Home Causal relevance of conditionals: semantics or pragmatics?
Article Open Access

Causal relevance of conditionals: semantics or pragmatics?

  • Robert van Rooij EMAIL logo and Katrin Schulz
Published/Copyright: April 28, 2022

Abstract

In this paper we argue that the antecedent of a (non-analytic) conditional is causally relevant to the consequent, … at least if standard background conditions hold. Natural counterexamples to the causal relevance analysis are argued to be cases where the standardly assumed background condition(s) do not hold.

1 Introduction

The following sentence is inappropriate and misleading:

(1)
If it was sunny in Berlin yesterday, there are COVID casualties in Brazil today.

Why? Because this conditional sentence strongly suggests that what happened in Berlin (the antecedent) is relevant to what happens in Brazil (the consequent). The sentence is misleading because we know no such relevance relationship exists.

Although what makes this conditional sentence misleading is clear, the standard semantic analyses of conditionals by themselves do not predict that anything is wrong with it, because they do not make relevance a part of the meaning of conditionals. According to one such theory (e.g. Adams 1975), the only thing that counts for the meaning of a conditional is that its consequent is likely, or probable, given its antecedent. Given that the consequent of the above conditional is likely, or even certain, Adams’ semantic analysis does not predict that the whole conditional sentence is inappropriate to use. The same prediction follows from the other popular semantic analysis of conditional sentences (e.g., Kratzer 2012; Stalnaker 1968), which demands, instead of relevance, that the consequent is true in all most similar/normal antecedent worlds.

We will discuss two ways to tackle this problem. According to the first semantic solution (e.g. Douven 2008, 2016) conditionals are used as explanations, and relevance is built in into the meaning of the conditional. We discuss two probabilistic ways to work out such a semantic approach. On the first semantic analysis, ‘If A, then C’ (from now on abbreviated by A C ) is assertable if p ( C | A ) p ( C | ¬ A ) = Δ P A C 0 . This analysis seems natural from a psychological point of view, because the measure Δ P A C (from now on abbreviated by Δ P if it is clear what A and C are) is used frequently to measure the learned association between A and C (cf. Shanks 1995). Unfortunately, the use of this notion gives rise to various empirical problems. These problems motivate a second causality-based semantic analysis of conditionals and generics proposed by van Rooij and Schulz (2019, 2021. Unfortunately, it turns out that this analysis won’t be appropriate for all (indicative) conditionals, because the analysis is problematic for some examples where causal relevance seems explicitly denied. To meet these problems, we discuss the natural pragmatic solution: conditional A C is true, or assertable, if P ( C | A ) 1 , but relevance comes out because of the implicature that the consequent is not believed. Although this analysis seems appealing, we will still argue in favour of a slightly adapted causal analysis after all, according to which the measure of causal power is influenced by background conditions as well.

2 Two relevance-based analyses of conditionals

One consequence of standard analyses of conditionals is their acceptance of an inference known as conjunction sufficiency, that A , C | = A C , i.e., the assumption that the (known) truth of A and C suffices for the assertion of (indicative) conditional A C , also without any connection between A and C. This principle, however, seems at odds with an appropriate use of conditionals, as exemplified by (1) and (2):

(2)
If I raise my little finger, there will be rainfall this winter.

where we should suppose that the finger is indeed raised and that there will be rainfall. Conjunction sufficiency is problematic as well if there is a connection, but where the connection is not of the right kind, for instance because the antecedent made the consequent not likely enough or led to it only through an indeterministic process (cf. Khoo 2020):

(3)
a. If he worked hard, he passed (he worked hard, but he passed only because he cheated, too).
b. If the coin was tossed, it fell heads.

Arguably, these examples are odd, because of a lack of (enough) relevance between antecedent and consequent. If one takes conditionals A C to express a positive relevance relation between antecedent and consequent (Douven 2008; Spohn 2013), what comes to mind is that instead of demanding that the conditional probability of C given A, p ( C | A ) is high, one demands that this probability is higher than that of p ( C ) , i.e., p ( C | A ) p ( C ) , or equivalently, Δ P = p ( C | A ) p ( C | ¬ A ) 0 .

If this is all that is demanded, this gives rise to a number of surprising predictions. First, on this analysis Contraposition ( A C ¬ C ¬ A ) and (the conditional variant of) Denying the Antecedent ( A C ¬ A ¬ C ) are predicted to be valid (Suppes 1970), in spite of many counterexamples. Furthermore, although Transitivity ( A B , B C A C ) and Strengthening of the Antecedent ( A C ( A B ) C ) are correctly predicted to be invalid (or so we think, following Adams 1975), under the above Δ P relevance-based analysis of conditionals, counterexamples to such inferences can be found very easily. For linguistic reasons, however, such counterexamples should be really exceptional, because strengthening of the antecedent, for instance, is important for the licensing of negative polarity items in antecedents of conditionals. Indeed, for Stalnaker (1975) these are pragmatic reasonable inferences.

Consider the example due to Eells and Sober (1983) illustrated by the picture below. In the story that belongs to this picture, individuals either smoke, S, or not, ¬ S , at time 1, t 1. At later time t 2 they either get heart attacks, H, or not, and still later, at t 3, they either experience heart pains, P or not. For the picture, we started with 100 representative smokers and 100 representative non-smokers. Note that S H and H P both hold according to the Δ P -based analysis: p ( H | S ) = a > b = p ( H | ¬ S ) and p ( P | H ) = 79 110 > 40 90 = p ( P | ¬ H ) (in fact, both p ( P | S H ) = w > x = p ( P | S ¬ H ) and p ( P | ¬ S H ) = y > z = p ( P | ¬ S ¬ H ) hold). Still it won’t be the case that S P holds according to the Δ P analysis, because p ( P | S ) = 45 100 < 74 100 = p ( P | ¬ S ) .

The reason that transitivity doesn’t go through here is that the probability of getting heart pains depends in this story not just on whether one had a heart attack at t 2, but also on whether one smoked at t 1. In the story, the probability of pain given heart attack and smoking is less than the probability of pain given heart attack and not smoking. To get transitivity, we need to make three assumptions: (i) the probability of having heart pains at t 3 depends only on whether there has been a heart attack at t 2, and is thus independent on what happened at t 1. Thus, p ( P | H S ) = p ( P | H ¬ S ) and p ( P | ¬ H S ) = p ( P | ¬ H ¬ S ) . In causal modelling this is known as the Markov property. The second assumption, (ii), is that to determine whether H P holds, we should not only check whether p ( P | H ) > p ( P | ¬ H ) , but we should also hold the other (background) factors (in this case only whether S) constant, thus we should check whether p ( P | H S ) > p ( P | ¬ H S ) and p ( P | H ¬ S ) > p ( P | ¬ H ¬ S ) hold (this holds in this case). Conditions (i) and (ii) strongly suggest that the conditionals should be given a causal relevance analysis, because this is how causal relevance is determined. But to assure transitivity, we need a third assumption, (iii), as well: there is no other factor at t 2 caused by S that is causally relevant to what happens at t 3. If we make all these three assumptions, we can easily prove that transitivity holds, also on our suggested analysis of conditionals: S H , H P | = S P . Condition (iii) is a minimality assumption (enforced by, e.g., the probability functions with maximal entropy): the assumption that there are no (for S, H and P relevant) other direct causal relevance relations than those mentioned: only S H and H P . Indeed, if we added S D and D ¬ P for new proposition D as premisses, it wouldn’t follow anymore that the indirect causal relation S P is predicted to hold.

The minimality assumption on causal relations can also explain why inferences like Strengthening of the Antecedent ( A C ( A B ) C ) and Contraposition ( A C ¬ C ¬ A ) – although not valid in general – go through in most cases. Strengthening holds, because by minimality B ¬ C . Contraposition holds because from A C and the assumption that C can only be caused by A due to the minimality inference, it follows that A C and we can thus conclude from ¬ C that ¬ A .

Douven (2008) also argued that for a relevance-based analysis of (indicative) conditionals of form A C it is insufficient to just demand that Δ P > 0 . He did so for a rather different reason than we did above, however, and claimed that conditionals require something else as well. Douven demanded that on a proper relevance-based analysis of the conditional A C , it should not only be that (i) p ( C | A ) > p ( C | ¬ A ) , but also that (ii) p ( C | A ) should be high, i.e., close to 1.

Interestingly, this combination of demands means that p ( C | A ) p ( C | ¬ A ) should be close to 1 p ( C | ¬ A ) , which means in turn that p ( C | A ) p ( C | ¬ A ) 1 p ( C | ¬ A ) = Δ * P A C should be high. But this later measure is exactly how Cheng’s (1997) notion of causal power can be estimated (under certain conditions), and van Rooij and Schulz (2019) show that on a causal power analysis, many conditionals, including diagnostic ones, can be handled naturally. Moreover, under the proposed causal power analysis of conditionals and the above mentioned minimality assumption (either due to the idea [cf. Brem and Rips 2000; Mill 1843] that hearers typically ignore alternative causes of C on interpreting A C , or due to an exhaustivity assumption), it immediately follows that the assertability of the conditional normally ‘goes by’ the corresponding conditional probability, p ( C | A ) . A good analysis of conditionals should also account for ‘analytic’ conditionals like ‘If x is a bachelor, x is a man’. Fortunately, our analysis in terms of Δ * P A C can, because if A | = C and p ( C ) 1 , it follows immediately that Δ * P A C = 1 , its maximal value.

3 A pragmatic analysis of relevance

According to the semantic analyses of conditionals discussed in the previous section, the antecedent should be positively relevant to the consequent. But it is clear that this is not always the case: there are examples where positive relevance is not required.

(4)
a. If Mary leaves the party early, Bill will be unhappy,
b. but if Mary doesn’t leave the party early, Bill will still be unhappy.

This suggests that the presumed positive relevance of the antecedent should be due to a pragmatic cancellable implicature. A pragmatic strategy presupposes a semantic analysis of indicative conditionals. What should the basic semantic analysis be? Although they have something to say for themselves, we strongly believe that the material or strict conditional account of indicative conditionals won’t do, for one thing because such analyses predict that indicative conditionals always allow for inferences like ‘strengthening of the antecedent’, ‘transitivity’ and ‘contraposition’, which seem false. For another thing, with such semantic analyses it is hard to capture the intuition that the probability of the conditional ‘If I pick an ace, it is going to be the ace of clubs’ intuitively ‘goes with’ the corresponding conditional probability.

The most direct route to account for the above intuition is that conditional ‘ A C ’ just expresses the speaker’s conditional probability of C given A, i.e., p ( C | A ) . But we don’t want to assume that the assertability value of A C , i.e. A V ( A C ) is simply p ( C | A ) . The reason is that for assertability we have to take into account pragmatic presuppositions and implicatures as well (cf. Skyrms 1980). Instead, let us assume with Skyrms that the basic assertability value of ‘If A, then C’, B A V ( A C ) , is p ( C | A ) . The assertabiility value of the indicative conditional A C , i.e., A V ( A C ) , is then based on its basic assertability value plus the (uncancelleble) appropriateness condition that A is really possible, i.e., 0 < < p ( A ) , and some cancellable pragmatic implicatures.

It only seems natural that the conditional is asserted because the alternative assertion that the consequent C is believed/known could not yet be appropriately made. Thus, A C conversationally implies that p ( C ) < < 1 . Let’s see how this works out:

  1. B A V ( A C ) 1 , and thus p ( C | A ) 1 [1] by assertion.

  2. p ( C ) < < 1 by implicature.

  3. p ( C | A ) p ( C ) > > 0 by 1 and 2.

  4. p ( C | A ) > > p ( C | ¬ A ) , because p ( C | A ) > > p ( C ) iff p ( C | A ) > > p ( C | ¬ A ) .

  5. Thus A V ( A C ) = p ( C | A ) p ( C | ¬ A ) 1 p ( C | ¬ A ) 1 because p ( C | A ) 1 (from 1).

Thus, the demand that relevance measure Δ * P A C should be high discussed in Section 2 falls out as a pragmatic implicature! The idea is that (i) a standard semantic analysis suffices according to which B A V ( A C ) = p ( C | A ) 1 , and (ii) that causal relevance follows as a pragmatic cancellable conversational implicature. The implicature of (4-a) that Bill’s unhappiness would be caused by Mary’s leaving early is cancelled by (4-b).

Also for counterfactual, or subjunctive conditionals the antecedent is normally causally relevant to the consequent. Indeed, such conditionals have much in common with indicative conditionals, although in contrast to indicative conditionals, for counterfactuals it is typically assumed that p ( A ) = 0 , if p is the current subjective probability function (cf. Stalnaker 1975). Indeed, Adams (1975) proposed that for counterfactuals we should look at the prior probability state, where A was still possible. This gives rise to the correct predictions for many examples, but not all. To see this, look at the following examples due to Morgenbesser and Edgington, respectively:

(5)
a. If John had bet on heads, he would have won.
b. If John had caught the flight, he would be in Paris now.

Intuitively, B A V ( A C ) would be 1 2 for (5-a), because we assume that the past chance of winning conditional on betting heads was 1 2 . Similarly, we may be almost certain about (5-b), given that we take the past chance of being in Paris conditional on taking the flight to Paris to be very high. However, suppose for (5-a) that we know that the coin came up heads. We then can be certain that John would have won, because how the coin would have landed would not have been influenced by John’s betting on the outcome. An analogous situation can arise with respect to (5-b) as described by Edgington (1995). Assume that we know that the plane crashed because the on-board computer broke down. Given this, we should have a probability close to 0 in (5-b), because if John had caught the flight, he would be dead now. Thus, Adams’ prior probability account is not completely correct:[2] we have to take into account facts that occurred later, but that were causally independent of the antecedent (see also Schulz 2011).

In the above cases the antecedent was causally relevant to the consequent. But it seems that doesn’t always have to be the case.[3] Consider the following variant of Tichy’s (1976) well-known example due to Frank Veltman:

Suppose that Jones always flips a coin before he opens the curtains to see what the weather is like. Heads means he is going to wear his hat in case the weather is fine, whereas tails means he is not going to wear his hat in that case. Like above, bad weather invariably makes him wear his hat. Now suppose that today heads came up when he filipped the coin, and that it is raining. So, Jones is wearing his hat.

Now the question is whether the following sentence is acceptable:

(6)
If the weather had been fine, Jones would (still) have been wearing his hat.

Intuitively, the answer is ‘yes’. This means that we conclude that the antecedent doesn’t have any causal effect on the consequent. It seems that the use of ‘still’, like in (6), indicates that causal relevance doesn’t play a role here, suggesting that the inference to causal relevance is indeed a cancellable conversational implicature.

4 Some doubts on the semantic/pragmatic picture

First, there are doubts about the semantic analysis that B A V ( A C ) = p ( C | A ) . Rothschild (2013) argues by example that at least sometimes p ( A C ) p ( C | A ) . As it turns out,[4] to account for Rothschild’s example, B A V ( A C ) should not be equated with p ( C | A ) , but rather with Pearl’s (2000) causal measure p ( C | d o ( A ) ) that he used to analyse counterfactual conditionals. Pearl’s p ( C | d o ( A ) ) can be estimated by b i B p ( b i ) × p ( C | A , b i ) , a measure already proposed by Skyrms (1984) to account also for indicative conditionals. Here B = { b i } is the partition of the set of worlds still possible into causally relevant background conditions for C.[5] Notice that the new proposal that B A V ( A C ) = p ( C | d o ( A ) ) is still compatible with the pragmatic analysis: by a similar reasoning as above it now follows that A V ( A C ) = p ( C | d o ( A ) ) p ( C | d o ( ¬ A ) ) 1 p ( C | d o ( ¬ A ) ) 1 , due to the cancellable implicature that C is not believed.[6]

Second, Krzyzanowska (2019) and Skovgaard-Olsen et al. (2019) argue on experimental grounds against the above pragmatic analysis: the relevance effect doesn’t seem to be cancellable, which according to Griceans is a defining feature of conversational implicatures. They point out, for instance, that an attempt to cancel the relevance effect by an explicit denial is rated by participants as completely inappropriate:

(7)
*If Mary left the party early, Bill was unhappy, though these things have nothing to do with each other.

The inappropriateness of (7) suggests that it is impossible to make a conditional claim if the antecedent and consequent have nothing to do with each other. However, that doesn’t mean that the relevance effect of the antecedent is thus not due to an implicature. It just means, or so we will argue, that the inference to a relevance relation comes about in another way.

5 Causal relevance w.r.t. background assumptions

To work towards our proposal for how the implicature comes about, let us look again at (6), on the assumption that we interpret the conditional in terms of an intervention, that is, in terms of d o ( A ) . Given that (6) is appropriate, we can learn something about the underlying causal model. First, B A V ( A C ) can only be high in case p ( C | d o ( A ) ) is high. If we know, or strongly believe, that p ( C ) 0 , this means that A has a positive causal effect on C, and thus that the causal picture is either A + C , or something of which it is part. In case C is already known, however, B A V ( A C ) can only be high in case the causal model must be such that A doesn’t make any difference anymore. This can be if A is causally completely unrelated to C. However, based on the inappropriateness of examples like (7), that seems unnatural. Another possibility is that now A is only a contributing cause of C, and the causal model is an AND-gate of the form A C + + B : A and B are both causally necessary conditions for C to hold. The latter seems to hold in the example involving Jones and his hat: if A holds, B (i.e., heads) is also required for C.

Before we take background, or enabling, assumptions into account, let us first see how the measure Δ * P A C that we discussed in Section 2 for the analysis of conditionals follows from Cheng’s (1997) causal analysis. To do so, assume with Cheng (1997) that events of type a have unobservable causal powers to produce events of type c denoted by p ac . The causal power p ac is taken to be a local property of a, and thus very different from p ( c | a ) = p ( a c ) p ( a ) , which is only a global property. We assume for now that events of type c are either due to events of type a, or due to other events of type o, thus the relevant causal structure is an OR-gate like A C + + O , and p ( c | ¬ a , ¬ o ) = 0 . It follows that p ( c ) can be determined as follows:

(8)
p ( c ) = p ( a ) × p a c + p ( o ) × p o c ( p ( a o ) × p a c × p o c )  .

From this we immediately derive p ac , the causal power of a to generate c. This is nothing else but the probability of c, conditional on a and ¬ o :[7]

(9)
p a c = p ( c | a , ¬ o )  .

One problem with this notion is that it depends on o, and this is not always observable. Fortunately, if we assume that a and o are, or are believed to be, independent, Cheng (1997) shows that we can estimate p ac after all. The estimation of p ac given the above OR-gate is exactly the probabilistic relevance notion that we mentioned in Section 2:

(10)
p a c = p ( c | a ) p ( c | ¬ a ) 1 p ( c | ¬ a ) = Δ * P a c .

So far, to determine p ac it was assumed that a by itself can cause c. Of course, this is a simplification for almost all cases of causal attributions. Striking a match, for instance, does not by itself cause it to light. Certain background, or enabling conditions have to be in place: there must be oxygen in the environment, the match must be dry, etc. In fact, for deterministic causation we can think of Δ * P a c = p a c as modelling the probability of the background conditions. Suppose that a can interact with b to cause c. The causal power of conjunctive cause ab, given b, to produce c is then

(11)
p a b , c = p ( c | a , ¬ o , b ) = P ( c | a , b ) p ( c | ¬ a , b ) 1 p ( c | ¬ a , b ) = Δ b * P a c

Now p a c = p ( b ) , if b is necessary for c, p ( c | ¬ b ) = 0 , and a and b jointly sufficient, p a b , c = 1 .

With this machinery we can now tackle examples where the antecedent seems (causally) irrelevant to the consequent. How is it possible for party-lover Bill that on the one hand (12) and (4-a)–(4-b), repeated here as (13-a)–(13-b), are appropriate,

(12)
Even if Mary leaves the party early, Bill will be happy.
(13)
a. If Mary leaves the party early, Bill will be unhappy,
b. but If Mary doesn’t leave the party early, Bill will still/nevertheless be unhappy.

although on the other hand (7) is inappropriate, suggesting that Mary’s leaving early is taken to be causally related with Bill’s unhappiness? To tackle this question, let’s say that a stands for ‘Mary leaves the party early’, c for ‘Bill will be unhappy’, and alternative o for, say, ‘Sue leaves the party early.’ Now consider the following conditional probability tables (where p ( c | a , o , b ) = 1 ( p a b , ¬ c × p o b , ¬ c )):

The tables differ only in the boxed entries. Notice that according to both tables,

(14)
p a b , c = p ( c | a , ¬ o , b ) = 0.9 = p ( c | a , b ) p ( c | ¬ a , b ) 1 p ( c | ¬ a , b ) = Δ b * P a c  .

We will assume that a conditional of the form a c is appropriate iff p ac is high, where p ac is now determined as follows, taking background b into account as well:

(15)
p a c = p ( c | a , ¬ o , b ) × p ( b ) + p ( c | a , ¬ o , ¬ b ) × p ( ¬ b )  .

How can we account for the appropriateness of (12), represented by a ¬ c ? Let’s assume that Bill’s supposed unhappiness if Mary leaves the party early is based on the background assumption that, say, Bill not only loves parties but is even more desperately in love with Mary. So, what (12) asserts is that p a ¬ c is high, and it implies that p a b , c is high, higher than p o b , c . What is asserted and what is implied are not in contrast with each other according to Table 1, if the speaker has good reason to believe that in contrast to the standard assumption, background b is false. Similarly, Table 2 can explain why conditionals (13-a) and (13-b) are both appropriate. These sentences claim that p a c and p ¬ a c are high, respectively, and according to Table 2 this can only be if the background condition b is taken to be false. On the other hand, it is still the case that a and c (are assumed to) have something to do with each other, for indeed a has high causal power to produce c in case the assumed background condition b is in place. Thus, or so we argue, examples like (13-a)-(13-b) do not falsify a causal relevance analysis of conditionals. However, this causal relevance is dependent on the standard background assumption, an assumption the speaker implies to be false by (13-b). As it turns out, the background assumption doesn’t even have to be taken to be expected, it can also be at issue, as shown by the following example due to Reinhard Muskens:

Table 1.

Table 2.

(16)
a. Will Bill be unhappy, if Mary leaves the party early?
b. No, even if Mary leaves early, Bill will be happy.

6 Conclusion

We propose that with a (non-analytic) conditional of the form A C it always has to be the case that A is causally relevant to C. This implies that antecedent A normally makes a difference to C, but that this doesn’t always have to be the case. It is not the case if the standardly, or at issue, assumed background condition does not hold. One can say that with the use of conditional A C a speaker asserts (and thus not just implies) that on the relevant background condition, A is causally relevant to C (where this relevance can be negative, as in (12)), that (s)he conversationally implies that this background condition holds, but that a speaker can make clear – e.g. by using markers like ‘still’ and ‘even’ – that the background condition does not hold.


Corresponding author: Robert van Rooij, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation (ILLC), University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands, E-mail:

Funding source: NWO

Award Identifier / Grant number: 406.18.TW.007

Award Identifier / Grant number: 406.D1.19.059

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented in an (online) colloquium in Amsterdam and in an (online) workshop in Freiburg in spring 2021. We like to thank the audiences for their comments and challenging questions. We would also like to thank Dean McHugh for correcting the English.

  1. Research funding: The work for this paper was supported by NWO (10.13039/501100003246) grant ‘From Learning to Meaning: A new approach to Generic Sentences and Implicit Biases’ (dossiernumber 406.18.TW.007) and by NWO grant ‘The biased reality of online media – Using stereotypes to make media manipulation visible’ (dossiernumber 406.D1.19.059).

References

Adams, Ernest. 1975. The logic of conditionals. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.10.1007/978-94-015-7622-2Search in Google Scholar

Brem, Sarah & Lance Rips. 2000. Explanation and evidence in informal arguments. Cognitive Science 24. 573–604.10.1207/s15516709cog2404_2Search in Google Scholar

Cheng, Patricia. 1997. From covariation to causation: A causal power theory. Psychological Review 104. 367–405.10.1037/0033-295X.104.2.367Search in Google Scholar

Douven, Igor. 2008. The evidential support theory of conditionals. Synthese 164. 19–44.10.1007/s11229-007-9214-5Search in Google Scholar

Douven, Igor. 2016. The epistemology of indicative conditionals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781316275962Search in Google Scholar

Edgington, Dorothy. 1995. On conditionals. Mind 104. 235–329.10.1093/mind/104.414.235Search in Google Scholar

Eells, Ellery & Elliott Sober. 1983. Probabilistic causality and the question of transitiviity. Philosophy of Science 50. 35–57.10.1086/289089Search in Google Scholar

Kaufmann, Stefan. 2004. Conditioning against the grain: Abduction and indicative conditionals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 33. 583–606.10.1023/B:LOGI.0000046142.51136.bfSearch in Google Scholar

Khoo, Justin. 2020. The meaning of if. Manuscript.Search in Google Scholar

Kratzer, Angelica. 2012. Modals and conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199234684.003.0004Search in Google Scholar

Krzyzanowska, Karolina. 2019. What is wrong with false-link conditionals? Linguistics Vanguard 5. 1–9.10.1515/lingvan-2019-0006Search in Google Scholar

Mill, John Stuart. 1843. A system of logic. London: John W. Parker, West Strand.Search in Google Scholar

Pearl, Judea. 2000. Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Rooij, Rorbert van & Katrin Schulz. 2019. Conditionals, causality and conditional probability. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 28. 55–71.10.1007/s10849-018-9275-5Search in Google Scholar

Rooij, Robert van & Katrin Schulz. 2021. A causal power theory of generics. Topoi 40. 131–146.10.1007/s11245-019-09663-4Search in Google Scholar

Rothschild, Daniel. 2013. Do indicative conditionals express propositions? Noûs 47. 49–68.10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00825.xSearch in Google Scholar

Schulz, Katrin. 2011. If you’d wiggled A, then B would’ve changed. Causality and counterfactual conditionals. Synthese 179. 239–251.10.1007/s11229-010-9780-9Search in Google Scholar

Shanks, David. 1995. The psychology of associative learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511623288Search in Google Scholar

Skovgaard-Olsen, Niels., Peter Collins, Karolina Krzyzanowska, Ulrike Hahn & Karl Christoph Klauer. 2019. Cancellation, negation, and rejection. Cognitive Psychology 108. 42–71.10.1016/j.cogpsych.2018.11.002Search in Google Scholar

Skyrms, Brian. 1980. Causal necessity. New Haven: Yale University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Skyrms, Brain. 1984. Pragmatics and empiricism. New Haven: Yale University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Spohn, Wolfgang. 2013. A ranking-theoretic approach to conditionals. Cognitive Science 37. 1074–1106.10.1111/cogs.12057Search in Google Scholar

Stalnaker, Robert. 1968. A theory of conditionals. In J. W. Comman. (ed.), Studies in logical theory: Essays, 98–112. Oxford: Blackwell.10.1007/978-94-009-9117-0_2Search in Google Scholar

Stalnaker, Robert. 1975. Indicative conditionals. Philosophia 5. 269–286.10.1007/BF02379021Search in Google Scholar

Suppes, Patrick. 1970. A probabilistic theory of causality. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Search in Google Scholar

Tichy, Pavel. 1976. A counterexample to the Stalnaker–Lewis analysis of counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies 29. 271–273.10.1007/BF00411887Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2021-03-02
Accepted: 2021-04-26
Published Online: 2022-04-28

© 2021 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 26.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/lingvan-2021-0030/html
Scroll to top button