which is probably not its best interpretation), there is a publicity issue. Procedural conceptions are public as they can be assessed relatively easily by subjects. In comparison, instrumental conceptions are a weaker basis for legitimate authority, as they are ‘based on the quality of outcomes which are exactly the subject of disagreement’ (Christiano 2012, 382). This is essential for the action-guiding function of legitimacy and the epistemic uncertainties in the political domain (e.g. Peter 2020; Scherz 2022). Second, however, if the service conception is best understood as a hybrid account, it seems difficult to see how the two should be combined, in particular, which one takes precedence when they come into conflict. Of course, this general objection can be raised for all kinds of hybrid accounts and there may be constructive ways to prioritise substantive and procedural considerations. However, the service conception does not provide guidance on how to do this. While the inclusion of the independence condition describes the conditions of when the NJT applies (or adds a different kind of reason, as discussed above), it is not clear that this tracks the substantive-procedural distinction. If it does track the distinction, there should be a procedure such as consent for cases in which it is more important that people decide for themselves and for the other cases covered by the NJT, namely, instrumental assessments. Yet, even then, it is not clear how we know whether it is better for individuals or states to decide for themselves rather than to follow the balance of reasons. Therefore, it is unclear which issues should, for example, be covered by state consent. If the independence condition does not track the substantive-procedural distinction, some of the reasons that the authority helps subjects comply with – for example equal respect for others – may require (or at least speak strongly in favour of) procedures such as democracy or consent, even for decisions that should strictly speaking follow the NJT. In conclusion, even though many are drawn to the service conception to evaluate the legitimacy of international institutions because it seems to provide a straightforward instrumental assessment, upon closer inspection this conception has problems in determining clear legitimacy standards.
3.2 Free Group Agent Account
Applbaum (2019) proposes a very different conception of legitimacy. His starting point is the puzzle of how a free moral agent can remain free when subjected to coercive governance. He formulates a substantive normative conception to answer this question (Applbaum 2019, 74). According to Applbaum’s free group agent account of political legitimacy, individuals are only free under the rule of a free group agent of which they are participating members. ‘A legitimately governs B only when A governs B in such a way that both A and B remain free moral agents over time. This is so only when A’s governance of B realises and protects B’s freedom over time, and this in turn is so only when A is a free group agent that counts a free B as a member’ (Applbaum 2019, 77). Here, the freedom of the individual and the freedom of the group are co-constituting.
To specify his free group agent account, Applbaum describes moral agents as agents that have three capacities, namely, considering (responsiveness to reasons for action), willing (capacity to choose), and doing (action guided by choice). A free agent must be sufficiently free in terms of both internal freedom as autonomy in the sense of self-governance, and external freedom as independence from the domination of others (Applbaum 2019, 78). A group agent then needs to be capable of unified action by possessing the three capacities to the required degree. This includes the capacity for second-order reflection and group action that then make the group subject to moral evaluations. Normative groups are ultimately bearers of respect and responsibility. Their normative status must, in Applbaum’s view, derive from the status of natural persons. Collective agents also have to be made up of sufficiently free natural agents. They also need to fulfil certain constitutive conditions as to how the collective agent is formed (meshed aims, representation or procedure) and conscriptive conditions as to why and how an authority comes to rule over its subjects (consent, fair play or practical necessity) (Applbaum 2019, 82–89). In conclusion, he subscribes to a conception with both substantive and procedural components. Instead of focusing on procedures alone and in particular ab ovo ideas of free founding moments, Applbaum locates legitimacy in ‘virtuous circles in which subjects are free enough to have the capacity to be authors of collective acts, procedures, and institutions that realise and protect the freedom that make them free enough to have the capacity to be authors’ (Applbaum 2019, 90).
While Applbaum’s account captures the necessity of ensuring the conditions of self-government and nondomination for individuals in terms of both human rights and political participation (2019, 90f.), it does not consider the necessary conditions under which the collective agents can relate to each other without domination. He acknowledges that group agents also need to be free from external domination and that not all normative groups – that is – peoples, are already free (2019, 80f.). Yet, in order to ensure the freedom of peoples that are organised in nondominating, representative states, they also need to enjoy freedom in relation to one another in a nondominating international order (e.g. Pettit 2010). However, Adom Getachew, for example, has raised the issue that both liberal (e.g. Rawls 1999) and republican (e.g. Pettit 2010) international political theory ignores the ‘interrelated character of domestic and international domination’ (2019, 35). To overcome this limitation, it is important to understand how to institutionalise the nondomination of peoples of so-called nonrepresentative states in international institutions (e.g. Gaedeke 2016). It is necessary to pay particular attention to contexts of multiple domination (Forst 2001) and to critically assess racial and other hierarchies that are structurally embedded in the international system (Lu 2017; 2018).
In Applbaum’s account, group agency alone is not enough. While a tyrannical regime may rule through group agency (as an agent of the regime itself), it does not personify the people (Applbaum 2010, 127). A society that fails to be a group agent cannot make any choices that deserve to be respected. Applbaum therefore argues that ‘setting a people free is a reason for coercion that meets the criteria of justified paternalism’, either because it is not a normative people or because it is a seriously impaired agent (Applbaum 2010, 128). On this basis, intervention can be justified, even though certain other conditions need to be fulfilled in addition. While I agree with Applbaum’s general idea that peoplehood is a normative concept, this account neglects that internal domination is often bound up with external domination both through historical – in particular in colonial contexts – and through ongoing international hierarchies. While Applbaum does, of course, not favour a dominating international order, neglecting the existence of these structures in his account can create the danger of reinforcing them. Permitting interventions to free those who are seen as peoples with seriously impaired agency and potentially also denying them representation in the international society reproduces exactly these dominating structures. If the means to resolve these domestic issues are themselves dominating as they reinforce dominating international structures or even permit intervention, they are not reducing domination but adding to it. In other words, two wrongs do not make a right (Ypi 2013, 185). Insisting on an ideal of personhood in such nonideal contexts is adding insult to (historic) injury. Instead, in contexts of multiple domination, the conceptual possibility of a potential people should be considered (Gaedeke 2016). These potential people are subjected to nonrepresentative political structures and their agency is diminished. Nevertheless, acknowledging this form of peoplehood maybe be what is normatively required.
3.3 Autonomy-Based Conception
Similar to the free group agent account, the autonomy-based conception relies on the personal autonomy of subjects and the political autonomy of the collective as the basis for legitimate authority. In other words, political institutions are legitimate if they protect personal autonomy, in particular through human rights protection, and political autonomy, as some form of equal participation (Scherz 2021). In my view, Appelbaum’s approach emphasises the substantive part in the hybrid conception. It seems clear that Applbaum proposes a hybrid account: ‘There needs to be an adequate connection between the governors and the governed (the procedural prong), and there needs to be adequate protection of at least basic human rights (the substantive prong). At a minimum, legitimacy requires the political freedom and basic protection that are constitutive of, or instrumentally necessary for, the individual moral agency of the members’ (Applbaum 2010, 91). The question then is whether he gives more weight to either one of these grounds of legitimacy. The fact that he calls his account a substantive account and that one of his book’s main aims is to make room for such an account seems to imply that he does. The substantive account that he proposes does challenges the exclusive reliance on procedural legitimacy criteria and argues specifically against pure procedural legitimacy (Applbaum 2010, 31ff.). Now, maybe his choice of label is just correcting an overreliance on procedural criteria in the legitimacy literature. If I am wrong about this emphasis in Applbaum’s account and we should rather understand his account as giving equal weight to both prongs, the general issue of hybrid accounts, namely, the problem of prioritising between substantive and procedural criteria in cases of conflict, arises.
In contrast to the free group agent account, the autonomy-based conception gives priority to political equality, that is, to the procedural basis. Tom Christiano argues for this priority on the basis of democracy’s public nature (Christiano 2004, 286). In his view, great intrinsic value is attached to being publicly treated as an equal. Public equality is congruent with other fundamental interests of persons, such as liberty, security, and material wellbeing, which are preconditions of being treated as an equal. Importantly, this focus on political autonomy also enables specifying these other substantial aspects in ways that are suitable for different societies. Since legitimacy judgements for political institutions must work precisely under circumstances of reasonable disagreement, political autonomy takes precedence over personal autonomy in the autonomy-based account proposed here. This focus can be understood as Kantian republican theory centring on justification and political autonomy (Forst 2013, 61).[4] However, there are still substantive limits, such as fundamental rights, to the procedural side, which are themselves grounded in the necessity of individuals to be autonomous decision-makers. One might argue that this is just a difference of emphasis rather than a different conception to Applbaum’s account. Yet the differences become more evident when we move to the international level.
Understanding the legitimacy of international institutions to be based on protecting the conditions of personal and political autonomy brings three central aspects to the fore that need to be considered to determine the specific legitimacy standards or criteria for an institution. In other words, the overarching principle is the justifiability of authority in terms of autonomy. The three aspects of legitimacy connect this general principle to the applicable standards used to evaluate the legitimacy of an institution in practice. These aspects are: first, the political power that the institution exercises; second, its purpose; and third, its institutional relationships. The capacity to affect autonomy explains the relevance of differences in power and the need for different standards. Different purposes lead to different ways in which this power is exercised, again causing different vulnerabilities for autonomy and the need for different standards. Finally, the relationship between different institutions can create checks and balances to protect autonomy if their interaction is constructive. However, it can also lead to risks for autonomy if they undermine, for example, accountability. These aspects of legitimacy are distinct but highly interrelated, as they specify how international institutions protect or create risks for personal and political autonomy. Let me expand on this.
First, depending on the political power an institution exercises, it has greater or lesser capacity to protect but also to endanger the autonomy of its subjects. Therefore, its institutional competences require corresponding graded standards for an institution’s legitimacy to reduce the risk that it poses to autonomy (Scherz 2021). Second, the purpose of an institution itself has to be minimally morally justifiable in order for the whole institution to be legitimate, I call this purposive legitimacy (see Adams 2020; Sangiovanni 2008; Scherz and Zysset 2020). The justifiability of the purpose should be determined in terms of autonomy, as outlined above. This includes minimal substantive criteria, but the purpose must also be publicly assessable and revisable through political autonomy-ensuring procedures. In addition, the purpose of an institution is essential to defining the required internal standards, such as independence for courts or accountability for legislative institutions.
Third, the relations of international institutions to other institutions, in particular states but also to other international institutions, influence their legitimacy. This is what I call relational legitimacy.[5] For example, international human rights courts may increase the legitimacy of states that have signed their respective conventions and conversely the legitimacy of the signatory states can influence the legitimacy of an international institution positively or negatively. For the autonomy-based conception, this is important for two reasons: First, these relationships matter vertically, that is, between states and international institutions. Both are required to establish nondomination between peoples in different states, and it also needs to be ensured that they themselves do not undermine the protection of personal and collective autonomy on the domestic level. In this regard, the creation of an international institution is also a part of its legitimacy requirements because certain ways of bringing an institution into existence contradict and therefore exclude the possibility to realise autonomy through them. Second, horizontally, the fragmentation of the international system means that different international institutions have different aims and functions. The relationship among these institutions matters as they can establish a division of labour that enables or protects autonomy, or their interactions can undermine accountability and hollow out existing protections. To conclude, when we judge an institution to be legitimate, this means: first, its political power – that is, competences and impact – is regulated by corresponding standards; second, it has a morally acceptable purpose; and third, it has appropriate relationships with other institutions, including states.
On the autonomy-based account, the legitimacy of international institutions depends on how they ensure or undermine the realisation of personal and political autonomy on the domestic level but also on the equal autonomy between peoples or, in other words, conditions of nondomination on the international level. So far, this may have been interpreted to mean that only peoples that would count as free group agents on Applbaum’s account should have their autonomy protected. Yet, given the structural issue of multiple domination discussed above, it would be detrimental to disregard what are not fully democratic states. Rather, a nonideal account of legitimacy on the international level is needed to not reproduce domination through international institutions. By and large, this means that the principle of equal sovereignty should guide legitimacy on the international level.
In the following, I will focus on the creation of international institutions as part of their legitimacy, as Applbaum explicitly distinguishes between legitimacy ab ovo versus in media res and does not see potential for the former. Applbaum concludes that no forms of legitimate foundings are possible and that, instead, legitimacy can only arise over time through the participation of a free enough people in political institutions (2010, 105). To be clear, I agree that, on the domestic level, we should not look for legitimacy in a founding moment or pedigree. I have argued similarly that here neither initial consent (Scherz 2013) nor necessity (Scherz 2022) can create legitimacy, but that it can only be realised over time. Internationally, however, there are already domestic institutions that are responsible for realising personal and political autonomy. Their normative value shapes a different backdrop against which we have to think about the legitimacy of international institutions.
4 Creation of International Institutions as a Legitimacy Concern
Applbaum argues in his free group agent account that all foundings are forced and that this is not an impediment to the legitimacy of a state; rather, in some cases it is necessary to force a people to be free (Applbaum 2010, 73ff.). Yet, the creation of an institution is part of its legitimacy, much in the way that it is relevant for justice. For example, the annexation of a state is generally a problem for its justice even if it produces distributive justice. For legitimacy, this is relevant as legitimacy judgements allow us to coordinate through institutions, which enable us to work towards justice (Buchanan 2008). If these institutions are created in a problematic way, this may undermine their ability to secure autonomy. Does this mean that forced foundings can never lead to legitimate institutions? No, under certain circumstances the injustice of the creation may be superseded (Meyer and Waligore 2022; Waldron 1992). However, against the background of an autonomy-based legitimacy theory, the question is whether the creation of an institution undermines the autonomy of those subjected to it. Institutions that have been created through oppression or domination, for example in the case of colonial states, can be thought to make autonomy as a form of self-determination impossible, as they lead to the alienation of (at least) certain groups (e.g. Stilz 2015). This means that such an origin makes an institution intrinsically opposed to the autonomy of its people(s). While it is possible that groups that were subjected to such historical injustice recognise the state as their own, thereby enabling their autonomy and gaining legitimacy over time, this history is still corrosive in many cases today (e.g. Lu 2017; Spinner-Halev 2007).
Legitimacy as a nonideal concept that allows working towards justice can nevertheless leave some room for relaxing the creation standards if the purpose of the institution is of high importance. Yet, an additional instrumental consideration needs to be made. Given that legitimacy is meant to provide action guidance of how to behave towards an institution, were legitimacy obtained even if an institution was created in a questionable way, this might lead to the creation of more institutions in that manner because they are expected to generate liability with their rules. In other words, assigning legitimacy to institutions with objectionable origins can lead to a moral hazard, which should, of course, be avoided. Therefore, some nonideal considerations might be allowed for, but if legitimacy is about protecting autonomy, these standards cannot be completely relaxed. In this sense, the adherence to at least negative standards, such as the prohibition of annexation, for the creation of institutions is a presumptive precondition for their general legitimacy.
So, what is the appropriate standard for the creation of international institutions? Kant already distinguished between the creation of a civil condition on the domestic level – that is, states – and the establishment of such a condition on the international level. For Kant, forcing others into the civil condition is famously justified because only in the civil condition can an omnilateral point of view be created and therefore justice be realised. So, forced foundings may be unavoidable in the case of individuals. However, the violent and oppressive past of colonialism is a stark warning against forcing others to be free in the case of peoples and what I have referred to as potential peoples. The analogy between individuals and states does not hold for Kant because ‘as states, they already have an internal legal constitution and have thus outgrown the coercions by which others subject them to a broader legal constitution according to others’ conception of right’ (Kant [1795] 2006, 80 (8:356)). While the interpretation of Kant’s position with regard to international politics is highly controversial (e.g. Kleingeld 2004), the disanalogy stated by Kant should give us reason to question under which circumstances it is permissible to force a state into an international institution. Therefore, with regard to the creation of international institutions, more stringent standards, such as state consent, should be required.
But what legitimacy standards are available for the creation of international institutions? Because we are addressing the creation of institutions, it is difficult to apply democratic standards, as this would require already existing procedures and therefore an institutional framework. A similar issue arises for instrumental service standards since it is difficult to reliably judge what kind of benefits an institution will create before it exists and for the publicity issue that has been discussed above. Under international law, international institutions are generally established through state consent. So, states are largely bound only by international institutions they have consented to. Yet, state consent has often been criticised as a normatively questionable standard that reinforces the power asymmetries in the international system and relies on regimes that are not accountable to their own citizens.
There are several normative issues concerning state consent and consent in general. First, consent in general can only be used in a situation in which a person is morally at liberty to give consent. With regard to directives of reasonably just states, this liberty seems to be highly restricted and can therefore not contribute much normatively to the legitimacy of the state’s authority. Second, consent is thought to create accountability of the power holder towards the consenter, which mainly serves the protection of autonomy. However, the consent of citizens or its absence does not seem to make any difference for the accountability of the state (Christiano 2012, 383–4). On the international level, consent and its withdrawal from states is, however, important for the functioning of international institutions. Third, only democratic states can be understood to consent on behalf of their citizens and to create content-independent reasons for them. However, this should not lead us to think that only the consent of democratic states is normatively relevant as, for reasons of self-determination, other considerations such as an established rule of law might be sufficient (Waldron 2006). The fact that an institution respects states equally by relying on their consent for its creation is a content-independent reason to comply with the rules of that institution, both for states that have consented (and their citizens) and other states. Fourth, the fairness of state consent is not given under the strong power and resource differences between states (Christiano 2012). Regarding autonomy and self-determination, the third and fourth considerations are particularly relevant and need to be balanced against each other.
Taking these considerations into account, under what conditions is state consent a normatively relevant standard for the formation of international institutions? Primarily, it is important to keep in mind that Kant’s discussion concerns the formation of a federation, either a state of states with coercive powers or a voluntary league. However, institutions with different purposes and less far-reaching competences might require less demanding creation standards. In particular, this applies to highly important or, as Christiano (2012) calls them, morally mandatory aims and restricted competences. This means that, under such circumstances, state consent is not a necessary requirement for the legitimacy of an international institution if it has morally mandatory aims, such as the restriction of global warming or the alleviation of global poverty. On this basis, Christiano argues that since there is uncertainty about how to achieve these aims, this speaks for a system of state consent because it allows for a significant amount of experimentation in how to solve the problems. However, ‘when a state refuses to participate in a cooperative venture for the pursuit of morally mandatory aims and has no adequate explanation, it may be subjected to some kind of sanction or coercion’ (Christiano 2012, 389). To conclude, for the creation of international institutions, unlike on the domestic level, (state) consent is an available procedural standard that can contribute to legitimacy. While the standard is problematic due to the highly unequal background conditions in the international system which may in parts not allow for genuine consent, it should still be seen as protecting political autonomy in the form of self-determination to a certain degree. Therefore, the standard may be overridden depending on the moral importance of an institution’s purpose. Nevertheless, there should be a presumption for state consent contributing to the legitimacy of international institutions.
5 Conclusions
This paper has argued that Applbaum’s power-liability account of legitimacy is conceptually clearer than the idea of legitimacy as justified coercion and the claim-right view. His account helps us understand the normative importance that the rules of a legitimate political order have and, at the same time, their distinctness from moral obligations to obey. I have argued that this concept also brings much needed clarity to the debate of normative legitimacy. Its application to the legitimacy of international institutions can also be useful to understand legitimacy issues beyond the state. For example, it brings to the fore a new dimension to the question of what the entire institution is to which we owe a moral duty, which is easily overlooked on the domestic level. I have suggested that there are different ways of drawing the boundaries of international institutions, but this question deserves more attention in future research.
In the second part of the paper, three different conceptions of legitimacy and their applicability to the international domain have been discussed: the service conception, Applbaum’s free group agent account and the autonomy-based conception. Interestingly, all three are hybrid accounts that combine substantive and procedural grounds for legitimacy. I have argued that the service conception does not provide a clear way of combining the two or prioritising between them. The free group agent account emphasises the substantive, while the autonomy-based conception emphasises the procedural ones. I contend that Applbaum’s free group agent account neglects the international dimension of freedom or autonomy between peoples and the potential risk of multiple domination. Attributing no normative value to peoples with “impaired” agency or even militarily intervening in unfree states to force them to be free does not overcome but rather introduces an additional source of domination. I have proposed an autonomy-based conception of legitimacy that prescribes the appropriate legitimacy standards of international institutions depending on their political power, their purpose, and their relations to other institutions. Therefore, we should adopt a multilevel understanding of legitimacy that is based on the protection of personal and political autonomy on the domestic level but does not require a full-blown democracy on the international level.
Funding source: Norges Forskningsråd
Award Identifier / Grant number: 325707
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the participants of the Workshop “Ruling in a Wanton World: Arthur Applbaum’s Work and the Philosophy of Legitimacy Beyond the State” University of Graz, 2022, where a draft version of this article was presented, the two anonymous reviewers of the journal and the editors of the special issue, Matthias Brinkmann and Anthony Taylor for their helpful and constructive comments.
The research was supported by the ENROL project (325707), funded by the Research Council of Norway.
-
Research funding: This work was supported by the Norges Forskningsråd (325707).
References
Adams, N. P. 2020. “Legitimacy and Institutional Purpose.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 23 (3): 292–310. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2019.1565712.Search in Google Scholar
Adams, N. P. 2023. “Legitimacy, Institutional Functions, and the State System.” In Conference Paper. Maynooth.Search in Google Scholar
Adams, N. P., Antoinette Scherz, and Cord Schmelzle. 2020. “Legitimacy beyond the State: Institutional Purposes and Contextual Constraints.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 23 (3): 281–91. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2019.1565710.Search in Google Scholar
Applbaum, Arthur Isak. 2010. “Legitimacy without the Duty to Obey.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 38 (3): 215–39. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2010.01186.x.Search in Google Scholar
Applbaum, Arthur Isak. 2019. Legitimacy: The Right to Rule in a Wanton World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.4159/9780674241923Search in Google Scholar
Besson, Samantha. 2014. “The Legitimate Authority of International Human Rights.” In The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes. Legal, Political and Philosophical Perspective, edited by Andreas Føllesdal, Johan Karlsson Schaffer and Geir Ulfstein, 32–83. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Blake, Michael. 2001. “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 30 (3): 257–96. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2001.00257.x.Search in Google Scholar
Brinkmann, Matthias. 2023. “The Asymmetry Between Domestic and Global Legitimacy.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2023.2216044.Search in Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2008. “Human Rights and the Legitimacy of the International Order.” Legal Theory 14 (01): 39–70. https://doi.org/10.1017/s1352325208080038.Search in Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2010. “Legitimacy of International Law.” In The Philosophy of International Law, edited by Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas, 79–96. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2011. “Reciprocal Legitimation: Reframing the Problem of International Legitimacy.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 10 (1): 5–19. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X09351958.Search in Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen, and Robert O. Keohane. 2006. “The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions.” Ethics and International Affairs 20 (4): 405–37. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-7093.2006.00043.x.Search in Google Scholar
Ceva, Emanuela, and Gideon Calder. 2009. “Values, Diversity and the Justification of EU Institutions.” Political Studies 57 (4): 828–45. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2009.00792.x.Search in Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2004. “The Authority of Democracy.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (3): 266–90. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x.Search in Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2008. The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198297475.003.0008Search in Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2012. “The Legitimacy of International Institutions.” In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law, edited by Andrei Marmor, 380–93. New York: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar
Duffield, John. 2007. “What Are International Institutions?” International Studies Review 9 (1): 1–22. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2486.2007.00643.x.Search in Google Scholar
Elsig, Manfred. 2007. “The World Trade Organization’s Legitimacy Crisis: What Does the Beast Look like?” Application/pdf. Journal of World Trade 41 (1): 75–98. https://doi.org/10.7892/BORIS.49426.Search in Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2014. “Authority and Reason-Giving1.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2): 296–332. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00610.x.Search in Google Scholar
Føllesdal, Andreas, and Simon Hix. 2006. “Why There Is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: A Response to Majone and Moravcsik.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 44 (3): 533–62. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5965.2006.00650.x.Search in Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2001. “Towards a Critical Theory of Transnational Justice.” Metaphilosophy 32 (1–2): 160–79. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9973.00180.Search in Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2013. “A Kantian Republican Conception of Justice as Nondomination.” In Republican Democracy: Liberty, Law and Politics: Liberty, Law and Politics, edited by Andreas Niederberger and Philipp Schink, 154–68. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.10.3366/edinburgh/9780748643066.003.0007Search in Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2022. Politische Legitimität, Rationalität Und Moral. WZB Workshop.Search in Google Scholar
Franck, Thomas M. 1990. The Power of Legitimacy among Nations, 1st ed. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780195061789.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Gaedeke, Dorothea. 2016. “The Domination of States: Towards an Inclusive Republican Law of Peoples.” Global Justice : Theory Practice Rhetoric 9 (1): 1–27. https://doi.org/10.21248/gjn.9.1.99.Search in Google Scholar
Getachew, Adom. 2019. Worldmaking after Empire: The Rise and Fall of Self-Determination. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691184340Search in Google Scholar
Hart, Herbert L.A. 2012. The Concept of Law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. [1651] 1962. Leviathan: or, the Matter, Forme and Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiasticall and Civi, 1st ed, edited by Michael Oakeshott. New York: Collier Books.Search in Google Scholar
Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb. 1917. “Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning.” The Yale Law Journal, Faculty Scholarship Series 26 (8): 710–70. https://doi.org/10.2307/786270.Search in Google Scholar
Howse, Robert, and Kalypso Nicolaïdis. 2003. “Enhancing WTO Legitimacy: Constitutionalization or Global Subsidiarity?” Governance 16 (1): 73–94. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0491.00205.Search in Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. [1795] 2006. “Toward Perpetual Peace.” In Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace, and History, edited by Pauline Kleingeld. New Haven: Yale University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. [1960] 2017. Reine Rechtslehre. Edited by Matthias Jestaedt. Studienausgabe der 2. Auflage 1960. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.10.33196/9783704683991Search in Google Scholar
Kleingeld, Pauline. 2004. “Approaching Perpetual Peace: Kant’s Defence of a League of States and His Ideal of a World Federation.” European Journal of Philosophy 12 (3): 304–25. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0966-8373.2004.00212.x.Search in Google Scholar
Lake, David A., Lisa L. Martin, and Thomas Risse. 2021. “Challenges to the Liberal Order: Reflections on International Organization.” International Organization 75 (2): 225–57, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818320000636.Search in Google Scholar
Locke, John. [1689] 2003. “Two Treatises of Government: And a Letter Concerning Toleration.” In Rethinking the Western Tradition, edited by Ian, Shapiro. London: Yale University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Lu, Catherine. 2017. Justice and Reconciliation in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781108329491Search in Google Scholar
Lu, Catherine. 2018. “Cosmopolitan Justice, Democracy, and the World State.” In Institutional Cosmopolitanism, edited by Luis Cabrera, 232–52. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780190905651.003.0010Search in Google Scholar
Majone, Giandomenico. 2000. “The Credibility Crisis of Community Regulation.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 38 (2): 273–302. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-5965.00220.Search in Google Scholar
Meyer, Lukas H., and Timothy Waligore. 2022. “Superseding Historical Injustice? New Critical Assessments.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 25 (3): 319–30. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2022.2039541.Search in Google Scholar
Owens, David. 2008. “Rationalism about Obligation.” European Journal of Philosophy 16 (3): 403–31. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2008.00327.x.Search in Google Scholar
Perry, Stephen R. 1989. “Second-Order Reasons, Uncertainty and Legal Theory Symposium: The Works of Joseph Raz.” Southern California Law Review 62 (3 & 4): 913–94.Search in Google Scholar
Peter, Fabienne. 2020. “The Grounds of Political Legitimacy.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 6 (3): 372–90. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2020.6.Search in Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2010. “A Republican Law of Peoples.” European Journal of Political Theory 9 (1): 70–94. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885109349406.Search in Google Scholar
Ratner, Steven R. 2015. The Thin Justice of International Law: A Moral Reckoning of the Law of Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198704041.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2006. “The Problem of Authority: Revisiting the Service Conception.” Minnesota Law Review 90: 1003–44.Search in Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2019. “The Future of State Sovereignty.” In Legitimacy: The State and Beyond, edited by Wojciech Sadurski, Michael Sevel and Kevin Walton, 69–81. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780198825265.003.0005Search in Google Scholar
Reglitz, Merten. 2015. “Political Legitimacy without a (Claim-) Right to Rule.” Res Publica 21 (3): 291–307. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9267-0.Search in Google Scholar
Renzo, Massimo. 2019. “Political Authority and Unjust Wars.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 99 (2): 336–57, https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12487.Search in Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean Jacques. 2002. The Social Contract: And the First and Second Discourses. New Haven: Yale University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2008. “Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (2): 137–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2007.00291.x.Search in Google Scholar
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1999. Governing in Europe: Effective and Democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198295457.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Scherz, Antoinette. 2013. “The Legitimacy of the Demos: Who Should Be Included in the Demos and on what Grounds?” Living Reviews in Democracy 4 (0): 1–14, https://ethz.ch/content/dam/ethz/special-interest/gess/cis/cis-dam/CIS_DAM_2015/WorkingPapers/Living_Reviews_Democracy/Scherz.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
Scherz, Antoinette. 2021. “Tying Legitimacy to Political Power: Graded Legitimacy Standards for International Institutions.” European Journal of Political Theory 20 (4): 631–53. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885119838137.Search in Google Scholar
Scherz, Antoinette. 2022. “You Can’t Tell Me what to Do! Why Should States Comply with International Institutions?” Journal of Social Philosophy December. josp.12503. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12503.Search in Google Scholar
Scherz, Antoinette, and Alain Zysset. 2020. “The UN Security Council, Normative Legitimacy and the Challenge of Specificity.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 23 (3): 371–91. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2019.1565720.Search in Google Scholar
Simmons, Beth A., and Lisa Martin. 2002. “International Organizations and Institutions.” In Handbook of International Relations, edited by Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse-Kappen and Beth A. Simmons. London: SAGE Publications.Search in Google Scholar
Spinner-Halev, Jeff. 2007. “From Historical to Enduring Injustice.” Political Theory 35 (5): 574–97. https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591707304585.Search in Google Scholar
Stilz, Anna. 2015. “Decolonization and Self-Determination.” Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (1): 1–24. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052515000059.Search in Google Scholar
Tasioulas, John. 2010. “The Legitimacy of International Law.” In The Philosophy of International Law, edited by Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas, 97–116. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Viehoff, Daniel. 2011. “Debate: Procedure and Outcome in the Justification of Authority.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 19 (2): 248–59. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2010.00375.x.Search in Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1992. “Superseding Historic Injustice.” Ethics 103 (1): 4–28. https://doi.org/10.1086/293468.Search in Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2006. “The Core of the Case against Judicial Review.” The Yale Law Journal 115 (6): 1346–406. https://doi.org/10.2307/20455656.Search in Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1964. The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. New York: Simon & Schuster.Search in Google Scholar
Ypi, Lea. 2013. “What’s Wrong with Colonialism.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 41 (2): 158–91. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12014.Search in Google Scholar
© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Special Issue: Legitimacy; Guest Editors: Matthias Brinkmann and Anthony Taylor
- Editorial
- Introduction to Special Issue
- Articles
- Persons, Agents and Wantons
- Political Legitimacy: What’s Wrong with the Power-Liability View?
- Does the Free Group Agency Account of Legitimacy Require Democracy?
- Applying Different Concepts and Conceptions of Legitimacy to the International Level: Service, Free Group Agents, and Autonomy
- Legitimacy Revisited: Moral Power and Civil Disobedience
- Regular Articles
- The Democratic Virtues of Randomized Trials
- Torture and Trolleys: Accepting the Nearly Absolute Wrongness of Philanthropic Torture of a Perpetrator
- Do Promises Towards Fossil Fuel Owners Matter?
- Does a State’s Right to Control Borders Justify Harming Refugees?
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Special Issue: Legitimacy; Guest Editors: Matthias Brinkmann and Anthony Taylor
- Editorial
- Introduction to Special Issue
- Articles
- Persons, Agents and Wantons
- Political Legitimacy: What’s Wrong with the Power-Liability View?
- Does the Free Group Agency Account of Legitimacy Require Democracy?
- Applying Different Concepts and Conceptions of Legitimacy to the International Level: Service, Free Group Agents, and Autonomy
- Legitimacy Revisited: Moral Power and Civil Disobedience
- Regular Articles
- The Democratic Virtues of Randomized Trials
- Torture and Trolleys: Accepting the Nearly Absolute Wrongness of Philanthropic Torture of a Perpetrator
- Do Promises Towards Fossil Fuel Owners Matter?
- Does a State’s Right to Control Borders Justify Harming Refugees?