Abstract
Copulative perception verbs such as English sound have received scant attention relative to other perception verbs, especially in non-European languages. In Hebrew, these verbs can take both adjectival and adverbial complements, a fact which sets Hebrew apart from previously studied languages, and which has heretofore been overlooked. This article investigates the usage of Hebrew copulative perception verbs with adverbial complements, with adjectival complements, and in impersonal constructions. A large-scale corpus study and a preference experiment reveal that each of these three constructions has a different interpretation. With adverbial complements, the verbs have an “attributary” meaning, attributing properties to perceptual impressions of objects. The complement slot in these cases is restricted to subjective multidimensional properties, which previous accounts of the attributary meaning fail to predict, motivating a novel analysis in terms of dimension selection. With adjectival complements, as well as in impersonal constructions, the verbs have a parenthetical meaning, taking and modifying a proposition argument. The two constructions are not equivalent, however. With adjectival complements, the verbs encode evidential but not epistemic information, and vice versa in impersonal constructions, reinforcing the need to maintain a distinction between the classes of evidentials and epistemic modals.
1 Introduction
In an interview on the talk show “Late Night with Seth Meyers”, actress Rachel Bloom described an online comment (emphases mine):
Some guy wrote on a video I was in ‘ she looks like her butt stinks ’. So here’s the thing. I can’t… So it’s like… This is like five years later, I can’t… I don’t know if that means ‘ she looks like she has a stinky butt ’, which I do, as does everybody. Uh, or, if it’s like ‘she looks like her butt stinks ’, like ‘ she looks as bad as her butt stinks ’. (Season 3, Episode 61, aired 14 January 2016).
As Bloom observes, copulative perception verbs such as English look have more than one meaning, and these meanings can be difficult to distinguish, even in context. The present article sheds new light on the class of copulative perception verbs by exploring these verbs in Hebrew, where they exhibit a grammatical alternation which has heretofore been overlooked.
The semantic domain of perception is quickly becoming one of the better-studied lexical fields, both within individual languages (e.g., Winter 2016) and crosslinguistically (e.g., Majid et al. 2018). In addition to the interest it generates in and of itself, research into the lexicon of perception ties into central linguistic concepts such as evidentiality (e.g., Whitt 2010) and subjectivity (e.g., Kaiser 2018).
Verbs of perception have received their fair share of attention in this literature (e.g., Evans and Wilkins 2000; Gisborne 2010; Ibarretxe-Antuñano 1999; Viberg 1983). A fundamental distinction is drawn between experiencer-based and phenomenon-based verbs (Viberg 1983). Experiencer-based verbs take an experiencer as their grammatical subject and refer to an act of perceiving by that experiencer. Phenomenon-based verbs, on the other hand, take a stimulus as their grammatical subject, and refer to a perceptual impression of that stimulus. They may be further divided into copulative verbs, such as sound (like), which require a predicate or clausal complement, and verbs such as buzz, which are predicates in themselves.[1]
There is some overlap between the verb classes described above, in that a single lexical form can belong to more than one class. For example, English smell occurs as an experiencer-based verb (e.g., I smelled it), a copulative verb (e.g., It smelled bad), and a phenomenon-based predicate (e.g., It smelled). The different classes may nonetheless be distinguished in such cases, based on their grammatical properties (inflections, argument structure, etc.).
My interest here is in the class of copulative perception verbs (henceforth CPVs), which are often overshadowed in the literature by the other classes of perception verbs. A first clue that these verbs are understudied is the lack of a single accepted label for them. The same class has been referred to as flip perception verbs (Rogers 1974), physical perception verbs (Asudeh 2002), perceptual resemblance verbs (Asudeh 2004), object-oriented perception verbs (Whitt 2009), sound-class verbs (Gisborne 2010), perceptual source verbs (Landau 2011), psych predicates (Anand and Korotkova 2018), descriptive perception verbs (Poortvliet 2018), and sensory copulas (Viberg 2019). Additionally, some studies simply refer to a construction in which they occur, e.g., looks like (Hansen and Markman 2005; Kaiser 2018). I adopt the label “copulative” from Taniguchi (1997) because it highlights the unique properties of the class without presupposing an analysis.
There has been very little work on CPVs in non-European languages. I therefore explore the class of CPVs in Hebrew, focusing on three constructions in which they occur, exemplified in (1) and (2) below. In (1a) and (2a), the verb takes an adjectival complement that agrees in gender (and number) with the verb’s subject. In this sense, the verb behaves like a copula; cf. (3a). I call this the copulative construction. In contrast, in (1b) and (2b), the verb’s subject and complement do not agree, and in fact, the complements in these cases are not adjectival at all, but adverbial (see also Avineri 2021).[2] That is, the verbs in these cases pattern with run-of-the-mill verbs modified by adverbs; cf. (3b). To the best of my knowledge, Hebrew is the first language reported to allow both adjectival and adverbial complements for CPVs.[3],[4] I call this the verbal construction. Finally, in (1c) and (2c) the verb occurs in an impersonal construction, either with the expletive subject ze or with no subject. Examples marked with [g] were retrieved from Google.
ani | nishma’at | muzara | kshe-ani | menasa | lesaper | mashehu. [g] | Copulative |
I | sound.fsg | weird.fsg | when-I | try.fsg | to.tell | something | |
‘I sound weird whenever I try to say something.’ |
kshe-ani | shara | be-ivrit | ani | nishma’at | muzar . [g] | Verbal |
when-I | sing.fsg | in-Hebrew | I | sound.fsg | weirdly | |
‘When I sing in Hebrew I sound weird.’ |
ulay | ze | nishma | she-ani | muzara | she-ani | shoelet. [g] | Impersonal |
maybe | it | sounds.msg | that-I | weird.fsg | that-I | ask.fsg | |
‘Maybe it sounds like I’m weird for asking this.’ |
hu | nire | axer, | muzar [g] | Copulative |
he | looks.msg | different.msg | weird.msg | |
‘He looks different, strange.’ |
ba-tmuna | hu | nire | axeret | legamrey [g] | Verbal |
in.the-picture | he | looks.msg | differently | completely | |
‘In the picture he looks completely different.’ |
ve-gam | me-ha-tguvot | shelo | nire | li | ||
and-also | from-the-comments | his | looks.msg | to.me | ||
she-hu axer . [g] | Impersonal | |||||
that-he different.msg | ||||||
‘And also from his comments it looks to me like he’s different.’ |
raxel | hayta | muzara. | Copula |
Rachel | was.fsg | weird.fsg | |
‘Rachel was weird.’ |
raxel | hitnahaga | muzar. | Verb |
Rachel | behaved.fsg | weirdly | |
‘Rachel behaved oddly.’ |
The copulative and verbal constructions exhibit distributional differences, which I take to be clues for semantic differences. I present a large-scale corpus study showing that the constructions vary in their co-occurrence with different CPVs and with a dative argument, and attract different complements and subjects. In particular, the copulative construction attracts abstract complements (e.g., hegyoni ‘logical’) and abstract subjects (e.g., she’ela ‘question’), whereas the verbal construction attracts subjective multidimensional complements (e.g., tov ‘good’) and perceivable subjects (e.g., ish ‘person’).
These findings suggest that verbal and copulative constructions map to previously identified meanings of CPVs. The verbal construction has an attributary meaning: it attributes a property to a perceptual impression. However, the complement slot of the construction is more restricted than predicted by previous accounts of the attributary meaning (e.g., Gisborne 2010; Muñoz 2019), motivating a novel account in terms of dimension selection (Sassoon 2013). The copulative construction, as well as the impersonal construction, have a parenthetical meaning: they take and modify a proposition argument. But the two constructions are not equivalent. I present a preference experiment revealing that the copulative construction encodes an evidential meaning, whereas the impersonal encodes an epistemic modal meaning. Consequently, the three-way formal distinction corresponds to a three-way semantic distinction.
2 Background
The literature on CPVs is not a cohesive body of work. In the generative tradition, recent studies on CPVs focus on one particular construction known as Copy Raising, e.g., Rachel looks like she went to a show, especially on the relationship between the matrix subject and its “copy”, the embedded pronoun (Asudeh 2002, 2004; Asudeh and Toivonen 2012; Landau 2011; but cf. Muñoz 2019). In contrast, studies drawing on cognitive or functional linguistics focus on relating CPVs to other perception verbs, synchronically and diachronically (Fernández Jaén 2015; Gisborne 2010; Jackendoff 2007; Taniguchi 1997; Whitt 2009, 2010). Other studies do not investigate CPVs per se, but rather, use them as diagnostics or in experimental materials to investigate other issues (Fishman 2022; Hansen and Markman 2005; Kaiser 2018; McNally and Stojanovic 2017). The divergent theoretical perspectives, methodologies and terminology, all lead to researchers overlooking previous observations or, inadvertently, “reinventing the wheel”. Rather than discuss previous studies individually, below I review recurring themes and noteworthy points of contention, glossing over differences in terminology and theoretical assumptions.
First, most researchers agree that CPVs have more than one meaning. Specifically, most researchers distinguish between an attributary meaning (following Gisborne 2010), which attributes a property to (a perceptual impression of) an object, and a parenthetical meaning, which modifies a proposition. The parenthetical meaning might be specified as an epistemic modal, i.e., relating a proposition to an individual’s beliefs, or as an evidential, i.e., relating a proposition to a type or source of evidence, or as both. To illustrate the difference between attributary and parenthetical meanings, contrast the exchange in (4), which concerns an auditory impression of Rachel, with the one in (5), which concerns (belief in or evidence for) the proposition ‘Rachel is a good comedian’. This basic semantic distinction underlies my review of the literature in this section, as well as my discussion of the empirical findings in Section 3.2.
A: Is Rachel a good singer? | |
B: Yeah, I’ve heard her sing and she sounds really good . | Attributary |
A: Is Rachel a good comedian? | |
B: I haven’t seen her perform, but she sounds really good . | Parenthetical |
The distinct meanings of CPVs were pointed out as early as Rogers (1974). Rogers focuses on one meaning of CPVs, which he analyzes as a belief caused by a perception – a parenthetical meaning which is both evidential and epistemic. But he notes that CPVs have at least two other meanings: one which doesn’t presuppose “actual physical perception” and is “roughly synonymous with… seem” (p. 90) – epistemic but not evidential; and another which attributes a property to an object only with regard to the sensory modality expressed by the verb (p. 152) – attributary. Later researchers independently reached similar conclusions, even if couched in different terms. For example, Hansen and Markman (2005) propose that the construction looks like can refer either to “likely reality” – epistemic parenthetical; or to “outward appearance”, which covers both true attribution of properties – attributary; and mistaken belief in a proposition – evidential parenthetical (p. 236).
Despite these observations, the fact that CPVs have multiple meanings nevertheless goes unnoticed at times, which again speaks to the status of CPVs as understudied. Overlooking this fact can have detrimental consequences when the verbs are employed as linguistic diagnostics or in experimental materials (e.g., Anand and Korotkova 2018; Kaiser 2018; McNally and Stojanovic 2017).
Next, it is well-established that CPVs can freely take adjectival complements, comparative complements and clausal complements, with the latter also available in impersonal constructions; see (6a)–(6d).[5] Other complements are more limited. For instance, English look can take infinitive complements, look and sound can both take nominal complements, and taste and smell can both take complements headed by of; see (7a)–(7d) (Examples (7a)–(7c) are from Usoniene 2000). As I show in Section 3, Hebrew has counterpart constructions for (6a)–(6d) and (7d), along with a variant taking an adverbial complement, an alternation which has not been discussed in earlier studies.
Rachel looks funny. |
Rachel looks like a comedian. |
Rachel looks like/as if/as though she went to a show. |
It looks like/as if/as though Rachel went to a show. |
Most of them looked to be students. |
Confrontation looked a real possibility. |
From the way you describe him he sounds a real idiot. |
It tastes/smells of garlic. |
When it comes to pairing (surface) structures with meanings, there is general agreement that CPVs with an adjectival complement can have both attributary and parenthetical meanings (Gisborne 2010; Lasersohn 1995; Muñoz 2019; Poortvliet 2018; Rogers 1974; Whitt 2011; but cf. Landau 2011), as do CPVs with a comparative complement (Gisborne 2010; Hansen and Markman 2005; Lasersohn 1995; Poortvliet 2018; but cf. Rogers 1974). Thus, (6a) above can either attribute funniness to Rachel’s looks, or modify the proposition ‘Rachel is funny’. Likewise, (6b) can either compare Rachel’s looks to those of a (generic or specific) comedian, or modify the proposition ‘Rachel is a comedian’. The main goal of the corpus study in Section 3.1 is to explore which meanings are possible for Hebrew CPVs with adjectival and with adverbial complements.
A number of studies draw explicit parallels between adjectival complements in the attributary use, and adverbs. Postal (1971) proposes that the adjectives in these cases are irregular -ly adverbs. Taniguchi (1997) argues that English CPVs developed out of the use of the phenomenon-based predicates sound and smell with adverbs (e.g., The alarm sounded loudly, The food smelled unpleasantly), and Poortvliet (2018) makes a similar argument for Dutch klinken ‘sound’ and ruiken ‘smell’. In Gisborne’s (2010) analysis, the way CPVs compose with their complements in attributary uses parallels the way other verbs compose with adverbs. These parallels naturally raise the hypothesis that Hebrew cases with adverbial complements would have attributary meanings.
As for CPVs with a clausal complement, there is again general agreement that they only have parenthetical meanings (Avineri 2021; Gisborne 2010; Landau 2011; Lasersohn 1995; Poortvliet 2018; Rogers 1974; Viberg 2019; Whitt 2011). But disagreements surface as to whether parenthetical meanings are the same for different structures. Rogers (1974) and Lasersohn (1995) don’t correlate different structures with different parenthetical meanings. In Gisborne’s (2010), Landau’s (2011) and Muñoz’s (2019) analyses, parenthetical meanings are always evidential, but impersonal constructions differ from other constructions in that they never specify a source of evidence. Hansen and Markman (2005) go further and imply that looks like in impersonal constructions can only be an epistemic modal, whereas in other constructions it can be an evidential instead. In Section 3.3, I report on a preference experiment designed to test whether parenthetical meanings differ between two Hebrew constructions.
In addition to the grammatical categories of CPVs’ subjects and complements, some studies also address their conceptual categories. In attributary uses, it is typically taken for granted that the verb’s subject denotes a stimulus perceivable through the relevant sensory modality (Gisborne 2010; Landau 2011; Lasersohn 1995; Petersen and Gamerschlag 2014). In parenthetical uses, a few researchers take the verb’s subject to again denote a perceivable stimulus (Asudeh and Toivonen 2012; Petersen and Gamerschlag 2014), but others find cases where it denotes something not perceivable through the relevant sense, e.g., an abstract entity (Avineri 2021; Gisborne 2010; Landau 2011; Lasersohn 1995; Poortvliet 2018; Rogers 1974; Usoniene 2000; Viberg 2019).
Regarding the verb’s complement, in attributary uses it is taken to denote a predicate over the relevant sensory modality, which is often a value judgment (Albelda Marco and Jansegers 2019; Poortvliet 2018; Rogers 1974: 151; Staniewski and Gołębiowski 2021; Usoniene 2000; Viberg 2019; Whitt 2009, 2011). The status of predicates associated with a single sense, as in look red or sound loud, is contested. While Gisborne (2010) along with Petersen and Gamerschlag (2014) consider these exemplary attributary uses, Viberg (2019) finds that they stand out for “point(ing) to uncertainty or special conditions” (p. 30), echoing the discussion in Grice and White (1961). In parenthetical uses, Petersen and Gamerschlag (2014) argue that the verb’s complement is permissible only if it denotes a property inferable through the relevant sensory modality (see also Rogers 1974: 138). For example, the complement of taste cannot normally denote a shape. In the corpus study presented below, I explore how two Hebrew constructions differ in which complements and subjects they attract.
In most studied languages, CPVs also optionally take a dative argument, which is analyzed as an experiencer, belief-holder, evidence-holder, or some combination thereof (Asudeh and Toivonen 2012; Avineri 2021; Jackendoff 2007; Landau 2011; Muñoz 2019; Usoniene 2000). Gisborne (2010) posits a difference between parenthetical and attributary meanings, in that the former have an obligatory experiencer role, which is filled pragmatically in the absence of a dative argument, whereas the latter have no experiencer role and never take a dative argument. In the corpus study presented below, I examine whether the different Hebrew constructions vary in co-occurrence with a dative argument.
Finally, and notably, most researchers do not propose an explicit procedure for disambiguating uses of CPVs, and only distinguish them by explicating or paraphrasing their meanings. Hansen and Markman (2005) argue that having such a procedure is critical for experimental studies employing CPVs, and a similar argument could be made for coding naturally occurring data. The few such procedures to have been developed are all quite limited in their applicability. Lasersohn (1995) offers a diagnostic for distinguishing uses of sound when it is followed by like NP: the attributary meaning is preserved, but the parenthetical is not, when a second mention of sounds is added after the NP. Thus, John sounds like a frog sounds can only attribute a description to John’s sound. Hansen and Markman (2005) claim that an epistemic meaning is the default for looks like, but can be blocked if relevant information is made part of the conversation’s common ground. Thus, a non-epistemic meaning can be forced by spelling out knowledge of the verb’s subject, e.g., This sponge looks like a rock, or by adding a qualification, e.g., This looks like a rock but that’s not what it really is. Gisborne (2010) similarly proposes using the continuation but (it) isn’t really to distinguish between different uses of CPVs with an adjectival complement. Parenthetical uses, but not attributary uses, allow this continuation. Thus, Rachel looks funny, but isn’t really can only be about the proposition ‘Rachel is funny’ and cannot attribute funniness to Rachel’s looks. In Section 3.2, I apply Gisborne’s diagnostic to Hebrew CPVs and show that it has a straightforward grammatical explanation.
3 Hebrew copulative perception verbs
The class of CPVs in Hebrew consists of nire ‘look’, nishma ‘sound’, meriax ‘smell’ and margish ‘feel’.[6] Each of these lexemes has other uses in addition to their CPV use. Most prominently, meriax and margish are also used as experiencer-based verbs (this alternation is discussed in detail by Avineri 2021), similarly to English smell and taste, while nire and nishma are also used as the passive forms of the experiencer-based verbs roe ‘see’ and shomea ‘hear’, respectively.[7]
Hebrew CPVs can take as their complement an adjectival phrase, an adverbial phrase, a comparative construction headed by kmo ‘like’ or ke- ‘as’, or a clausal complement with the complementizer keilu ‘as if’. Impersonal constructions – without a subject or with the expletive subject ze – additionally allow the complementizers she- ‘that’ and ki ‘that’. The CPV meriax ‘smell’ can also take a prepositional complement in the form me-DP ‘of DP’. The various complements are demonstrated in (8a)–(8f). Regardless of which type of complement they take, Hebrew CPVs may optionally take a dative argument.
raxel | niret | /nishma’at | /merixa | /margisha | muzara. | Copulative | |
Rachel | looks. | /sounds. | /smells. | /feels.fsg | weird.fsg | ||
‘Rachel looks/sounds/smells/feels weird.’ |
raxel niret | /nishma’at | /merixa | /margisha | muzar. | Verbal | ||||
Rachel looks. | /sounds. | /smells. | /feels.fsg | weirdly | |||||
‘Rachel looks/sounds/smells/feels weird.’ |
raxel niret | /nishma’at | /merixa | /margisha | kmo | komikait. | |
Rachel looks. | /sounds. | /smells. | /feels.fsg | like | comedian.f | |
‘Rachel looks/sounds/smells/feels like a comedian.’ |
raxel niret | /nishma’at | /merixa | /margisha | keilu | hi | hayta | be-hofa’a. | |
Rachel looks. | /sounds. | /smells. | /feels.fsg | as.if | she | was.fsg | in-show | |
‘Rachel looks/sounds/smells/feels like she went to a show.’ |
(ze) nire | /nishma | /meriax | /margish | she- | /keilu | raxel | hayta | be-hofa’a. | |
(it) looks. | /sounds. | /smells. | /feels.msg | that- | /as.if | Rachel | was.fsg | in-show | |
‘It looks/sounds/smells/feels like Rachel went to a show.’ |
raxel | merixa | me-sigaryot. |
Rachel | smells | of-cigarettes |
‘Rachel smells of cigarettes.’ |
3.1 Corpus study
In this section I present distributional data on Hebrew CPVs extracted from the Hebrew Web 2014 corpus (heTenTen14, with automated part-of-speech tagging developed by Meni Adler) available on www.sketchengine.eu (Kilgarriff et al. 2014). This is a multiple domain corpus of 890 million words, made up of texts collected from the Internet, including newspaper materials, Wikipedia articles, blog posts, and both personal and commercial web pages. In presenting the data, I focus on differences between the copulative and verbal constructions, examining their distributions with each CPV, their co-occurrence with a dative argument, and the subjects and complements they attract. The corpus data and the scripts used to analyze them are available online at https://osf.io/g7kw6/.
To make it possible to distinguish between copulative and verbal constructions, data on them are restricted to feminine and plural inflections of the CPVs. This is because adjectival and adverbial complements in masculine singular form are indistinguishable, with very few exceptions. To eliminate false positives where margish ‘feel’ occurs as an experiencer-based verb rather than a CPV, data on it are restricted to instances with a dative argument. This is because margish takes the same types of complements whether it occurs as a CPV or as an experiencer-based verb, and the latter are far more frequent.[8]
The total occurrences of each CPV in copulative, verbal and impersonal constructions, and their co-occurrence with a dative argument in each construction, are presented in Table 1. Overall, nire ‘look’ is more frequent than nishma ‘sound’ by an order of magnitude, as is nishma in comparison to meriax ‘smell’. The frequency of margish ‘feel’ falls between nishma and meriax.
Total occurrences of each CPV in copulative, verbal and impersonal constructions, and their co-occurrence with a dative argument in each construction. Data on copulative and verbal constructions are restricted to feminine and plural inflections of the CPV. Data on margish are restricted to instances with a dative argument.
CPV | nire ‘look’ |
nishma ‘sound’ |
meriax ‘smell’ |
margish le- ‘feel to’ |
---|---|---|---|---|
Copulative | 29,281 | 5,026 | 9 | 217 |
↳ with dative | (6,561) | (723) | (4) | (217) |
Verbal | 8,616 | 1,684 | 217 | 54 |
↳ with dative | (219) | (69) | (8) | (54) |
Impersonal | 53,406 | 1,357 | 5 | 83 |
↳ with dative | (14,781) | (140) | (0) | (83) |
The distribution of each CPV’s occurrences in copulative and verbal constructions, with and without a dative argument, are visualized in Figure 1. Copulative constructions are considerably more frequent than verbal constructions for nire ‘look’ (∼3:1), nishma ‘sound’ (∼3:1) and margish ‘feel’ (∼4:1). The opposite is true for meriax ‘smell’ (∼1:24). A series of Fisher’s exact tests, with Bonferroni corrections for multiple comparisons, reveals that the distribution of constructions differs significantly between meriax and each of nire (p < 0.001), nishma (p < 0.001), and margish (p < 0.001).

Distribution of CPVs in copulative and verbal constructions. The darker shading represents instances with a dative argument.
Across verbs, co-occurrence with a dative argument is considerably higher in the copulative construction (between 14.4 % and 44.4 %) than in the verbal construction (between 2.5 % and 4.1 %). A series of Fisher’s exact tests, with Bonferroni corrections for multiple comparisons, reveals that co-occurrence with a dative argument differs significantly between copulative and verbal constructions for each of nire ‘look’ (p < 0.001), nishma ‘sound’ (p < 0.001), and meriax ‘smell’ (p = 0.002).
Impersonal constructions are most frequent for nire ‘look’ (58.5 %), followed by margish ‘feel’ (23.4 %) and nishma ‘sound’ (16.8 %), and finally meriax ‘smell’ (2.2 %). Co-occurrence with a dative argument in the impersonal construction is highest for nire (27.7 %), followed by nishma (10.3 %) and finally meriax (0.0 %).
Next, I employ the exploratory technique of Distinctive Collexeme Analysis (Gries and Stefanowitsch 2004) to identify further differences between copulative and verbal constructions. Distinctive Collexeme Analysis is a method of quantifying the attraction between a lexeme and a construction, in contrast to another construction. Unlike traditional collocational analyses, it focuses on lexemes occurring in particular slots within a construction, rather than all words within a given span.
Here I conduct Distinctive Collexeme Analyses on two slots in the copulative and verbal constructions: the complement and the subject. Due to the vast differences in frequency, I conduct separate analyses for each of the four CPVs. The analyses are performed using Gries’ (2014) R script. In each case, the results indicate which lexemes are attracted to the relevant slot in each of the two constructions, and to what extent, expressed in a measure termed collostructional strength.[9]
The complete set of results of all eight Distinctive Collexeme Analyses, comprising a total of 6495 lexeme/verb combinations, is available online at https://osf.io/g7kw6/. Below I present side by side comparisons of the top 5 complements (Tables 2–5) and the top 5 subjects (Tables 6–9) attracted to each of the two constructions, for each of the four CPVs. These comparisons reveal striking differences between the copulative and verbal constructions, consistent across the four verbs. Each table shows observed and expected frequencies with both constructions, as well as collostructional strength with the preferred construction. For example, the top row of Table 2 shows that the complements of nire ‘look’ most strongly attracted to the copulative and verbal constructions are hegyoni ‘logical’ and nehedar ‘terrific’, respectively. The observed frequencies of hegyoni are 566 in the copulative construction and 9 in the verbal construction, whereas its expected frequencies (i.e., if it occurred in either construction randomly) are 444.27 and 130.73, respectively. Its collostructional strength with the copulative construction is 50.41 (representing a p-value under 10−50).
Top 5 complements of nire ‘look’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
hegyoni ‘logical’ | 566 (444.27) | 9 (130.73) | 50.41 | nehedar ‘terrific’ | 27 (462.04) | 571 (135.96) | ∞ |
mat’im ‘fitting’ | 493 (384.01) | 4 (112.99) | 48.78 | tov ‘good’ |
324 (2940.69) | 3,482 (865.31) | ∞ |
xaser ‘lacking’ |
471 (366.23) | 3 (107.77) | 47.80 | axer(et) ‘different’ | 273 (1355.22) | 1,481 (398.78) | ∞ |
pashut ‘simple’ | 481 (374.73) | 4 (110.27) | 47.46 | metsuyan ‘excellent’ | 53 (549.35) | 658 (161.65) | ∞ |
raxok ‘distant’ |
460 (360.05) | 6 (105.95) | 42.56 | nifla ‘wonderful’ | 23 (413.37) | 512 (121.63) | 296.90 |
Top 5 complements of nishma ‘sound’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
hegyoni ‘logical’ | 385 (289.88) | 2 (97.12) | 46.27 | tov ‘good’ |
57 (576.01) | 712 (192.99) | ∞ |
mukar ‘familiar’ | 193 (149.81) | 7 (50.19) | 16.34 | metsuyan ‘excellent’ | 18 (168.53) | 207 (56.47) | 104.40 |
mufrax ‘unfounded’ | 130 (98.12) | 1 (32.88) | 14.96 | nehedar ‘terrific’ | 5 (106.36) | 137 (35.64) | 76.04 |
meanyen ‘interesting’ | 114 (86.14) | 1 (28.86) | 12.97 | axer(et) ‘different’ | 32 (109.36) | 114 (36.64) | 41.23 |
pashut ‘simple’ |
98 (73.41) | 0 (24.59) | 12.40 | nifla ‘wonderful’ | 12 (56.18) | 63 (18.82) | 26.22 |
Top 5 complements of meriax ‘smell’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
amiti ‘real’ |
1 (0.04) | 0 (0.96) | 1.40 | tov ‘good’ |
0 (4.70) | 118 (113.30) | 2.96 |
muxan ‘ready’ |
1 (0.04) | 0 (0.96) | 1.40 | ra ‘bad’ |
0 (1.19) | 30 (28.81) | 0.57 |
mutslax ‘successful’ |
1 (0.04) | 0 (0.96) | 1.40 | nifla ‘wonderful’ | 0 (0.96) | 24 (23.04) | 0.45 |
mefukpak ‘dubious’ | 1 (0.04) | 0 (0.96) | 1.40 | nehedar ‘terrific’ | 0 (0.44) | 11 (10.56) | 0.20 |
naki ‘clean’ |
1 (0.04) | 0 (0.96) | 1.40 | axer(et) ‘different’ | 0 (0.24) | 6 (5.76) | 0.11 |
Top 5 complements of margish ‘feel’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Complement | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
amiti ‘real’ |
6 (4.80) | 0 (1.20) | 0.59 | tov ‘good’ |
1 (15.21) | 18 (3.79) | 12.53 |
zar ‘unfamiliar’ | 5 (4.00) | 0 (1.00) | 0.49 | naxon ‘correct’ |
17 (24.82) | 14 (6.18) | 3.23 |
gadol ‘large’ |
5 (4.00) | 0 (1.00) | 0.49 | muzar ‘strange’ |
2 (6.41) | 6 (1.59) | 3.00 |
kaved ‘heavy’ |
5 (4.00) | 0 (1.00) | 0.49 | axer(et) ‘different’ | 0 (2.40) | 3 (0.60) | 2.12 |
xashuv ‘important’ | 4 (3.20) | 0 (1.00) | 0.39 | nifla ‘wonderful’ | 1 (2.40) | 2 (0.60) | 0.99 |
Top 5 subjects of nire ‘look’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
derex ‘way’ |
153 (126.36) | 2 (28.64) | 11.02 | davar ‘thing’ | 679 (912.23) | 440 (206.77) | 65.19 |
she’ela ‘question’ | 82 (66.85) | 0 (15.15) | 7.30 | baxur ‘young person’ |
20 (53.80) | 46 (12.20) | 18.98 |
tshuva ‘answer’ | 62 (50.54) | 0 (11.46) | 5.51 | kvutsa ‘group’ | 29 (59.51) | 44 (13.49) | 14.59 |
matara ‘goal’ | 49 (39.95) | 0 (9.05) | 4.36 | ish ‘person’ |
236 (293.48) | 124 (66.52) | 12.68 |
nekuda ‘point’ | 60 (49.73) | 1 (11.27) | 4.25 | xayim ‘life’ | 217 (259.24) | 101 (58.76) | 8.23 |
Top 5 subjects of nishma ‘sound’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
davar ‘thing’ | 203 (181.27) | 40 (61.73) | 3.53 | (kli) neshifa ‘wind instrument’ | 4 (10.44) | 10 (3.56) | 3.42 |
she’ela ‘question’ | 26 (19.39) | 0 (6.61) | 3.33 | muzika ‘music’ |
23 (32.82) | 21 (11.18) | 2.99 |
safa ‘language’ | 12 (8.95) | 0 (3.05) | 1.53 | oznit ‘earphone’ |
0 (3.73) | 5 (1.27) | 2.98 |
tshuva ‘answer’ | 15 (11.94) | 1 (4.06) | 1.23 | ma’arexet ‘system’ |
3 (8.21) | 8 (2.79) | 2.89 |
tsura ‘shape’ |
9 (6.71) | 0 (2.29) | 1.15 | tof ‘drum’ |
6 (11.94) | 10 (4.06) | 2.74 |
Top 5 subjects of meriax ‘smell’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
sipur ‘story’ |
1 (0.20) | 0 (0.80) | 0.70 | ish ‘person’ |
0 (0.60) | 3 (2.40) | 0.30 |
brauni ‘brownie’ | 1 (0.20) | 0 (0.80) | 0.70 | xomer ‘material’ |
0 (0.40) | 2 (1.60) | 0.20 |
bira ‘beer’ |
1 (0.20) | 0 (0.80) | 0.70 | mutsar ‘product’ | 0 (0.40) | 2 (1.60) | 0.20 |
dmut ‘character’ | 1 (0.20) | 0 (0.80) | 0.70 | xeder ‘room’ |
0 (0.20) | 1 (0.80) | 0.10 |
kokteyl ‘cocktail’ | 1 (0.20) | 0 (0.80) | 0.70 | netax ‘chunk’ |
0 (0.20) | 1 (0.80) | 0.10 |
Top 5 subjects of margish ‘feel’ in copulative and verbal constructions.
Preference for copulative construction | Preference for verbal construction | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength | Subject | Copula. obs. (exp.) | Verbal obs. (exp.) | Collostr. strength |
xayim ‘life’ | 3 (2.37) | 0 (0.63) | 0.31 | xavaya ‘experience’ | 0 (0.79) | 1 (0.21) | 0.68 |
derex ‘way’ | 2 (1.58) | 0 (0.42) | 0.21 | xelbon ‘protein’ |
0 (0.79) | 1 (0.21) | 0.68 |
she’ela ‘question’ |
2 (1.58) | 0 (0.42) | 0.21 | xalal ‘space’ |
0 (0.79) | 1 (0.21) | 0.68 |
ish ‘person’ | 2 (1.58) | 0 (0.42) | 0.21 | sadna ‘workshop’ |
0 (0.79) | 1 (0.21) | 0.68 |
yad ‘hand’ |
2 (1.58) | 0 (0.42) | 0.21 | rexiva ‘riding’ |
0 (0.79) | 1 (0.21) | 0.68 |
As Table 2 shows, complements of nire ‘look’ attracted to the verbal construction are all subjective in some way (see Section 3.2), and are also virtually unrestricted in terms of what they can be predicated of; any object can be terrific, good, different, etc., whether it’s concrete or abstract, animate or inanimate, perceivable or non-perceivable. On the other hand, complements attracted to the copulative construction are not necessarily subjective, and some can only be predicated of specific classes of objects, e.g., hegyoni ‘logical’ for abstract ideas and raxok ‘far’ for physical locations. Complements that can only be predicated of specific classes of objects are shaded in gray in Tables 2–5.
In addition, Table 2 shows that the observed frequencies of complements attracted to the verbal construction are higher than those of complements attracted to the copulative construction, despite the verbal construction being overall less frequent (see Table 1). This indicates that a relatively small number of complements account for a considerable proportion of all verbal constructions. Indeed, tov ‘good’ alone accounts for 40.4 % of verbal constructions with nire ‘look’, and the top 5 complements taken together account for 77.8 %. In stark contrast, no single complement of nire accounts for even 2 % of copulative constructions.
Turning to complements of the other CPVs, the exact same patterns emerge; see Tables 3–5 for nishma ‘sound’, meriax ‘smell’ and margish ‘feel’, respectively. Complements attracted to the verbal construction are all subjective and, with the exception of naxon ‘correct’, can be predicated of anything. Moreover, these complements are extremely uniform, both within each verb – with very few complements accounting for considerable proportions of all verbal constructions; and across verbs – with the same 8 predicates recurring as the top 5 complements of all 4 CPVs. In comparison, complements attracted to the copulative construction are more varied both within and across verbs, with only 3 predicates recurring among the top 5 complements of the 4 CPVs. Again, many of these complements are not subjective, and many can only be predicated of specific classes of objects, e.g., mufrax ‘unfounded’ for abstract ideas and naki ‘clean’ for physical objects.
The top 5 subjects attracted to each of the copulative and verbal constructions, for each of the four CPVs, are presented in Tables 6–9. As Table 6 shows, all but one of the subjects of nire ‘look’ attracted to the verbal construction denote objects which can be directly perceived via vision, e.g., baxur ‘young person’. In contrast, subjects attracted to the copulative construction are just as likely to denote objects which cannot be perceived in the same way, e.g., she’ela ‘question’. Objects not perceivable through the relevant sensory modality are shaded in gray in Tables 6–9. It should be noted that davar ‘thing’, ish ‘person’ and xayim ‘life’ are attracted to the verbal construction despite having more occurrences in the copulative construction. As high as their observed frequencies in the copulative construction are, they are nevertheless lower than their expected frequencies, and vice versa for the verbal construction.
Data for the other CPVs again match the pattern observed with nire ‘look’; see Tables 7–9 for nishma ‘sound’, meriax ‘smell’ and margish ‘feel’, respectively. In fact, all of the subjects attracted to the verbal construction denote objects directly perceivable through the relevant sensory modality: hearing, smell, or bodily experience. In contrast, several subjects attracted to the copulative construction denote objects which cannot be perceived in the same way, e.g., tsura ‘shape’ via hearing, sipur ‘story’ via smell, and she’ela ‘question’ via touch. It may also be noted that, as Table 7 shows, subjects of nishma attracted to the verbal construction tend to denote musical instruments and audio devices, e.g., (kli) neshifa ‘wind instrument’ and oznit ‘earphone’, whereas subjects attracted to the copulative construction tend to denote linguistic objects, e.g., safa ‘language’.
3.2 Discussion
Summarizing the corpus findings detailed above, nire ‘look’, nishma ‘sound’ and margish ‘feel’ all occur in copulative constructions more frequently than in verbal constructions, whereas meriax ‘smell’ predominantly occurs in verbal constructions. Additionally, nire stands out for frequently occurring in impersonal constructions, which are relatively rare for the other CPVs. Across verbs, copulative and impersonal constructions take dative arguments more frequently than verbal constructions. Complements in verbal constructions are uniform, subjective and can be predicated over anything, whereas complements in copulative constructions are more varied, and more likely to be non-subjective and narrower in terms of what they can be predicated over. Subjects in verbal constructions tend to denote perceivable objects, whereas in copulative constructions they can denote non-perceivable objects.
All in all, the corpus data strongly suggest that the verbal and copulative constructions map to attributary and parenthetical meanings, respectively. Recall that on the attributary meaning, CPVs attribute a property to (a perceptual impression of) an object. This requires an object with a relevant perceptual impression, along with a property applicable to that impression (e.g., Petersen and Gamerschlag 2014). Verbal constructions have parallel requirements, in that their subjects denote perceivable stimuli, and their complements can be predicated of perceptual impressions (since they can be predicated of anything). Moreover, their complements are predominantly subjective, in accordance with previous observations that attributary uses tend to be value judgments (Poortvliet 2018; Rogers 1974; Usoniene 2000; Viberg 2019; Whitt 2009, 2011). The idea that verbal constructions map to attributary meanings also aligns with previous suggestions that complements in attributary uses behave like, have evolved from, or structurally are, adverbs (Gisborne 2010; Postal 1971; Taniguchi 1997).
In addition, we may consider Gisborne’s (2010) diagnostic for identifying the attributary meaning: the impossibility of the continuation but (it) isn’t really. Hebrew verbal constructions are indeed unacceptable with such a continuation, which can be explained by grammatical constraints on ellipsis. Thus, sentences like (9) are ruled out because the elided material can be neither an adverb – which would be missing a verb, nor an adjective – which would be missing an antecedent. Contrast this with the copulative construction in (10), which allows the continuation because the elided adjective has an antecedent.
*raxel | niret | muzar, | aval | be’etsem | hi | lo |
|
/ |
Rachel | looks.fsg | weirdly, | but | actually | she | not | weirdly | /weird.fsg |
‘Rachel looks weird, but isn’t really.’ |
raxel | niret | muzara, | aval | be’etsem | hi | lo |
|
Rachel | looks.fsg | weird.fsg, | but | actually | she | not | weird.fsg |
‘Rachel looks weird, but isn’t really.’ |
On the parenthetical meaning, CPVs take a proposition as an argument. If we assume that this proposition may be formed by predicating the verb’s complement over its subject, then the two are only restricted in that the complement must be applicable to the subject, and, possibly, in that the complement must be inferable from the relevant sensory modality (Petersen and Gamerschlag 2014). Copulative constructions show a similar permissiveness, taking subjects which denote stimuli not perceivable through the relevant sense, or at all, as well as complements which cannot be predicated of physical objects or perceptual impressions thereof. The diversity of complements across CPVs may reflect how different properties are inferable from different senses, and the overall paucity of copulative constructions with meriax ‘smell’ may reflect how relatively few properties are inferable from smell, at least for Hebrew speakers.
At this point, we might consider existing analyses of the two constructions. A typical account of the attributary meaning is Petersen and Gamerschlag’s (2014) frame-theoretic analysis (for an analysis along the same lines in model-theoretic semantics, see Muñoz 2019). In their analysis, each CPV specifies an attribute (e.g., sound, taste) of its subject’s denotation, and the CPV’s complement assigns a value to that attribute (e.g., sound: high, taste: bitter). Thus, a felicitous attributary use must satisfy two constraints: the attribute specified by the verb must be appropriate for the subject’s denotation, and the value assigned by the complement must be appropriate for that attribute. The former blocks attributary uses with subjects denoting stimuli which are not perceivable via the relevant perceptual modality (e.g., #the music looks X, #the dish sounds Y), and the latter blocks attributary uses with complements which cannot be predicated of relevant perceptual impressions (e.g., #X looks logical, #Y sounds blue).
However, if we apply Petersen and Gamerschlag’s (2014) analysis to the Hebrew verbal construction, we over-generate which complements the construction takes. If the construction simply requires a complement which can be predicated of the relevant perceptual impression, why is it that complements are overwhelmingly subjective? Granted, some predicates might be ruled out because they have no adverbial form; this could explain why there are no color terms among the complements of the verbal construction, for instance. But there are predicates in Hebrew which can be predicated of perceptual impressions, and do occur as adverbs, yet never occur in the verbal construction; see (11)–(13).
raxel | shara | xazak | /xalash | /gavoha | /namux. |
Rachel | sings.fsg | strongly | /weakly | /high | /low |
‘Rachel sings loudly/softly/with a high/low-pitched voice.’ |
*raxel | nishma’at | xazak | /xalash | /gavoha | /namux. |
Rachel | sounds.fsg | strongly | /weakly | /high | /low |
‘Rachel sounds loud/soft/high-pitched/low-pitched.’ |
ha-menora | meira | xazak | /xalash. |
the-lamp | shines.fsg | strongly | /weakly |
‘The lamp shines brightly/softly.’ |
*ha-menora | niret | xazak | /xalash. |
the-lamp | looks.fsg | strongly | /weakly |
‘The lamp looks bright/soft.’ |
ha-mexonit | nosa’at | xalak. |
the-car | drives.fsg | smoothly |
‘The car handles smoothly.’ |
*ha-mexonit | margisha | xalak. |
the-car | feels.fsg | smoothly |
‘The car feels smooth.’ |
Before we proceed, we should clarify what it means for a predicate to be subjective. This issue has received increasing attention in the past two decades, but remains thorny from both an empirical and a theoretical perspective (e.g., Kennedy 2013; Lasersohn 2005; McNally and Stojanoivc 2017). The most widespread diagnostic for identifying subjective predicates is whether they give rise to faultless disagreement, the intuition that speakers can disagree about certain propositions, e.g., whether something is tasty, without any one of them being objectively wrong (Kölbel 2004). However, experimental evidence shows that faultless disagreement arises to different extents for different predicates (Solt 2018) and depends on social consensus as much as on predicate choice (Kaiser and Rudin 2020). Moreover, faultless disagreement arises from at least three different sources: dimensional vagueness, multidimensionality, and judge-dependence (Kennedy 2013; McNally and Stojanovic 2017; Solt 2018).
Dimensional predicates such as strong and high may allow faultless disagreement due to vague standards. For instance, speakers might disagree about whether or not Rachel is strong, due to having different standards for what counts as strong in context. Notably, faultless disagreement disappears when these predicates occur in comparative and superlative constructions, e.g., Rachel is stronger than Adam.
Multidimensional predicates such as smart and healthy allow faultless disagreement by involving multiple criteria which can be used to determine whether, and to what degree, an object has the property in question. For instance, speakers might disagree about whether Rachel is healthier than Adam, due to having different considerations in determining how healthy someone is, e.g., their blood pressure, immune system, etc. Multidimensional predicates can be identified with phrases which explicitly target their dimensions, e.g., healthy with respect to X (Sassoon 2013).
Judge-dependent predicates such as fun and tasty give rise to faultless disagreement by involving a judgment regarding taste, value, etc. For instance, speakers might disagree about whether Rachel is more fun than Adam, because the degree to which something is fun is a matter of personal judgment rather than fact. Judge-dependent predicates can often – though not always – be identified by taking an optional argument representing the judge, e.g., fun for X (Lasersohn 2005; McNally and Stojanovic 2017).
For present purposes, it is clear that dimensional vagueness alone does not license complements in the verbal construction. As the examples in (11a)–(13a) above show, the dimensional complements xazak ‘strong’, xalash ‘weak’, gavoha ‘high’, namux ‘low’, and xalak ‘smooth’, are not acceptable in the verbal construction, even in non-comparative forms. As for multidimensionality and judge-dependence, most of the predicates attracted to the complement slot of the verbal construction are both multidimensional and judge-dependent (tov ‘good’, nehedar ‘terrific’, etc.). But are either of these a necessary or sufficient condition for complements in the verbal construction? Paradigmatic multidimensional predicates which are not judge-dependent, xaxam ‘smart’ and bari ‘healthy’, and likewise paradigmatic judge-dependent predicates which are not multidimensional, kef ‘fun’ and taim ‘tasty’, are ruled out for independent reasons – they have no adverbial form, or cannot be predicated of relevant perceptual impressions. There are, however, multidimensional predicates which are not judge-dependent, and which are attracted to the verbal construction, most prominently axeret ‘different’ but also other (dis)similarity predicates such as dome ‘similar’ and shone ‘different’. In contrast, only one judge-dependent predicate which is not multidimensional – naxon ‘correct’ – is attracted to the verbal construction to a comparable extent, and only with the verb margish ‘feel’.
It appears, then, that the verbal construction attracts multidimensional predicates to its complement slot. To account for this, I propose that the CPV in the verbal construction interacts directly with the dimensions of its complement. That is, rather than specifying an attribute of its subject’s denotation, as suggested by Petersen and Gamerschlag (2014), the CPV restricts the interpretation of its complement to a subset of dimensions: visual dimensions for nire ‘look’, auditory dimensions for nishma ‘sound’, etc. This functions similarly to phrases which directly target a multidimensional predicate’s dimensions, e.g., with respect to X (Sassoon 2013; see also Alrenga 2010), such that (14a) is analyzed as equivalent to (14b). If the complement is not a multidimensional predicate, the CPV has no dimensions to target and composition fails; see (15a) and (15b). Likewise, if the resulting predicate – restricted to a specific subset of dimensions – cannot apply to the subject’s denotation, composition fails; see (16a) and (16b).
raxel | niret | muzar. |
Rachel | looks.fsg | weirdly |
‘Rachel looks weird.’ |
raxel | muzara | mi-bxinat | mare. |
Rachel | weird.fsg | from-aspect.of | look |
‘Rachel is weird with respect to looks.’ |
*ha-menora | niret | xazak. |
the-lamp | looks.fsg | strongly |
‘The lamp looks bright.’ |
ha-menora | xazaka | (*mi-bxinat | mare). |
the-lamp | strong.fsg | (from-aspect.of | look) |
‘The lamp is bright (with respect to looks).’ |
*ha-muzika | niret | muzar. |
the-music | looks.fsg | weirdly |
‘The music looks weird.’ |
ha-muzika | muzara | (*mi-bxinat | mare). |
the-music | weird.fsg | (from-aspect.of | look) |
‘The music is weird with respect to looks.’ |
We can see that the CPV restricts its complement to a subset of dimensions, and not to a single dimension, from the possibility of it co-occurring with another phrase targeting a predicate’s dimensions. Thus in (17a), the predicate niret muzar ‘look weird’ is restricted to visual dimensions but remains multidimensional, allowing the phrase mi-bxinat tseva ‘with respect to color’ to further restrict its interpretation to a single visual dimension, color. In contrast, (17b) with the phrase mi-bxinat ta’am ‘with respect to flavor’ is unacceptable, because the subset of dimensions which niret muzar ‘look weird’ is restricted to, does not include the dimension of flavor.
ha-uga | niret | muzar | mi-bxinat | tseva. |
the-cake | looks.fsg | weirdly | from-aspect.of | color |
‘The cake looks weird with respect to color.’ |
*ha-uga | niret | muzar | mi-bxinat | ta’am. |
the-cake | looks.fsg | weirdly | from-aspect.of | flavor |
‘The cake looks weird with respect to flavor.’ |
The present proposal explains why CPVs in the verbal construction so rarely co-occur with a dative argument in the corpus (between 2.5 % and 4.1 %). Unlike the copulative and impersonal constructions (see below), the verbal construction does not actually have a semantic role for the dative argument to fill (see Gisborne 2010). In the few cases where the CPV does take a dative argument, it likely fills the judge role required by a judge-dependent complement, e.g., tov ‘good’, ra ‘bad’, which licenses a dative argument on its own.
Moving on to the copulative construction, the CPV appears to function as a raising verb: its subject and complement combine to form a proposition, which the CPV takes as an argument and modifies (see also Avineri 2021, who analyzes the complement in this construction as a small clause). The present finding that the copulative construction attracts abstract subjects lends credence to analyses which don’t require the subject to be a source of evidence (Gisborne 2010; cf. Muñoz 2019). The remaining question is whether CPVs in the copulative and impersonal constructions are semantically equivalent. Particularly, does the CPV in each construction have an evidential meaning, an epistemic modal meaning, or both?
Note that I use the term evidentiality to refer to any encoding of information about the source or type of evidence for a proposition, whether or not it is grammaticized. I distinguish a priori between evidentiality and epistemic modality, which refers to the encoding of an individual’s beliefs or knowledge. It’s possible, however, for an expression to encode both evidential and epistemic meaning, and in fact, Matthewson (2012) explicitly claims that every expression which encodes one also encodes the other. Even if an expression only encodes evidential meaning, its use may convey epistemic information via pragmatic inference, and vice versa (Degen et al. 2019). This makes it difficult to tease apart evidential and epistemic meaning within corpus data. Thus, to test whether the copulative and impersonal constructions differ in encoding evidential and epistemic meaning, I conducted a preference experiment.
3.3 Preference experiment
The experiment was designed to test whether copulative and impersonal constructions differ in encoding evidential and epistemic meanings. I restricted the experiment to nire ‘look’ and nishma ‘sound’, since meriax ‘smell’ and margish ‘feel’ occurred in impersonal constructions very rarely in the corpus. The experiment relied on contradictions to the evidential and epistemic meanings presumably encoded by the CPV, specifically direct evidence of an object (e.g., Landau 2011) and compatibility with the speaker’s knowledge (e.g., Hansen and Markman 2005). I assumed that, if one construction encoded evidential meaning but the other did not, then the latter would be preferred in contexts contradicting the evidential meaning. Likewise, if one construction encoded epistemic meaning but the other did not, then the latter would be preferred in contexts contradicting the epistemic meaning.
The experiment consisted of categorical preference judgments. In each trial, participants were presented with a short context introducing two speakers discussing an object, and an incomplete sentence by one of the speakers. Participants were asked to indicate which of two possible continuations would be better, that is, would complete the speaker’s sentence in a way that sounds more natural, logical and reasonable. Participants could also choose to indicate that neither continuation was better than the other.
In every trial, the presented incomplete sentence contradicted either the evidential or the epistemic meaning presumably encoded by the CPV. For the evidential meaning, the incomplete sentence asserted that the speaker had no direct evidence of the object under discussion, of the type associated with the CPV (seeing for nire ‘look’, hearing for nishma ‘sound’). For the epistemic meaning, the incomplete sentence asserted that the speaker had prior knowledge contradicting the proposition argument of the CPV. In the critical trials, the two continuations presented to participants were one copulative and one impersonal construction, both with the same CPV. To ensure that a contradiction arises, all continuations included a 1st person dative argument. Examples of critical trials, translated from Hebrew, are given in (18) and (19) (in the original Hebrew, the dative argument immediately follows the CPV in both constructions, and there is no expletive subject in the impersonal construction). The full list of materials is available online at https://osf.io/g7kw6/.
Noa is consulting with Hila about Professor Sabag’s course. | |
Hila: “I’ve never heard her, but… | (No direct evidence) |
… she sounds nice to me.” | (Copulative) |
… it sounds to me that she’s nice.” | (Impersonal) |
Dvir and Ehud are gossiping about the lecturer in Statistics for Historians. | |
Dvir: “I know that she’s young, but… | (Prior knowledge) |
… she sounds old to me.” | (Copulative) |
… it sounds to me that she’s old.” | (Impersonal) |
A total of 32 critical trials were created, half with no direct evidence, and half with prior knowledge. Half of each included nire ‘look’ in their continuations, and the other half included nishma ‘sound’. 16 filler trials were also created, in which the two continuations presented to participants were instances of the same construction, with two different CPVs. The experiment was created in Google Forms, and participants were recruited via social media. 41 native speakers of Hebrew volunteered to participate. Before completing the experiment, participants saw two example trials which did not include CPVs, and were advised that there were no right or wrong answers. Each participant then saw all 48 trials, in a pseudo-random order.
The results of the preference experiment are presented in Figure 2. In trials where the speaker had prior knowledge contradicting the proposition argument of the CPV, participants consistently preferred the copulative construction, both with nire ‘look’ (76.8 %) and with nishma ‘sound’ (80.5 %). In trials where the speaker had no direct evidence of the object in question, speaker preferences depended on the CPV in the available continuations. With nire, speakers generally preferred the impersonal construction (67.8 %), but with nishma, there was no preference for either construction (35.1 % copulative, 30.5 % impersonal, 34.5 % no preference).

Results of the preference experiment. Participants chose whether the copulative or impersonal construction was better in trials where the speaker had prior knowledge contradicting the proposition argument of the CPV, and in trials where the speaker had no direct evidence of the object in question.
These results strongly suggest that CPVs encode compatibility with the speaker’s beliefs – an epistemic modal meaning – in the impersonal construction, but not in the copulative construction. The impersonal construction is consistently dispreferred when the speaker’s knowledge contradicts the CPV’s proposition argument, similarly to how epistemic might or must are unacceptable when their prejacent contradicts the speaker’s knowledge.
In contrast, the results suggest that nire ‘look’ encodes direct evidence of the subject – evidential meaning – in the copulative construction, but not in the impersonal construction. The copulative construction is consistently dispreferred when the speaker has no direct visual evidence of the object in question, regardless of whether they believe that evidence. Note that direct evidence of the subject is a default assumption rather than a logical entailment, given the corpus finding that the copulative construction attracts abstract subjects which cannot be seen (e.g., she’ela ‘question’, matara ‘goal’). Additionally, the results do not preclude the impersonal construction from encoding a weaker evidential meaning, e.g., visual evidence from an unspecified source.
The picture is not as clear-cut for nishma ‘sound’. Since there was no preference for either construction in trials where the speaker had no auditory evidence of the object in question, it’s possible that both constructions were acceptable, or that both constructions were unacceptable. I hypothesize that participants found both constructions acceptable, not because nishma lacks evidential meaning, but because it allows indirect reported evidence in addition to direct auditory evidence (see also Gisborne 2010; Landau 2011; Viberg 2019).
These results raise a possible explanation for why the impersonal construction occurs in the corpus almost exclusively with nire ‘look’. If the meaning of the impersonal construction is primarily epistemic rather than evidential, it essentially doesn’t matter which CPV is used. Thus nire, as the most frequent CPV to begin with, might be used by default.
4 Conclusions
In this article I investigated Hebrew CPVs occurring in the verbal, copulative and impersonal constructions. The alternation between the verbal and copulative constructions has not been discussed in previous literature, although it appears in at least one language other than Hebrew (see fn.3). I presented corpus data suggesting that the formal distinction between the verbal and copulative constructions corresponds to the semantic distinction between attributary and parenthetical meanings of CPVs.
The corpus data additionally show that CPVs in the verbal construction attract subjective multidimensional predicates. This weakens existing accounts of the attributary meaning, which predict that it can take any complement that can be predicated over the relevant type of perceptual impression (Gisborne 2010; Muñoz 2019; Petersen and Gamerschlag 2014). I therefore proposed that CPVs in the verbal construction should be given a different analysis, one which interacts directly with the dimensions of the complement, along the lines of Alrenga (2010) and Sassoon (2013). Note that this proposal is compatible with the observation that CPVs may also have an attributary meaning with comparative complements, since comparative phrases too are multidimensional (Alrenga 2010).
I would go further and suggest that in languages other than Hebrew, attributary uses may be more restricted than previously assumed, in ways similar to the Hebrew verbal construction. Specifically, I believe we should reexamine cases where CPVs take complements associated with a single sensory modality, e.g., look oblong, sound loud, feel sticky, which are ascribed attributary meanings by Gisborne (2010) and Petersen and Gamerschlag (2014). Yet Gisborne’s (2010) own diagnostic for identifying the attributary meaning – the impossibility of the continuation but (it) isn’t really – suggests that such examples can in fact have a parenthetical meaning; see (20).
It looks oblong, but we know the moon is really round. [g] |
a. *really* good drummer can balance their playing so that it sounds loud but isn’t . [g] |
Playfoam is a great sensory moulding material which feels sticky but isn’t ! [g] |
Moreover, there is no apparent communicative function for an attributary use of a CPV taking a complement associated with a single sense. To borrow Petersen and Gamerschlag’s (2014) terminology, if the phrase sound loud simply assigned a value to the sound attribute of the subject’s denotation, then it would be equivalent to the bare predicate loud, given that sound is the only attribute that loud can be assigned to in the first place. In other words, a CPV only makes a semantic contribution with a predicate that can in principle assign values to more than one attribute, i.e., a multidimensional predicate. It remains to be seen whether attributary uses in other languages actually follow this logic, but if they do, we would expect them to predominantly take multidimensional complements, just like CPVs in the Hebrew verbal construction.[10]
Finally, I conducted a preference experiment comparing the semantics of the copulative and impersonal constructions. The results indicate that the copulative construction encodes a more specific evidential meaning than the impersonal construction, namely direct evidence of the CPV’s subject. The impersonal construction, conversely, encodes an epistemic modal meaning, namely compatibility of the proposition argument with the speaker’s knowledge. The former finding aligns with previous claims that the impersonal construction doesn’t specify a source of evidence (e.g., Landau 2011; Muñoz 2019), and the latter with Hansen and Markman’s (2005) suggestion that the impersonal construction can only refer to “likely reality” and not to “outward appearance”. More generally, these findings reinforce the need to maintain a distinction between the class of evidentials and the class of epistemic modals (cf. Matthewson 2012).
Funding source: Israel Science Foundation
Award Identifier / Grant number: 1196/12
Award Identifier / Grant number: 1398/20
Acknowledgments
I thank Mira Ariel, Yeshayahu Shen, Bodo Winter, Klaus von Heusinger, the audience at the Tel Aviv University Thursday Interdisciplinary Colloquium, the editor and two anonymous reviewers, for helpful comments on this manuscript. All errors are my own.
-
Research funding: This research was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant no. 1398/20 to Mira Ariel and grant no. 1196/12 to Yeshayahu Shen).
References
Albelda Marco, Marta & Marlies Jansegers. 2019. From visual perception to evidentiality: A functional empirical approach to se ve que in Spanish. Lingua 220. 76–97. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2019.01.005.Search in Google Scholar
Alrenga, Peter. 2010. Comparisons of similarity and difference. In Patricia Cabredo Hofherr & Ora Matushansky (eds.), Adjectives: Formal analyses in syntax and semantics, 155–186. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.10.1075/la.153.05alrSearch in Google Scholar
Anand, Pranav & Natasha Korotkova. 2018. Acquaintance content and obviation. In Uli Sauerland & Stephanie Solt (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, vol. 22, 55–72. Berlin: ZAS.10.21248/zaspil.60.2018.454Search in Google Scholar
Asudeh, Ash. 2002. Richard III. In Mary Andronis, Erin Debenport, Anne Pycha & Keiko Yoshimura (eds.), Papers from the 38th regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 31–46. Chicago, IL: Chicago Linguistic Society.Search in Google Scholar
Asudeh, Ash. 2004. Resumption as resource management. Stanford, CA: Stanford University dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
Asudeh, Ash & Ida Toivonen. 2012. Copy raising and perception. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 30(2). 321–380. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-012-9168-2.Search in Google Scholar
Avineri, Bar. 2021. Alternating smell in Modern Hebrew. In Łukasz Jędrzejowski & Przemysław Staniewski (eds.), The linguistics of olfaction, 305–342. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.10.1075/tsl.131.11aviSearch in Google Scholar
Degen, Judith, Andreas Trotzke, Gregory Scontras, Eva Wittenberg & Noah D. Goodman. 2019. Definitely, maybe: A new experimental paradigm for investigating the pragmatics of evidential devices across languages. Journal of Pragmatics 140. 33–48. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2018.11.015.Search in Google Scholar
Evans, Nicholas & David Wilkins. 2000. In the mind’s ear: The semantic extensions of perception verbs in Australian languages. Language 76(3). 546–592. https://doi.org/10.2307/417135.Search in Google Scholar
Fernández Jaén, Jose. 2015. The pseudo-copulative verbs verse and sentirse: Diachronic and synchronic aspects. In Elisa Barrajón López, José Luis Cifuentes Honrubia & Susana Rodríguez Rosique (eds.), Verb classes and aspect, 218–237. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.10.1075/ivitra.9.10ferSearch in Google Scholar
Fishman, Alon. 2022. The picture looks like my music sounds: Directional preferences in synesthetic metaphors in the absence of lexical factors. Language and Cognition 14(2). 208–227. https://doi.org/10.1017/langcog.2022.2.Search in Google Scholar
Gisborne, Nikolas. 2010. The event structure of perception verbs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577798.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul & Alan R. White. 1961. The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 35. 121–152. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristoteliansupp/35.1.121.Search in Google Scholar
Gries, Stefan Th. 2014. Coll.analysis 3.5. A script for R to compute perform collostructional analyses.Search in Google Scholar
Gries, Stefan Th & Anatol Stefanowitsch. 2004. Extending collostructional analysis: A corpus-based perspective on “alternations.” International Journal of Corpus Linguistics 9(1). 97–130. https://doi.org/10.1075/ijcl.9.1.06gri.Search in Google Scholar
Hansen, Mikkel B. & Ellen M. Markman. 2005. Appearance questions can be misleading: A discourse-based account of the appearance-reality problem. Cognitive Psychology 50(3). 233–263. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogpsych.2004.09.001.Search in Google Scholar
Ibarretxe-Antuñano, B. Iraide. 1999. Polysemy and metaphor in perception verbs: A cross-linguistic study. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
Jackendoff, Ray. 2007. Language, consciousness, culture: Essays on mental structure. Cambridge & London: The MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/4111.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Kaiser, Elsi. 2018. Effects of sensory modality on the interpretation of subjective adjectives: Comparing sight, smell and taste. Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 44. 99–114.Search in Google Scholar
Kaiser, Elsi & Deniz Rudin. 2020. When faultless disagreement is not so faultless: What widely-held opinions can tell us about subjective adjectives. Proceedings of the Linguistic Society of America 5(1). 698–707. https://doi.org/10.3765/plsa.v5i1.4757.Search in Google Scholar
Kennedy, Chris. 2013. Two sources of subjectivity: Qualitative assessment and dimensional uncertainty. Inquiry 56(2–3). 258–277. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2013.784483.Search in Google Scholar
Kilgarriff, Adam, Vít Baisa, Bušta Jan, Miloš Jakubíček, Vojtěch Kovář, Jan Michelfeit, Pavel Rychlý & Vít Suchomel. 2014. The Sketch Engine: Ten years on. Lexicography 1. 7–36. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40607-014-0009-9.Search in Google Scholar
Kölbel, Max. 2004. Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104(1). 53–73. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9264.t01-1-00003.Search in Google Scholar
Landau, Idan. 2011. Predication vs. aboutness in copy raising. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 29(3). 779–813. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-011-9134-4.Search in Google Scholar
Lasersohn, Peter. 1995. Sounds like like. Linguistic Analysis 25. 70–77.Search in Google Scholar
Lasersohn, Peter. 2005. Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy 28(6). 643–686. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-005-0596-x.Search in Google Scholar
Majid, Asifa, Seán G. Roberts, Ludy Cilissen, Karen Emmorey, Brenda Nicodemus, Lucinda O’Grady, Bencie Woll, Barbara LeLan, Hilário de Sousa, Brian L. Cansler, Shakila Shayan, Connie de Vos, Gunter Senft, N. J. Enfield, Rogayah A. Razak, Sebastian Fedden, Sylvia Tufvesson, Mark Dingemanse, Ozge Ozturk, Penelope Brown, Clair Hill, Olivier Le Geun, Vincent Hirtzel, Rik van Gijn, Mark A. Sicoli & Stephen C. Levinson. 2018. Differential coding of perception in the world’s languages. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 115(45). 11369–11376. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1720419115.Search in Google Scholar
Matthewson, Lisa. 2012. Evidence about evidentials: Where fieldwork meets theory. In Britta Stolterfoht & Sam Featherston (eds.), Empirical approaches to linguistic theory: Studies in meaning and structure (Studies in Generative Grammar 111), 85–114. Berlin & Boston: De Gruyter Mouton.10.1515/9781614510888.85Search in Google Scholar
McNally, Louise & Isidora Stojanovic. 2017. Aesthetic adjectives. In James O. Young (ed.), Semantics of aesthetic judgments, 17–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198714590.003.0002Search in Google Scholar
Muñoz, Patrick J. 2019. On tongues: The grammar of experiential evaluation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
Petersen, Wiebke & Thomas Gamerschlag. 2014. Why chocolate eggs can taste old but not oval: A frame-theoretic analysis of inferential evidentials. In Thomas Gamerschlag, Doris Gerland, Rainer Osswald & Wiebke Petersen (eds.), Frames and concept types: Applications in language and philosophy, 199–220. Dordrecht: Springer.10.1007/978-3-319-01541-5_9Search in Google Scholar
Poortvliet, Marjolein. 2018. Perception and predication: A synchronic and diachronic analysis of Dutch descriptive perception verbs as evidential copular verbs. Oxford: University of Oxford dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
Postal, Paul M. 1971. Cross-over phenomena. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Search in Google Scholar
Rogers, Andrew D.Jr. 1974. Physical perception verbs in English: A study in lexical relatedness. Los Angeles, CA: UCLA dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
Sassoon, Galit W. 2013. A typology of multidimensional adjectives. Journal of Semantics 30(3). 335–380. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs012.Search in Google Scholar
Solt, Stephanie. 2018. Multidimensionality, subjectivity and scales: Experimental evidence. In Elena Castroviejo, Louise McNally & Galit W. Sassoon (eds.), The Semantics of gradability, vagueness, and scale structure: Experimental perspectives (Language, Cognition, and Mind 4), 59–91. Cham: Springer.10.1007/978-3-319-77791-7_3Search in Google Scholar
Staniewski, Przemysław & Adam Gołębiowski. 2021. To what extent can source-based olfactory verbs be classified as copulas? In Łukasz Jędrzejowski & Przemysław Staniewski (eds.), The linguistics of olfaction, 403–448. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins.10.1075/tsl.131.14staSearch in Google Scholar
Taniguchi, Kazumi. 1997. On the semantics and development of copulative perception verbs in English: A cognitive perspective. English Linguistics 14. 270–299. https://doi.org/10.9793/elsj1984.14.270.Search in Google Scholar
Usoniene, Aurelia. 2000. On the modality of the English verbs of seeming. Belgian Journal of Linguistics 14(1). 185–205. https://doi.org/10.1075/bjl.14.11uso.Search in Google Scholar
Viberg, Åke. 1983. The verbs of perception: A typological study. Linguistics 21(1). 123–162. https://doi.org/10.1515/ling.1983.21.1.123.Search in Google Scholar
Viberg, Åke. 2019. Phenomenon-based perception verbs in Swedish from a typological and contrastive perspective. Syntaxe et Sémantique 20. 17–48. https://doi.org/10.3917/ss.020.0017.Search in Google Scholar
Whitt, Richard J. 2009. Auditory evidentiality in English and German: The case of perception verbs. Lingua 119. 1083–1095. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2008.11.001.Search in Google Scholar
Whitt, Richard J. 2010. Evidentiality and perception verbs in English and German. Oxford: Peter Lang.10.3726/978-3-0353-0306-3Search in Google Scholar
Whitt, Richard J. 2011. (Inter)Subjectivity and evidential perception verbs in English and German. Journal of Pragmatics 43. 347–360. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2010.07.015.Search in Google Scholar
Winter, Bodo. 2016. The sensory structure of the English lexicon. Merced, CA: UC Merced dissertation.Search in Google Scholar
© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Why we need a gradient approach to word order
- Spanish modal ellipsis is not null complement anaphora
- Revisiting areal and lexical diffusion: the case of Viennese Monophthongization in Austria’s traditional dialects
- Variation, gender and perception: the social meaning of Japanese linguistic variables
- Hebrew copulative perception verbs
- From their point of view: the article category as a hierarchically structured referent tracking system
- Prosodic words are the domain of emphasis spread: evidence from Northern Rural Jordanian Arabic
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Why we need a gradient approach to word order
- Spanish modal ellipsis is not null complement anaphora
- Revisiting areal and lexical diffusion: the case of Viennese Monophthongization in Austria’s traditional dialects
- Variation, gender and perception: the social meaning of Japanese linguistic variables
- Hebrew copulative perception verbs
- From their point of view: the article category as a hierarchically structured referent tracking system
- Prosodic words are the domain of emphasis spread: evidence from Northern Rural Jordanian Arabic