Home Organisation as Reflexive Structuration
Article Open Access

Organisation as Reflexive Structuration

  • Günther Ortmann , Jörg Sydow and Arnold Windeler ORCID logo EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: June 28, 2023
Become an author with De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

Our "Beacons of Organizational Sociology" series makes available, through first-time translations, texts that have shaped debates in organizational sociology in non-English-speaking countries, or presents reflections on such debates by established scholars. The first text in this series is a shortened English translation of the German article “Organisation als reflexive Strukturation” by Günther Ortmann, Jörg Sydow, and Arnold Windeler, published in 1997 in the highly influential book “Theorien der Organisation. Die Rückkehr der Gesellschaft” [Theories of Organization. The Return of Society]. The article applies Giddens’ social theory to organizational research. In elaborating on “the principle of reflexive organization,” the text provides a social-theoretically informed concept of organization that is of continuing relevance for organization research today. The publication can be classified as one of the decisive writings by the authors contributing to establishing organizational research based on structuration theory in the German-speaking world, informing many studies, e.g., on new organizational forms, innovation, and inter-organizational relations. The concise overview of the various existing studies in organization research using a structuration perspective at that time in the original manuscript is not part of this translation.

Original Citation

Ortmann, Günther, Jörg Sydow, and Arnold Windeler. 1997. “Organisation als reflexive Strukturation.” In Theorien der Organisation, edited by Günther Ortmann, Jörg Sydow and Klaus Türk, 315–354. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.

When we say ‛organisation,’ we are operating with a fundamental ambiguity. It can mean either the process of organising or the result of that process: the ‛organisedness’ of social action and subsequently a system of organised action. Trying to eliminate this ambiguity by regulating the language we use would not only be futile because it is far too deeply embedded in language―it would also be unwise. A better suggestion would be to grant language a presumption of wisdom and ask why it has so stubbornly preserved this ambiguity―and not only in German. Following this path, one soon hits upon that recursiveness of human action which lies in the fact that our action results in the production of precisely those structures that subsequently enable and restrict our further action. Giddens (1976, 1979, 1984) wanted to preserve this double meaning of producing and product explicitly under the heading of ‛structuration’, and his conception of the duality of structure dissolves the commonplace dualism of action and structure, their mere opposition, in the circular figure of recursiveness. Structures are the medium and the outcome of action. Even in organisations, they are initially only a ‛concomitant’ result―in the sense that they are an unintended and unreflected side effect of action. Often enough, we create structures without wanting to and without attending to them. But when the flash of reflection illuminates structuration as producing and product, when we pause and begin to ask questions (What is actually repeating? There does seem to be a pattern: What sort of pattern is it? How can we fix it? Isn’t there another way?) and to practise structuration in a reflexive way, then structuration becomes―in nuce―organisation. Organisation is structuration that has lost its naivety, its primordiality, its innocence: reflexive structuration.

This reflexive structuration finds its most pointed expression in the formality of modern organisation, in formal constitutions and procedures, which are of great importance in the coordination of action. The organisers, not least, hope that this will collectively secure and increase individual reflexivity and rationality. Whether this actually happens, and who benefits and who is burdened, is a subordinate question. Markets can also be the object of such organisational efforts―resulting, for example, in strategic business networks. Finally, even those more extensive modes of inter-organisational coordination of action that Hollingsworth calls governances are partly the result of reflexive structuration (cf. Braczyk 1997, who himself speaks of discursive coordination). However, the feature of formal constitution―such as rules of formal membership―is much more weakly developed in inter-organisational networks than in organisations.

The concept of organisation is ambiguous also because today it concerns a state of affairs that existed in the most diverse historical epochs and societies: When Ptahhotep, vizier of King Isesi, recorded the “best practices” of pyramid building on papyrus scrolls around 2700 BCE (Kieser 1993b, 63), this was the result of what we would today call reflection on the structuration of pyramid building, which resulted in the formulation of rules and regular practices. But organisation per se, sans phrase, is a modern concept that has only emerged in the course of what has been called ‛modernisation’ in sociology―the detachment of social practice from religion and tradition by means of rationalisation.[1] Only with this development does talk of ‛organisations as institutions’―usually referring to social systems called organisations―gain its historical substrate; and somehow these organisations have a conspicuous part in the genesis of capitalism (and vice versa, provocatively Türk 1995). The bearers of this reflection, however, are no longer just single people―subjects, personal actors, individuals―but, recursively enough, organised systems of science, administration and economy, to name but a few, or corporative actors in whose structures―rules and resources―the cumulative reflexive knowledge of modernity is stored; perhaps one could even say ‛inscribed’. In this latter case, we can also follow Ritsert (1981) in speaking of system reflexivity. While subject reflexivity refers to an individual’s self-reference in thinking and acting, without which reflexive structuration is unthinkable, system reflexivity in our context refers to a supra–individual, namely, organisational reflexivity: a movement back into itself beyond individuals and individual thinking and acting, in the course of which organisational knowledge is produced and inserted into new recursive loops of organisational action.[2]

1 Foundations of Structuration Theory: Organisation, Reflexivity and Recursiveness

In this view, organisations, conceived as systems of organised action or practices, are reproduced as a result of the―more or less purposive―actions of competent actors or “knowledgeable agents” (Giddens 1984). Such agents refer in their interactions to structures, to sets of rules and resources and to other structural features of their field of action, properties that are appended to the field of action by this structured action―rigid departmental boundaries, for example, or a rigid division of labour, a high failure rate in conventional mass production, discrimination against employees, asymmetrical income distribution, to name but a few. In drawing on these, actors thus reproduce these structures and structural properties―and entire social systems such as firms and inter-firm networks. Indeed, they often do this intentionally, though they are neither completely aware of nor able to fully control the consequences of their actions.

Organisations are characterised by organisational practices, by recurring forms of action practiced in organisations, and not merely by formal structures, structural properties or input-output relations or by communication or decision-making alone. Organisational structures only exist at all in the actions and practices of actors―and subsequently in their memories and expectations, in the form of a virtual order. In our view, organisations are those social systems within which action is directed and coordinated by means of reflection, specifically by means of reflection on their structuration. The formulation and establishment of rules and the provision of resources takes place in a reflected way, which is to say that when it comes to organisations, structuration is the result―although an only partially intended one―of reflection striving for expediency.

For Giddens (1984, 5), actors always act reflexively. This is to say that in their actions they refer more or less deliberately to their own past, present and anticipated future behaviour as well as to that of others and to the structures of the field of action. Yet we speak of organising only when this reflexivity pertains to the shaping of these structures; and we speak of organisations in the―modern―sense of organised social systems only when formality―formal constitution and regulation―is present as differentia specifica.

Following Giddens’ actor model (1984, 5), even the level of individual action involves the interplay of three layers of action that must always be considered:

  1. individual[3] and organisational forms of “reflexive monitoring” (“Does my action connect well with that of others? Did it work out that way? I have to do it differently next time! What now? What will the others do? Watch out, there’s someone coming from the right! Do I have to greet the person?”);

  2. the “rationalization” of action (when actors develop a commonsensical theoretical understanding of the reasons for their actions: ‛I did that (this way) because … ’);

  3. the conscious or unconscious “motivation” of action by a desire for wish fulfilment or fear avoidance. (However, for Giddens a major part of human action is not directly motivated. Much of what we do stems from “routine,” “habit”).

It is already evident here how familiar discourses in organisational research can dovetail: those on steering and control, those on organisational ideologies and those on motivation (cf. on such discourses, e.g. Staehle 1994).

For Giddens, however, actors never fully control the processes of social reproduction. Much is closed off to them, such that in many respects they act as competent actors on the basis of merely ‛practical’, implicit knowledge. They know how it is done, or perhaps better: they know how to do it, they are good at it, without being able to explain exactly how and why they (have to) do it. Furthermore, they act on unrecognised premises and thereby produce unintended consequences. The results especially of collective―for example, organisational―action often turn out differently than intended.

In doing what they do, competent actors refer recursively to structures, perpetuating them through this very action―even if they are not always left unchanged in the process. This is exactly what recursiveness means: the iterative application of an operation/transformation to its own result―in this case, the operation ‛structuring’ is applied to the result ‛structure’. In other words, recursiveness means that the output of an operation/transformation is reapplied as a new input to this same operation/transformation, which is precisely what happens to the structure reproduced in and by action: It is the (concomitant) result of action and enters into further action as its ‛medium’.[4] Structures therefore enable reflexively acting actors to act competently in interaction situations even as they constrain actors’ possibilities of action. Given the pervasiveness of views that focus one-sidedly on their restrictive character, we would like to emphasise this restricting and enabling aspect of social―as well as organisational―structures. We can go even further: Enabling is based on restriction. (Time-coordinated action, for example, is based on restrictions on action, such as those imposed on us by rules of punctuality, schedules etc.). Modern organisations are a special case only insofar as these restricting and enabling structures―rules and resources―are established reflexively and their fixation is attempted by means of formalisation. Formality here means first of all formal determination. The obligations, expectations, rights and resources specified in the formal structure refer―and this is another, the primary meaning of formality―not to concrete contents and situations, but to generalisable ‛cases’; not to concrete persons, but to positions (‛jobs’), departments, areas of expertise etc. and finally to the corporate entity itself (as a legal person, for example), in this sense establishing formal relations between positions/organisational units/organisations, but not concrete relations between persons. The fact that the latter relations are (supposed to be) formalised and formed in this way, however, points to the power dimension of formal organisation and to the way power can be expanded by its detachment from concrete persons (Coleman 1990). Indicated in the formal structure are also modes of attribution that permit one to punctuate the stream of action; to make out of the stream of practical intervention in the world delimited acts, which is to say actions; to break them down into ‘responsibilities’ of this or that department, into causes and effects, costs and benefits etc.; and to constitute the identity and boundaries of an organisation.[5]

Giddens distinguishes between three dimensions of the social that are initially only separable analytically: At the level of social structures, these dimensions are called signification, legitimation and domination. When referring to the corresponding action or interaction, they are called communication, sanction and power (Figure 1). As they interact, actors mediate the level of action with the level of structure by making the rules and resources under situational conditions into modalities of their action in ways specific to the situation and in accordance with their biographies and competences, which is to say in highly particular ways.

Figure 1: 
The dimensions of the duality of structure (Giddens 1984, 29).
Figure 1:

The dimensions of the duality of structure (Giddens 1984, 29).

When members of organisations communicate with each other, they refer reflexively and recursively to structural forms―rules in the sense of generalisable procedures―of signification, which they in this―always situational, particular―way make into modalities of their action. They exercise power in interactions by referring to organisational resources that they bring into the interaction sequence as means of power (facilities). They sanction by attributing their actions to norms and evaluating and judging the actions of others on the basis of norms that they derive from reflexive recourse to the ways and means of legitimation; in organisations, for example, they might refer to the practices of evaluation used for persons, performance, processes, buying and selling behaviours and so on. And in doing all this, the actors (re-)produce the organisational structures: the structure of signification, legitimation and domination―which is to say, the existing rules and resources.

Let us summarise: Following Giddens, the structures of social systems can be broken down analytically into two types of rules and two types of resources:

  1. Rules for the constitution of meaning (signification) establish what can be called the cognitive order of a social system or, in our case, of an organisation. For Giddens, this includes all those aspects related to the interpretation of the world as the foundation for action. In organisations, this refers, for example, to interpretative schemes, symbols, myths and so on. Even the sensual-aesthetic aspects of organisations, for instance, their architecture or, less concretely, the attractiveness of actions and objects of action, form part of this cognitive order (Ortmann et al. 1990, 31–35).

  2. Rules for sanctioning social action (legitimation) make up the normative order of an organisation. From examining the rise and fall of organisational culture as a possible object of reflexive structuration―that is, organisational design―it is apparent that feasible cognitive and normative orders are only the tip of the iceberg, also in organisations.

  3. Allocative resources enable actors to control material aspects of social situations such as the disposition of factors of production, goods produced or money.

  4. Authoritative resources, by contrast, permit the exercise of power over persons, for example, by determining workflows, schedules and pay.

We view Giddens’ structuration theory, which we have sketched above in outlining a few of its basic lines of reasoning, as a kind of socio-theoretical framework―some even speak of a meta-theory―for social science research. This framework needs to be supplemented by building blocks from theory of society and, in our case, organisational theory. To this we will now turn.[6]

2 Organisation as a Reflexive Form of Structuration

Hardly anyone would deny the enormous relevance of organisations for modern society (as, for example, the admittedly somewhat outmoded talk of the organisational society indicates). And―aside from the most prominent exceptions of Luhmann and Coleman―hardly any author of ‛grand theory’ gave the modern organisation the place it thus deserves in his theoretical architecture: not Parsons,[7] not Habermas, not Bourdieu, not even Giddens.

Nonetheless, a growing number of authors and publications have been attempting to claim structuration theory for organisational research. From the point of view of Giddens’ theory, this should come as no surprise, since the three concepts whose centrality we have underscored here―reflexivity, structuration and recursiveness―easily and plausibly converge in the concept of organisation if organisation is defined as reflexive structuration in precisely that double sense of recursive production (“organising”) of a product (“organisedness”, organisation as a social system) discussed above. In any instance where reflection sheds light on structures and structuration and enters into the practice of structuring as well as into its results, we are dealing with organisations. Reflexivity is institutionalised in organisations―reflection, namely, on the structuration of collective action―which is not to say organisations are a paragon of rationality. The labour, management and organisational sciences of the twentieth century, especially business administration, are already forms of the reflection of reflection, even if they are also forms of reflection that were halted early on insofar as they long remained restricted to the search for universal or situational one best ways. As the twentieth century comes to a close, however, awareness of contingency has once again sharpened considerably and taken hold of the Taylorist paradigm of mass production and, beyond that, of one-best-way thinking in general.

However, applying structuration theory to the ends of organisational research also suggested itself from the point of view of organisational theory. First, organisational theory was in urgent need of a foundation in social theory and a theory of society, an urgency that is only magnified in view of a development that can also be observed elsewhere―for example, in industrial sociology, technology studies and economics―towards an explosively increasing number of theoretical perspectives and paradigms that hardly communicate with each other, such that warning about the fragmentation and even “dissolution of organisational research” (Friedberg 1995, 96, our translation) is not entirely unjustified. Our impression is that the dimensions of the social proposed by Giddens―signification, legitimation and domination―are well-suited for carefully integrating these diverging theoretical perspectives: interpretative, culturalist and institutionalist approaches; approaches based on theories of power, domination or control; and economic approaches to organisational research.[8]

Second, the concept of structuration, with its notion of the duality and recursiveness of structure, allows for what we find to be a relaxed approach to controversies, which, as we know, are notorious also in organisational theory―and which we should, however, gradually leave behind. We have in mind especially the controversies around the question of ‛action versus structure’ (or system), which in organisational theory has been answered often enough in favour of one side or the other―in favour of action or decision, for example, by Simon and the Carnegie Mellon school, and in favour of structure by the theories of structural contingency, for example, in which what actors do plays such an underestimated role. Yet Giddens’ concept of structure―with its dual components, rules and resources―offers particularly favourable ways of approaching questions of organisational theory. While this may be self-evident for the concept of rules―as the relevance of organisational rules certainly seems obvious―it requires careful explication by way of precisely defining the concept of rule. It applies then also, and particularly so, to the concept of resources, which is indispensable in the framework of political and economic organisational analyses. One need only think of the resource-dependence approach of organisational research, the resource-based view of strategic management, or of micropolitical or strategic organisational analysis (which cannot get by without a concept of power resources), or generally of the view that the enterprise is an institution for the transformation of production factors into products.

Third, the concept of recursiveness suggests also considering the relationship of organisations to supraorganisational institutions in its light. This means taking account not only of the influence of these institutions on organisations but also of the reverse influence organisations have on the manifold institutional conditions of organisational action―a supplement to new institutionalism that we consider highly significant.

Fourth, a peculiarity of Giddens’ concept of structure consists in its emphasis on space-time binding as a decisive effect, an aspect whose relevance is becoming strikingly clear today in view of, for example, just-in-time manufacturing in regional and global networks.

Fifth, the concept of organisational structures, which―except in traces of memory and expectation―exist only in action and are therefore always under the tension of action, permits an unconstrained understanding not only of organisational stability and inertia but also of organisational transformation; and it does so with a view both to the individual organisation and its intended change―the keyword here is ‘reorganisation’―as well as to a possible unintended transformation of an organisation or of the ‛genre of organisation’ or of particular types of organisations, including questions of their origin, their genesis―the keyword here is ‘evolution’.

Sixth, Giddens’ concept of action can connect up with a theoretical description of the relationship between organisation and psyche that allows us to reckon with those dramatis personae who create and change the organisations in the first place―and who are also, for their part, to some extent creatures of the organisation.

While these six areas of problems are certainly not the only ones, nor ordered here in a perfectly systematic manner, they are nevertheless highly significant desiderata of a socio-theoretical foundation for organisational theory. We now intend to discuss them in greater detail.

2.1 The Dimensions of the Social and the Role of the Economy

All organisational action, we emphasise once again, plays out in all three dimensions of the social at once: A certain organisational vocabulary is used repeatedly as a set of interpretative patterns and is reproduced ipso facto as an element of the cognitive order of an organisation. The ‛laws’ of the formal organisation, the formal rules, evaluation procedures and leadership styles, but also the informal standards of what constitutes good work, for example, are applied, followed (or subverted) and thereby reproduced (or undermined) as the organisation’s order of legitimacy. The organisation of labour implies a form of domination over (the labour of) human beings and is reproduced as an authoritative resource through repeated practice. Know-how and technology permit domination over nature and matter and are reproduced as allocative resources by recurrent application. In general, organisational action implies recourse to a set of organisational patterns of interpretation and norms, organisational rules and resources derived from an organisational structure, which in this way―by application of organisational rules and resources―is recursively reproduced and in some circumstances modified in the process.

At first glance, Figure 1 seems merely to provide an unsatisfying juxtaposition of these dimensions of the social. Rather, it begs the question―and this is in many ways the most exciting question of organisational theory: How are the dimensions of cognition, legitimation and domination related? We all know, to put it mildly, that they have a bearing on each other: Our norms depend on our understanding of the world, on our patterns of interpretation and vice versa; our patterns of interpretation, concepts and definitions of situations are established with power, and they are, conversely, powerful means of exercising power. And whatever is considered legitimate depends likewise on power relations, just as, conversely, norms function as instruments of power. In this ‛horizontal’ direction, in the relationship of the dimensions of the social, we thus reckon with recursive relationships of constitution, and we indicate these relationships in Figure 2 by arrows, which set it apart from Figure 1 only in emphasising this recursive circularity once again.[9]

Figure 2: 
Recursiveness between the dimensions of the social.
Figure 2:

Recursiveness between the dimensions of the social.

How does the economy come into play in all of this?

The traditional way of understanding economy as the management of and struggle over scarce resources would be too narrow for Giddens―scarcity is better understood, following Commons (1936, 243), as institutional production itself, institutional scarcity.

A general social theory-based definition of economy must be conceived more broadly, and in Giddens (1984, 34) this is the case. He regards the inherently constitutive role of allocative resources in the reproduction of “societal totalities”, be they entire societies or organisations, as differentia specifica of the sphere of the economic. Indeed, only in modernity does this sphere experience that institutional differentiation which has become so self-evident to us. Modern economic institutions―money and credit, labour markets, product and financial markets, competition and enterprises all designate institutionalised practices that are historical to the highest degree―are marked by the dominance of the (re-)production of allocative resources. And for many organisations―enterprises, above all, of course―this might be a suitable characterisation. We can then speak of economic organisations. In the case of capitalist enterprises, practices of profitable (re-)production even dominate. We can take this as a starting point for a structurationist theory of the enterprise that gives economics its due without reducing the enterprise to pure economics. The acquisitive principle, as Gutenberg called it, is not an anthropological constant, not a psychologically but an “institutionally anchored regulative without which the system could not function” (Gutenberg 1973 [1955], 9, our translation). However, this institutional dominance by no means signifies that the other dimensions of the social are insignificant in and for economic practices. Rather, even when it comes to the rules and resources in and of economic organisations, we are dealing with that recursiveness between the dimensions of the social indicated in Figure 2. Economic practices go hand in hand with the reproduction not only of allocative and authoritative resources but also of rules of signification and legitimation. This manifests particularly clearly in the maintenance of the cognitive and normative order, which is shaped by accounting and bookkeeping systems―an order that recursively ensures that (economic) practices are recognised and evaluated as economic, or else modified (rationalised) until they roughly conform to that order (cf. Sydow et al. 1995, 33–40). The extent to which the rules for the constitution of meaning depend on the allocative and authoritative resources of an organisation and vice versa can also be shown, for example, by the fact that concepts for the organisation of production such as Taylorist mass production or lean production never concern only the production technology ‛per se’―assembly lines, computers, automation, storage areas and technology, transport technology―but always the practical handling of it. And this immediately implies questions about the domination of human beings, questions about legitimation, about fairness in dealing with human beings, for example, and about signification. (What exactly is lean production? What does group work mean? What are the rights and duties of a machine operator? And so on).

“Rules cannot be conceptualized apart from resources, which refer to the modes whereby transformative relations are actually incorporated into the production and reproduction of social practices. Structural properties thus express forms of domination and power” (Giddens 1984, 18).

It has already been indicated above that we can further differentiate the dimension of domination into politics and economy along the lines of the distinction between authoritative and allocative resources, as long as we keep in mind that this does not mean economy in a pure sense―that is, purified of the other dimensions of the social―but refers instead to the more or less far-reaching institutional differentiation of two spheres, one of which is concerned primarily with the domination of human beings and the (re-)production of authoritative resources, and the other primarily with domination over nature and matter and the (re-)production of allocative resources. This distinction of practice is quite common also within organisations, as the―critically intended―talk of ‛political decisions’ in enterprises indicates whenever considerations of power prevail over economic concerns. We can then inquire further about the recursive relationship between these two dimensions: the use of power resources (facilities in Figure 2) may increase efficiency and/or profit, just as, conversely, economic resources increase power over human beings. And we can ask about the relationship of each, now separated into politics and economics, to the interpretative schemes and norms by means of which we define the ‘is and ought’ in organisations. We will not go into these differentiations in any more detail here, but instead conclude by pointing out―using the example of law and politics―that organisational action stands in a recursive constitutional relationship not only to organisational but also to supra-organisational structures―to the institutional environment, as we can say in the language of new institutionalism. It is constrained and enabled by the institutional environment―think of the political and legal regulation of telecommunications or TV markets, labour protection and co-determination laws and so on―and it has an impact on these supra-organisational structures (in this example, political and legal structures). The latter does not always involve strategic intent, but often enough it does―namely to influence those restricting and enabling structures. Organisations try to regulate “their” regulations, that is, the ones that affect them: regulation of regulation, recursive regulation. Ortmann and Zimmer (1998) call this “strategic institutionalisation”.

2.2 Institutions and Institutionalisation

It could be shown that this way of wielding influence (for instance, via lobbying) involves the use of communicative, normative, political and economic means and that it targets all the above-mentioned dimensions of the social: seeking to change interpretations and interpretative schemes[10] and influence perceptions of legitimacy and norms[11] as well as political and economic conditions. The “return of society to organisational theory” then also means addressing the enormous influence of organisations, and especially of enterprises, on the institutional―but particularly the regulatory―constitution of society as a whole. Business administration has always had a certain interest in this topic. Today, the pertinent questions of how environmental protection laws, accounting rules, capital market laws, banking regulations, anti-trust legislation and so on affect (the efficiency of) enterprises are handled predominantly by property rights theory, transaction cost theories, agency theories, political economy and public choice theory, as one can now learn from the instructive anthology Regulation and Corporate Policy [Regulierung und Unternehmenspolitik] by Sadowski, Czap, and Wächter (1996). Usually, however, it is how certain regulations operate―especially their efficiency effects―that is of interest. In business administration, the question begins with a regulation that is somehow assumed or alleged to be given in order to trace its effects on enterprises and ‛the’ economy. Influence in the opposite direction (from the enterprises to those regulations), as obvious as it is, is much more seldom discussed.[12] From the perspective of structuration theory, however, institutions and regulations must be analysed from the outset as a―restricting and enabling―medium and as a product of action, which is to say also as a product of strategic action that calculates and seeks to influence the effects of institutionalisation processes and regulations in light of well-understood interests.

Tracing the lines of the Giddensian dimensions of the social permits us to distinguish and consider institutional orders that pervade all of society―all of its symbolic, political, economic and legal institutions―in this recursive constitutional relationship to action and, now especially, to the action of organisations as corporate actors. This ties institutions and institutional orders more closely to action, more closely to strategic action and therefore more closely to economic and other interests and thus more closely to power, conflict and politics than is often the case in neo-institutionalism. And if we follow Giddens (1984, 17) in defining institutions as those societally imposed regular practices that have the greatest distanciation in time and space within societal totalities (for details, see Ortmann, Sydow, and Türk 1997, 25–33), then perhaps this is also a sufficient response to concerns voiced, for example, by Türk (1997) and Nelson (1997): that the concept of institution is too vague to be truly fertile.

Societally imposed practices―this definition, however, requires further clarification of the concept of rule it contains.

2.3 Rules, Resources and Modalities

Giddens defines rules―those of the constitution of meaning as well as those of legitimation―quite simply as generalisable procedures of practice. As “generalisable procedures applied in the enactment/reproduction of social practices” (Giddens 1984, 21), they are inherent in the actions of the actors (and subsequently in their memory)―and nowhere else. Verbally formulated rules, such as those found in legal codes or organisational instructions, job descriptions etc., that is, in the ‘blueprints’ of formal organisations, are not rules in this sense, but “codified interpretations of rules” (Giddens 1984, 21). Games in organisations, to which we will return below (see Section 2.5), are based largely on (game!) rules in the sense of practised procedures that are not codified.

What we get from all of this are some not very obvious, yet very important distinctions for which the usual terminology of organisational theory often has no equivalent:

  1. a regular praxis, made up of organisational practices, in which

  2. rules, understood as generalisable procedures, are inherent; these

  3. can be formulated as “codified interpretations of rules” (written laws, formal organisational ‛rules’), and finally

  4. beyond rules (and resources, see below), the additional structural properties of social systems that are produced, reproduced and altered by that regular praxis, but are themselves neither rules nor resources: for example, the division of labour, hierarchy, the spatiotemporal interrelatedness of interactions, or centralisation―in short, everything that is usually called structure in organisational theory but is not structure in the narrower sense of rules and resources that we have given it here.

The strange thing about rules of all kinds is that they cannot themselves govern the way they are applied and therefore, strictly speaking, it is only in this situational application that their meaning is fully decided―also and especially their meaning for what happens in organisations. This is of particular significance when it comes to formal―explicitly formulated―‛rules’ (better: codifications of rules), which traditionally play such a prominent role in organisational theory. Application, which only appears to be secondary because it is derived from the formal ‛rule’, is in reality eminently constitutive for the meaning of this ‛rule’, and the concept of informal organisation points to how this supposedly so marginal application is of the utmost importance for the functioning of any organisation, even and especially when that application consists in a deviation, an undermining―indeed, even when it consists in the violation of the formal set of ‛rules’.[13] As Alfred Schutz (1967 [1932]) has said, in this set of ‛rules’ is a certain emptiness that needs to be (ful-)filled in and by application. This is as true for rules of constituting meaning as it is for rules of legitimation, which can only be (ful-)filled, supplemented/replaced in situational, contextual circumstances, equipped with the indices of the here and now―even as they are stripped, in concrete action, of their typicality.

Giddens’ term modalities refers to the rules and resources that are (ful-)filled in this way, deployed hic et nunc by someone with a specific biography and competency. According to this interpretation,[14] they designate the place of mediation between action and structure (between subject and object), and therefore Giddens’ reception of Schutz is, on this reading, of some significance for the notoriously controversial question of whether Giddens succeeded in this mediation.[15] If we have continuously cited the example of the constitution of meaning by use of interpretative schemes and the concomitant (re-)production of a cognitive order as its corresponding structural dimension, all this applies equally to the constitution of legitimacy by use of norms and the concomitant (re-)production of an order of legitimation―and to every practical intervention in the world by use of facilities (in the broadest sense) and the concomitant (re-)production of an order of domination. The latter proceeds with recourse to resources made available by an existing order of domination, and every disposition under situational circumstances implies an analogous movement from an emptiness―the somehow still empty generality of resources as means to typical but not concretely defined ends―to the fullness of the now, here and in this way, which the user only imparts to it in praxis.[16]

As explained above, we consider it a great advantage that Giddens’ concept of structure in this way includes specific resources, especially with a view to organisations and especially enterprises. Note that this concept of resources avoids the opposition between the material and the immaterial, even if it sometimes seems otherwise:

“Some forms of allocative resources (such as raw materials, land, etc.) might seem to have a ‘real existence’ in a way which I have claimed that structural properties as a whole do not. But their ‘materiality’ does not affect the fact that such phenomena become resources, in the manner in which I apply that term here, only when incorporated within processes of structuration” (Giddens 1984, 33).

That we first must make resources into resources, that we have to generate them in recursive loops of organisational praxis as―socially significant―resources before we can use them as such; this is an insight that is thoroughly incorporated in the resource-dependence approach of organisational research as well as in the resource-based view of strategic management, where, as one can see, it has considerable consequences for the praxis of organisation and management (on this, see Knyphausen-Aufseß 1997).

2.4 The Binding of Time and Space

In Giddens’ terminology, structures―that is, rules and resources―‛bind’ time and space.[17] ‛Instantiated’ in situated practices, they provide the latter with temporospatial extension, institutionalisation and a globalisation that can be supplemented, replaced, offset or corrected by certain forms of localisation and regionalisation. Technologies of storage, irrigation, conservation, transport and, as of recently, especially data storage and processing as well as communication provide the enormous possibilities of time-space extension that we are confronted with today. Organisations are the medium and result of the development of precisely such technologies: They enable or promote technology development, which in turn massively accelerates the development, proliferation and power of organisations in society. With ‛storage’, Giddens―with a view to modernity―has in mind also and above all the storage of authoritative resources in memory, in the form of writing and, today, by means of computer technology; but he also has in mind the form of organisation, which considerably increases the possibilities for storage. The origin of this special nuance (Giddens 1979, 198–233) in a tradition which, from Husserl via Schutz and Heidegger to Derrida,[18] has made the temporality and spatiality of human existence a prominent object of reflection, may have impeded―and may continue to impede―its reception in Germany. However, this will change in times when dichotomies such as global–local indicate spatially the distance and the rending tension contained therein. The small dairy cooperative in East Frisia whose dried milk is enjoyed (months or years after production?) by children in southern Africa is a standard example of what Giddens (1990, 64–65) calls “time-space distanciation”―the globalisation of modernity, a globalisation that initially occurs naturally and only later becomes an object of reflection, which is also to say an object of reflection on the structuration of global enterprises and enterprise networks.

The fact that organisation is always about spatiotemporal organisation―about production schedules, time worked and time lost, operating hours, just-in-time production, night work and overtime, cycle times, target times, set-up times, break times; and about production spaces, reworking and storage spaces, transport routes and communication channels, outsourcing, regional and global networks―requires no explanation. Modernity has given rise to enterprises that, on the one hand, have nearly disappeared from view―that are ‛hollow,’ ‛virtual’―and, on the other hand, operate worldwide; enterprises that are detached―‛disembedded’―from their local contexts and ‘re-embedded’ only via organisation, information technology and communication technology.

The close attention Giddens’ social theory pays to “time, space and regionalisation”, his concept of structure and structuration especially tailored to this and his keen eye for the fact that the concept of space-time distanciation is directly related to the theory of power (Giddens 1984, 258)―in other words, that space-time extension by way of organisation is of fundamental significance for the extension of power: this too contributes to the attraction his theory holds for research on organisational theory.

2.5 Organisational Change

Organisational change may be more or less intentional or unintentional. In the former case, we will speak of reorganisation, in the latter of evolution. ‘Evolution’ may refer to individual organisations,[19] but above all to the genres, here populations of organisations. Of course, they are interrelated: Evolution also takes place through reorganisation, the factual consequences of which are, incidentally, never entirely intended. But evolution proceeds also by way of change that is unplanned from the outset, as well as by selection. Evolution, as we use the term, does not imply any sort of advancement, however defined.

In the case of reorganisation, the intentionality of change means that it is intended but not that it is realised as intended. In opposition to rationalist textbook versions of reorganisation, we have borrowed Levi-Strauss’ image of bricolage, tinkering: a productive action that works on an unfinished task with a limited supply of means―a tinker box (Ortmann et al. 1990, 391–395). Bounded rationality, goals that change depending on opportunities―think of the opportunities created by new technologies―and tool-like means for tasks of a type only partly defined by ends: these are the most important features of tinkering as well as of reorganisation, which makes changes to the structure of organisations, to their rules and resources, in a political process that ultimately outstrips the metaphor of the lonely tinkerer. Reorganisation is the conscious, reflexive re-structuration of ‛organisation’ as a field of action, a re-structuration that aims to change an organisation’s rules and resources while playing out in every dimension of the social as an attempt to change established structures of signification, legitimation and domination. This is subject, like all organisational action, to the recursiveness of structure. Reorganisation―as well as resistance to change―must therefore make use of the very means of power made available by the (still) given organisational structure. Disputes about restructurings are often so fierce because they regulate how power will be distributed in the future rounds of organisational games. We therefore follow Giddens as well as Crozier and Friedberg (1980 [1977]) in interpreting resistance to reorganisations not as an expression of the irrationality, stupidity and inertia of human nature but, on the contrary, as an organisationally induced phenomenon: the usually thoroughly rational behaviour[20] of players in an established game of routine who have become comfortable and proven themselves within its structures, its game rules and distribution of resources. And now, in the face of a game of innovation that impacts on and may destroy the old game structures, and should at the very least change them, they react by deferring, putting on the brakes or resisting―not seldom, by the way, while citing reasons that are good even from an organisational point of view. This view of things deprives reorganisation processes of much of that well-ordered rationality that textbooks often attest to them, and which is frequently expressed not only in unaffected ends-means hierarchies and correspondingly ‛rational’ step sequences and phase schemes but also in the more or less unshattered belief that the results of reorganisation processes are also properly understood as the results of intentional action.

Even after abandoning such a picture of rational and controlled reorganisation, the rationality that is threatened in this way can rescue itself by means of ever-rationalist social Darwinist conceptions of evolution. Then it is not rational reorganisers but rather environment, selection and/or adaptation that ensure the survival of rational, perhaps even optimal, forms of organisation. We can here leave aside the critique of these ideas, as handed down from Veblen via the population ecology approach to some variants of new institutionalism, because this has been done conclusively elsewhere, for example, by Kieser (1993a) and by Nelson (1997). We would just like to point out that Giddens (1984) strongly rejects this kind of evolutionism in the social sciences as well as any theory of social transformation understood in this way. His primary reasons are twofold: (1) People do not make their history just as they please but in knowledge of this very history, as reflexive beings, and they change this history depending on their knowledge. The same, by the way, could be said of organisations (cf. Kieser 1993a, 255–256). (2) Neither ‛societies’ nor ‛organisations’ (again Kieser 1993a, 257) are fit to serve as those clearly definable basic evolutionary units that are independent of the course of history itself, but whose very evolution should be the issue at stake here. Representations of organisational change also require a completely different form and, in short, must operate with concepts such as episode, coincidence and critical threshold of change; they must reckon with contingency, necessity and chance (cf. also Giddens 1984, 244–262), which can force change into certain courses and trajectories. Path dependency (“organizational tracks”, Greenwood and Hinings 1988) is an important concept in this context because it allows us to grasp fairly well the peculiar mixture of chance (‛small events’ in the beginning) and necessity (‛lock-in’ in the further course) that brings about the ‛evolution’ of organisation in specific directions.[21] It is not the heroes of a universal principle of efficiency―‛survival of the fittest’―who are victorious according to this account but lucky winners who could just as easily have become losers, but who now, having won, have at their disposal the means to build on their victory: to oust the others from the market permanently, to gradually ensure their own efficiency and, last but not least, to rewrite the criteria for success and history itself in such a way that their victory appears as a heroic act of efficiency: Winner takes all. It is not by chance, then, that path dependency runs like a golden thread through Nelson’s (1997) contribution.

Finally, structuration means structuredness and structuring. In principle, stability and change are on equal footing here. This is perhaps the greatest advantage of which a Giddens-inspired organisational theory can boast: that it allows us to think both the sometimes so rapid changes and the sometimes sheer despairing inertia of organisations―as well as the complication that change without stability (e.g. valid interpretative schemes and guaranteed access to resources) is not even possible (and vice versa). For both, of course, structuration theory provides only a theoretical framework within which the rigidity and conservatism of organisational structures―or indeed their changeability―become theoretically workable. It does not provide this theorisation for particular empirical cases―it cannot and does not intend to at its level of generality. Yet it renders stability, inertia, encrustation, blockage and immobility issues that can be addressed theoretically because they are deciphered as results of recursive reproduction―as results of constant movement.

2.6 Organisation and Psyche

At least since Barnard (1938) it has been clear that organisations consist of actions, not persons; this is a consensus that would not deny that persons are ‛important for organisations’ but would like to insist (a) that no organisation subsumes the whole person with all his or her activities, (b) that it is precisely their―organisational―activities that are organised and in turn (re-)produce the organisations and not, for example, the character traits of persons, their hopes, doubts, aversion to garlic, secret thoughts or vices and virtues, and (c) that all organisational activities are understood as elements of organisations (and not just productive labour, to cite an example taken from older versions of both Marxism and business administration, cf. Witt 1997).

But how then are we to grasp theoretically that―and how―persons are ‛important for organisations’―and, nota bene, vice versa? Psyche, motives, performance readiness, anxiety, likes and dislikes―that is, the needs[22] of the acting persons, to use the concept under which economic theory subsumes all this without dealing with it―how can they feature in our social- and organisational-theoretical outline?

The fact that it does not suffice, for the more precise definitions that are required here, to imagine adding in psychoanalysis as the competent discipline, as it were―after all, psychoanalysis portrays “the individual in his or her unmistakable identity, in his or her life-situational and life-historical individuality” (Lorenzer 1976, 19, our translation)―is due to the circumstance that the object of psychoanalysis is not real interactions and object relations but the interpersonal relations that are embedded in personality or, to put it more drastically, “the inner world of fantasy scenes” (Lorenzer 1976, 24–25, our translation). Psychoanalysis is concerned with schemes of events-as-sensed (‛Erlebnisentwürfen’), not the investigation of events-as-such.[23] Interactions, however, as an element of the social, are events. Psychoanalysis cannot immediately connect up with this. Hope for mediation is nourished only by the insight

“that the figures of experience derive genetically from real interaction, the foundational interaction forms are always the inner precipitation of interactions and, furthermore, the forms of interaction are functionally related to real interaction as drafts of behaviour and action” (Lorenzer 1976, 25, our translation).

“Interpersonal relations in personality” is thus supposed to mean:

“From the collective social structures, we get past the mediating figures of the interaction game and into the individual in the following way: The […] interplay in the mother-child dyad influences the child’s organism, calibrates its behavioural reactions; that is, it is precipitated in the child’s organism. […] Interaction is laid down as an interaction engram to then be instrumentalised as a design of behaviour. Themselves the result of interactions, these drafts of behaviour determine subsequent interactions. Genetically as well as functionally, they are related to interactions; they are specified by interactions in order to determine further interactions; but as regulated regulators, they are internal to the individual.

As internal regulators, they clearly do not belong to the observable level of interaction phenomena, rather they are building blocks of the essence of personality in its societally specified form. These drafts of behaviour embedded in the personality, which constitute the personality in its essence, have been called ‘specified interaction forms’.[24] The specified forms of interaction are the societal relations in the concrete individual” (Lorenzer 1976, 20–21, emphases in original, our translation).

As we can see, they are the results of a recursive process of (re-)production: Emerging from interaction processes, they enter into new interactions in important ways and are fixed as interaction engrams in order to then be related, in the form of interaction designs, to action―which recursively stabilises that fixation. Lorenzer’s ‛specified interaction forms’ designate the level of mediation between action and personality structure. Thanks to Lorenzer’s reformulation of psychoanalytical concepts in terms of forms of interaction―nota bene, this somewhat misleading choice of words refers to interaction designs or patterns in individuals, not to forms of real interaction―we can offer a sketch of the individual that can be meaningfully linked to social and organisational theory, a schematic version of which looks something like Figure 3.[25]

Figure 3: 
Individual: Interaction, interaction drafts, personality structure interaction designs.
Figure 3:

Individual: Interaction, interaction drafts, personality structure interaction designs.

“The interaction forms [interaction designs; the authors] can only appear in interactions, be they imagined or really occurring scenes” (Lorenzer 1976, 25, our translation). The psychoanalytic achievement, however, is still the reconstruction of events-as-pereceived (‘Erlebnisrekonstruktionen’), not of events.

To speak of interaction engrams and personality structure as we do here, and as Lorenzer does in his work, is also to imply something like a cognitive structure that is not, however, central to the framework of psychoanalysis. Desires and fears on the one hand and something like reason on the other―both sides are accounted for in Giddens’ model of action, which distinguishes between three levels of consciousness in actors:

discursive consciousness

practical consciousness

unconscious motives/cognition (Giddens 1984, 7).

It also considers both “reflexive monitoring” and “rationalisation” (in the sense of commonsensical justification) as well as the “motivation of action”:

“I distinguish the reflexive monitoring and rationalization of action from its motivation. If reasons refer to the grounds of action, motives refer to the wants which prompt it. However, motivation is not as directly bound up with the continuity of action as are its reflexive monitoring or rationalisation. Motivation refers to potential for action rather than to the mode in which action is chronically carried on by the agent. […] For the most part motives supply overall plans or programmes―‘projects’, in Schutz’s term―within which a range of conduct is enacted. Much of our day-to-day conduct is not directly motivated” (Giddens 1984, 6).

With the help of Lorenzer, we can understand this more precisely, that is, in terms of recursiveness and structuration theory: as the relationship between an interaction engram (‛motives supply overall plans or programmes’), which refers only indirectly to interaction scenes, and specified interaction designs, which refer to them directly.

But we need psychological access not only to desires, fears and motives but also to cognition, including its unconscious parts.

For a combination of cognitive psychology and symbolic interactionism, which are linked to Jakob and Thure von Uexküll’s recursively constructed models of the ‛function circle’ and the ‛situation circle’, we have taken hints from the instructive work of Brauner (1994). With its structuration-theoretical design―recursiveness of interaction and cognitive structure (cognitive maps, mental models)―Brauner’s dynamic, circular model of interaction represents a cognitive-psychological elaboration of the basic idea we would like to present here. Connections to Anthony Giddens’ concept of action are unmistakable, especially the proximity of “mental control of action” [mentale Handlungskontrolle] (Brauner 1994, 103–105) to Giddens’ ‘reflexive monitoring of action’. Brauner’s model makes clear―and it is no coincidence that it shares this with Giddens’ actor model―that we produce and change our individual cognitive maps of the world in iterative and recursive loops of practice―that is, in the practical application and reflection of these cognitive maps. Both therefore offer possible links to the most promising approaches of cognitive psychology that are not rationalistically pre-occupied, such as Neisser’s perceptual cycle and its reworking by Karl Weick, both fine examples of thinking in terms of recursivity―in this case between perceiving and acting (Neisser 1979; Weick 1985 [1969], 223–226; cf. also Conrad and Sydow 1984, 73–92). Neisser’s perceptual schemata are the results of a perceptual learning that enter into new acts of perception as active, information-seeking (individual) structures and are thereby recursively reproduced and possibly modified. Connections to questions of organisational learning are obvious and Weick elaborates them. We include not only Lorenzer’s interaction designs but also these Neisserian cognitive structures in the personality structure of acting persons, and we are now prepared to connect these two descriptions of social and individual structuration. We will then see that the place of mediation between the individual and society―or organisation―is interaction [26] (Figure 4).

Figure 4: 
Individual and society: structuration and mediation.
Figure 4:

Individual and society: structuration and mediation.

Every interaction is simultaneously individual and social action and the perception of events and event-as-such, the putting-into-action of interaction designs and the occurring of social praxis in the medium of social structures. That every interaction is both at the same time does not imply that both are the same thing; nor does the fact that each is something very different imply that they are not related in a comprehensible and specifiable way. On the contrary, there is no “specific form of interaction” in Lorenzer’s sense that can be realised in interaction wholly outside the medium of social structures, nor any social practice that is not somehow the realisation of individual drafts of interaction.

Furthermore, every interaction implies, on the side of social structures, (re-)production and institutionalisation (including modification) and, on the side of the individual, socialisation and internalisation, although we cannot reckon a priori with successful or even mutually harmonious processes of socialisation/internalisation on the one hand or of reproduction/institutionalisation on the other. (And if they do ‛succeed’ in the sense of achieving mutual correspondence, then we certainly do not have to like the result, as the case of Barnard’s organisational personality makes clear. In Barnard’s classic example of a switchboard operator at the New Jersey Bell Telephone Company, its conformity went quite far. She specifically chose a subordinate position in an outlying district because from there she could watch her sick mother’s house while she worked. When the house caught fire one day, she stayed at her post and watched while the house burned down, showing, in Barnard’s words, “extraordinary ‘moral courage’” and “high responsibility” regarding the organisational norm of uninterrupted readiness to serve Barnard 1938, 269, Barnard left a footnote: Her mother was rescued).

Interactions, these central sites of mediation between the individual and society (or organisation), are therefore not to be characterised merely as agencies of socialisation (Lorenzer 1976, 44) but always simultaneously, with a view to society, as sites of (re-)production of social structures and institutions.[27]

4 Critique and Outlook

Despite the considerable spread of structuration-theoretical research in organisational theory in particular, the reception of Giddens is marked by noticeable deficits leaving important room for improvement, especially in the German-speaking world. This is due not only to the fact that the field he tills is occupied in this country by Habermas and his students, who have hardly ever spoken of organisations (and, to the extent that they have, have done so predominantly in the sense of Luhmann’s systems theory). But Giddens himself has abetted this trend in a certain sense. It is not merely that he has written well over 20 books to date, making it difficult even for benevolent readers to follow the developments of his thought. Rather, it is precisely the reader who is still unfamiliar with Giddens’ work who is left with the impression that Bernstein (1989, 27) has described as follows:

“One sometimes feels that Giddens is not always in control of the material he is discussing. Where one expects detailed explication and justification, too often there is repetition and ‘eloquent’ variation. Temperamentally, Giddens is foxlike in his approach to issues, although his systematic ambitions require him to be like the hedgehog. Given the sheer variety of topics, themes, and thinkers he treats, one can understand why he tells us [about his book Constitution of Society:] ‘This was not a particularly easy book to write and proved in some part refractory to the normal ordering of chapters’ (Giddens 1984, xxxv).”

Inaccuracies and inconsistencies concerning terminology and conceptualisation have rightly been pointed out and not only by critics such as Archer (1990) and Stinchcombe (1990). The German-language edition of Giddens’ magnum opus, The Constitution of Society (Die Konstitution der Gesellschaft 1988), with its grave translation deficiencies, did not improve the situation. Yet even in the original English edition, the glossary of this work contains strange terminological deviations from the body of the text. There are categorical inconsistencies in Giddens’ definitions of authoritative and allocative resources, for example―a meaningful distinction, which he, however, sometimes seems to confound with the distinctions “material/immaterial resources” and “technological/organisational resources” (Ortmann 1995a, 299, fn. 9). Bernstein (1989, 30, 33) has bemoaned deficits in how the theory deals with the justification of norms and in terms of its critical quality (see also Joas 1988, 23; for a response to this, Ortmann 1995a, 226–252). Gerstenberger (1988) has found the validity of historical claims lacking, a criticism whose relevance for the social-theoretical core of structuration theory would need to be discussed separately. It is thus not surprising that Giddens’ writings have received a great deal of attention, but at the same time have triggered vehement controversies (for summaries, see the anthologies by Held and Thompson 1989; Clark, Modgil, and Modgil 1990; Bryant and Jary 1991).

Many critiques revolve around different ways of reading the basic theorem about the duality of structure. Archer (1990, 77), for example, charges that Giddens’ concept of structuration oscillates between two divergent images: On one side there is the hyperactivity of agency, which contributes innately to the volatility of society; on the other side, the structural properties of society exhibit a rigid coherence, so that the aspect of stability is exaggerated. Outhwaite (1990, 85) has objected that Archer reads into Giddens’ texts the very opposition between action and structure that Giddens is so intent on eliminating. Kieβling (1988, 232–244, 179–232) refers to a ‛standard critique’ that accuses Giddens of subjectivist reductionism, but himself comes to the opposite conclusion that Giddens’ theoretical apparatus suffers from an objectivist surplus (for a concise anti-critique, see Gondeck 1998).

Discussion of the mediation of action and structure continues. It is rather surprising that the theoretical debates have lacked any specific discussion of the mechanisms of mediation and, in particular, that the significant question of modalities in Giddens’ theorem of the duality of structure has garnered little attention. Although our remarks on this will not be the last word, either, we believe we have at least suggested the way forward for discussion of this concept in Section 2.2.

In our view, further clarification of the mediation of action and structure could be fruitful for the interplay of theory development and empirical research―if expectations are kept in check:

“The concepts of structuration theory, as with any competing theoretical perspective, should for many research purposes be regarded as sensitizing devices, nothing more. That is to say, they may be useful for thinking about research problems and the interpretation of research results” (Giddens 1984, 326–327).

A look at the landscape of current empirical organisational and network research shows how much it stands to gain from theoretical inspiration. Giddens’ structuration theory provides just such an inspiring theoretical framework―provided we do not limit ourselves to trying to fill it with empiricism but instead keep in mind the constitutive role of this ‛filling’ for that framework and the considerable opportunities to absorb and productively work with the insights of other theoretical traditions and the established concepts of organisation theory. This then also opens up opportunities for communication between supposedly incommensurable discourses―one need only think of interpretative organisational research, economic and sociological neo-institutionalism or even distinctly structuralist or action-theoretical approaches as well as the classical organisation theory of business administration. It then becomes only natural that in the course of its fulfilment such a framework should also be supplemented, perhaps even replaced―in a process of principally interminable critique.


Corresponding author: Arnold Windeler, Department of Sociology, Technische Universität Berlin, Berlin, Germany, E-mail:

References

Archer, M. 1990. “Human Agency and Social Structure: A Critique of Giddens.” In Anthony Giddens: Consensus and Controversy, edited by J. Clark, C. Modgil, and S. Modgil, 73–84. London, New York, Philadelphia: Falmer Press.Search in Google Scholar

Arthur, B. W. 1989. “Competing Technologies, Increasing Returns, and Lock-In by Historical Events.” The Economic Journal 99 (394): 116–31. https://doi.org/10.2307/2234208.Search in Google Scholar

Arthur, B. W. 1990. “Positive Feedbacks in the Economy.” Scientific American 262: 80–5. https://doi.org/10.1038/scientificamerican0290-92.Search in Google Scholar

Barnard, C. I. 1938. The Functions of the Executive. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Beck, U. 1992. Risk Society. Towards a New Modernity. London. Newbury Park, New Dehli: Sage.Search in Google Scholar

Beck, U., A. Giddens, and S. Lash, eds. 1994. Reflexive Modernization. Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order. Cambridge: Polity Press.Search in Google Scholar

Bensam, J., and I. Grever. 1963. “Crime and Punishment in the Factory: The Function of Deviancy in Maintaining the Social System.” American Sociological Review 28 (4): 588–98.10.2307/2090074Search in Google Scholar

Bernstein, R. J. 1989. “Social Theory as Critque.” In Social Theory of Modern Societies: Anthony Giddens and His Critics, edited by D. Held and J. B. Thompson, 19–33. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511557699.002Search in Google Scholar

Braczyk, H.-J. 1997. “Organisation in industriesoziologischer Perspektive.” In Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 530–75. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_26Search in Google Scholar

Brauner, E. 1994. Soziale Interaktion und neutrale Modelle. Planungs- und Entscheidungsprozesse in Planspielgruppen. Münster/New York: Waxmann.Search in Google Scholar

Bryant, C. G. A., and D. Jary. 1991. Giddens’ Theory of Structuration. A Critical Appreciation. London: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Clark, J., C. Modgil, and S. Modgil, eds. 1990. Anthony Giddens. Consensus and Controversy. London: Falmer Press.Search in Google Scholar

Coleman, J. S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Commons, J. R. 1936. “Institutional Economics.” The American Economic Review 26 (1): 237–49.Search in Google Scholar

Conrad, P., and J. Sydow. 1984. Organisationsklima. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter.10.1515/9783110857313Search in Google Scholar

Crozier, M., and E. Friedberg. 1980[1977]. Actors and Systems. The Politics of Collective Action. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Search in Google Scholar

David, P. A. 1986. “Understanding the Economics of QWERTY: The Necessity of History.” In Economic History and the Modern Economist, edited by W. N. Parker, 30–49. Oxford, New York: B. Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

David, P. A. 1990. “The Dynamo and the Computer: An Historical Perspective on the Modern Productivity Paradox.” Papers and Proceedings of the Hundred and Second Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association 80 (2): 355–61.Search in Google Scholar

Duschek, S. 1995. Miszelle zur Dualität von Struktur. Manuscript. Wuppertal: Universität Wuppertal.Search in Google Scholar

Friedberg, E. 1995. Ordnung und Macht. Dynamiken organisierten Handelns. Frankfurt a.M.; New York: Campus.Search in Google Scholar

Gerstenberger, H. 1988. “Zu Anthony Giddens’ “Konstitution der Gesellschaft”.” Prokla 18 (71): 144–64. https://doi.org/10.32387/prokla.v18i71.1299.Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1976. New Rules of Sociological Method. LV. London: Hutchinson.Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1979. Central Problems in Social Theory. Action, Structure and Contradiction in Social Analysis. Basingstoke, Hampshire, London: Macmillan.10.1007/978-1-349-16161-4Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1984. The Constitution of Society. Outline of the Theory of Structuration. Cambridge: Polity Press.Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1988. Die Konstitution der Gesellschaft. Grundzüge einer Theorie der Strukturierung. Frankfurt a.M.; New York: Campus.Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1990. The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.Search in Google Scholar

Giddens, A. 1993[1976]. New Rules of Sociological Method, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Polity Press.Search in Google Scholar

Gondeck, H.-D. 1998. “Einzelbesprechung zu Kiessling 1988.” Soziologische Revue 12: 157–9.Search in Google Scholar

Gould, S. J. 1989. Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History. New York: Norton.Search in Google Scholar

Greenwood, R., and C. R. Hinings. 1988. The Dynamics of Strategic Change. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Gutenberg, E. 1973[1955]. Grundlagen der Betriebswirtschaftslehre. Zweiter Band. Der Absatz. 14. Auflage. Berlin: Springer Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Hegel, G. W. F. 2010[1832, 1832, 1816]. The Science of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Held, D. and J. B. Thompson, eds. 1989. Social Theory of Modern Societies: Anthony Giddens and His Critics. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511557699Search in Google Scholar

Hutter, M. 1989. Die Produktion von Recht. Eine selbstreferentielle Theorie der Wirtschaft, angewandt auf den Fall des Arzneimittelpatentrechts. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Search in Google Scholar

Joas, H. 1988. “Einführung. Eine soziologischen Transformation der Praxisphilosophie – Giddens’ Theorie der Strukturierung.” In: Die Konstitution der Gesellschaft. Grundzüge einer Theorie der Strukturierung, edited by A Giddens. B. Frankfurt a.M., New York: Campus.Search in Google Scholar

Kieser, A. 1993a. “Evolutionstheoretische Ansätze.” In Organisationstheorien, edited by A. Kieser, 243–276, 3rd ed. Stuttgart; Berlin; Köln: Kohlhammer.Search in Google Scholar

Kieser, A. 1993b. “Managementlehre und Taylorismus.” In Organisationstheorien, edited by A. Kieser, 63–94, 3rd ed. Stuttgart; Berlin; Köln: Kohlhammer.Search in Google Scholar

Kießling, B. 1988. Kritik der Giddenschen Sozialtheorie. Ein Beitrag zur theoretisch-methodischen Grundlegung der Sozialwissenschaften. Frankfurt a.M.: Lang.Search in Google Scholar

Knyphausen-Aufseß, , D. zu. 1997. “Auf dem Weg zu einem ressourcenorientierten Paradigma? Resource-Dependence-Theorie der Organisation und Resource-based View des Strategischen Managements im Vergleichnu.” In Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and Klaus Türk, 452–480. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_22Search in Google Scholar

Korzybski, A. 1949. Science and Sanity. An Introduction to Non-aristotelic Systems and General Semantics, 3rd ed. Lakeville, CT: Internatioanl Non-Aristotelian Library.Search in Google Scholar

Leithäuser, T., and B. Volmerg. 1988. Psychoanalyse in der Sozialforschung. Eine Einführung am Beispiel der Sozialpsychologie der Arbeit. Opladen. Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-663-07773-2Search in Google Scholar

Lorenzer, A. 1971. “Symbol, Interaktion und Praxis.” In Psychoanalyse als Sozialwissenschaft, edited by A. Lorenzer, H. Dahmer, K. Horn, K. Brede, and E. Schwanenberg, 9–59. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Lorenzer, A. 1976. “Zur Dialektik von Individuum und Gesellschaft.” In Produktion, arbeit, Sozialisation, edited by T. Leithäuser, and Walter R. Heinz, 13–47. Frankfurt a.M: Suhrkamp Verlag.Search in Google Scholar

Luhmann, N. 1995[1984]. Social Systems. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Martens, W. 1997. Organisation und gesellschaftliche Teilsysteme. In Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 263–311. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_12Search in Google Scholar

McClosky, D. 1990. If You’re So Smart: The Narrative of Economic Expertise. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Search in Google Scholar

Neisser, U. 1979. Kognition und Wirklichkeit. Prinzipien und Implikationen der kognitiven Psychologie. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.Search in Google Scholar

Nelson, R. R. 1997. “Recent Evolutionary Theorizing About Economic Change.” In Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 81–123. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_5Search in Google Scholar

North, D. C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511808678Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G. 1995a. Formen der Produktion. Organisation und Rekursivität. Opladen. Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-97055-8Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G. 1995b. “Organisation und Psyche.” In Nach allen Regeln der Kunst : Macht und Geschlecht in Organisationen, edited by B. Volmer, T. Leithäuser, O. Neuberger, G. Ortmann, and B. Sievers, 205–250. Freiburg im Breisgau: Kore.Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G. 1995c. “Unter der Hand. Über die Virulenz verpönter Interaktion.” In Nach allen Regeln der Kunst : Macht und Geschlecht in Organisationen, edited by B. Volmer, T. Leithäuser, O. Neuberger, G. Ortmann, and B. Sievers, 251–269. Freiburg im Breisgau: Kore.Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G. 1996. “Wiedergänger der Moderne – Derrida, Giddens und die Geister der Aufklärung.” Soziologische Revue 19: 15–28.Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G., J. Sydow, and K. Türk 1997. “Einführung.” In Theorien der Organisation: Die Rückkehr der Gesellschaft, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 15–34. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_2Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G., A. Windeler, A. Becker, and H.-J. Schulz. 1990. Computer und Macht in Organisationen. Mikropolitische Analysen. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-663-11998-2Search in Google Scholar

Ortmann, G., and M. Zimmer. 1998. “Strategisches Management, Recht und Politik.” Betriebswirtschaft 58 (6): 747–69.Search in Google Scholar

Outhwaite, W. 1990. “Agency and Structure.” In Anthony Giddens: Consensus and Controversy, edited by J. Clark, C. Modgil, and S. Modgil, 63–72. London, New York, Philadelphia: Falmer Press.Search in Google Scholar

Parsons, T. 1956. “Suggestions for a Sociological Approach to the Theory of Organizations-I.” Administrative Science Quarterly 1 (1): 63–85. https://doi.org/10.2307/2390840.Search in Google Scholar

Parsons, T. 1957. “Suggestions for a Sociological Approach to the Theory of Organizations-II.” Administrative Science Quarterly 1 (2): 225–39. https://doi.org/10.2307/2390988.Search in Google Scholar

Ritsert, J. 1981. “Anerkennung, Selbst und Gesellschaft. Zur gesellschaftlichen Konstitution von Subjektivität in Hegels “Jenaer Relphilosophie”.” Soziale Welt 22 (3): 275–311.Search in Google Scholar

Sadowski, D., H. Czap, and H. Wächter. 1996 Regulierung und Unternehmenspolitik: Methoden und Ergebnisse der betriebswirtschaftlichen Rechtsanalyse. Wiesbaden: Gabler Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-82419-6Search in Google Scholar

Schutz, A. 1967[1932]. The Phenomenology of the Social World. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Scott, W. R. 1994. “Institutions and Organizations. Toward a Theoretical Synthesis.” In Institutional Environments and Organizations. Structural Complexity and Individualism, edited by W. Richard Scott, and J. W. Meyer, 55–80. Thousand Oaks, London, New Dehli: Sage.Search in Google Scholar

Staehle, W. H. 1994. Management. Eine verhaltenswissenschaftliche Perspektive. 7 Auflage. München: Vahlen.Search in Google Scholar

Stinchcombe, A. 1990. “Milieu and Structure Updated: A Critique of the Theory of Structuration.” In Anthony Giddens: Consensus and Controversy, edited by J. Clark, C. Modgil, and S. Modgil, 47–56. London, New York, Philadelphia: Falmer Press.Search in Google Scholar

Stolz, H.-J., and K. Türk. 1992. “Organisation als Verkörperung von Herrschaft. Sozialtheoretische und makrosoziologische Aspekte der Organisationssoziologie.” In Technik Arbeit Betrieb Gesellschaft. Beiträge der Industriesoziologie und Organisationsforschung, edited by F. Lehner and J. Schmid, 125–171. Opladen: Leske + Budrich.10.1007/978-3-663-11600-4_8Search in Google Scholar

Sydow, J., A. Windeler, M. Krebs, A. Loose, and B. van Well. 1995. Organisation von Netzwerken. Strukturationstheoretische Analysen der Vermittlungspraxis in Versicherungsnetzwerken. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-99598-8Search in Google Scholar

Tullock, G. 1967. “The Welfare Costs of Tarifs, Monopolis, and Theft.” Economic Inquiry 5 (3): 224–32.10.1111/j.1465-7295.1967.tb01923.xSearch in Google Scholar

Türk, K. 1995. “Die Organisation der Welt.” Herrschaft durch Organisation in der modernen Gesellschaft. B. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-97058-9Search in Google Scholar

Türk, K. 1997. “Organisation als Institution der kapitalistischen Gesellschaftsformation.” In Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 124–176. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_6Search in Google Scholar

Walz, W. R. 1996. “Rechtspolitik und Betriebswirtschaftslehre. Eine juristische Perspektive.” In Regulierung und Unternehmenspolitik: Methoden und Ergebnisse der betriebswirtschaftlichen Rechtsanalyse, edited by D. Sadowski, H. Czap, and H. Wächter, 23–49. Wiesbaden: Gabler Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-82419-6_2Search in Google Scholar

Weick, K. E. 1985[1969]. Der Prozeß des Organisierens. B. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.Search in Google Scholar

Wenger, E. 1996. “Kapitalmarktrecht als Resultat deformierter Anreizstrukturen.” In Regulierung und Unternehmenspolitik: Methoden und Ergebnisse der betriebswirtschaftlichen Rechtsanalyse, edited by D. Sadowski, H. Czap, and H. Wächter, 419–58. Wiesbaden: Gabler Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-82419-6_21Search in Google Scholar

Witt, F. H. 1997. “Organisation und Gesellschaft in der Theorie der Unternehmung.” AB Theorien der Organisation, edited by G. Ortmann, J. Sydow, and K. Türk, 424–48. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.10.1007/978-3-322-95661-3_20Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2023-06-02
Accepted: 2023-06-05
Published Online: 2023-06-28

© 2023 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 9.10.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/joso-2023-0017/html?lang=en
Scroll to top button