Home Re-creating the engagement in managerial learning
Article Publicly Available

Re-creating the engagement in managerial learning

  • Eva Gatarik and Rainer Born EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: February 8, 2018

Abstract

When defending his doctoral dissertation, Umberto Eco was accused of narrative fallacy because he presented his research as if it were a detective novel. He should have presented only his conclusions. However, this criticism inspired Eco to claim that “[e]very scientific book should be ... the report of a quest for some Holy Grail” (Eco, 2011, p. 7). A quest presupposes engagement on both sides of the knowledge exchange. Building upon our own research, we have produced a model-theoretic scheme for management studies in support of the practicability of Eco’s claim. The idea is to re-create the engagement when establishing problem-solving competence in managerial learning: We start with an analysis of real-life cases of successful managerial problem solving (“best practices”). Next, we attempt to find the common denominator of those successful solutions. Lastly, we instantiate the principles found in the previous step in new problem situations, and thus provide new uses for them.

Introduction

Towards Organizational Knowledge edited by Krogh et al. (2013), a Festschrift honouring the lifework of Ikujiro Nonaka, dealt with the ecology of knowledge creation. In chapter 11, Konno who together with Nonaka in 1998 introduced the concept of ba—the shared context formed among individuals through interaction in pursuit of knowledge—points out that we are now in need of knowledge creation management as a follow-up concept to knowledge management. The idea behind knowledge creation management is to connect “social innovation, business model generation and a new paradigm software development method” (Konno, 2013, p. 205). According to Konno (2013, p. 206), knowledge creation management can be considered an area that will transform capitalism and society. A paradigm shift in “the traditional theories of management” is required, whereby business organizations move away from the analytical model of management to a more creative one (Konno, 2013, p. 206). In the same chapter Konno (2013) takes Peter Drucker’s ideas and questions about post capitalism (Drucker, 1993) as the starting point for his own answers. Drucker (1993, p. 177) states:

We need an economic theory that puts knowledge into the centre of the wealth-producing process. Such a theory alone can explain the present economy. It alone can explain economic growth. It alone can explain innovation. It alone can explain how the Japanese economy works, and above all, why it works.

While bureaucratic rationalization and mass production techniques were capable of producing economic value in the initial stages of capitalism, Drucker (1993) argues that in today’s economy new factors have come into play and hence new means/techniques for creating value have appeared such as flexible networking and collaboration among knowledge workers. Konno (2013, p. 204) suggests that Drucker (1993) was “sounding a warning to our society and that we should seek such an organizational evolution beyond the industrial society.” Furthermore, Konno (2013, p. 204) argues that knowledge creation theory is one answer to Drucker’s request for a new economic theory, and suggests that we make the transition from knowledge management to knowledge creation management and that we consequently require a new management model.

Paul Mason (2016) also discusses Drucker (1993), though from a different perspective. He concentrates on two questions posed by Drucker (1993). First: “How do we improve the productivity of knowledge?” (Mason, 2016, p. 273). Second: “Who is the social archetype of post capitalism?” (Mason, 2016, p. 274). Dealing with the first question, Mason (2016) argues that humanity came up with a better solution than Drucker’s: the network, where the “focus [is] on ‘connection’ and the modular use of information as the key to productivity” (p. 274). Regarding the second question, Mason (2016) wonders whether it could be Drucker’s “the universal educated person” (p. 275).

This paper adopts a semiotic and, ultimately, generalized model-theoretic approach. Its purpose is to reintroduce Umberto Eco’s semiotic approach to knowledge transfer and knowledge creation, called “narrative fallacy” (Eco, 2011), into managerial thinking and learning to support the ecology of knowledge creation within the grammar of knowledge creation management for prudent capitalism. It will implicitly link Drucker’s (1993) suggestions with Paul Mason’s (2016) equally interesting thoughts on post capitalism and show what we can learn from Umberto Eco (2011) to further develop their ideas.

In Confessions of a Young Novelist (2011), Umberto Eco says that when defending his doctoral dissertation, he was accused (though in a friendly way) of a sort of narrative fallacy because he had presented his research in the style of a “whodunit” narrative as if it were a detective novel. Instead, he should have presented his conclusions. However, this criticism inspired Umberto Eco with the idea that “Every scientific book should be ... the report of a quest for some Holy Grail” (Eco, 2011, p. 7).

In this paper, we will argue that Eco is not only right in certain contexts but that his experience sheds light on the idea that when trying to apply knowledge properly (i.e. considering the limits of the application of knowledge) we have to concentrate on understanding how that knowledge came about (cf. the discussion below on the crash of Air France flight 447 and how prior learning on the coming about and credibility of the data could have helped). We will establish whether it is possible to reduce knowledge to rules and practices (economic or otherwise) so they can be used alongside universal common sense, whether we need to understand any exceptions to these rules/practices as well, and how the background knowledge for the use of the rules/practices could be enriched in practice. Our arguments will be supported by diagrams and real-life cases/examples.

As indicated above, we will also outline a model-theoretic scheme for producing analyses, explanations and actions in the context of reconceiving organizations from the perspective of knowledge and innovation ecosystems. This will be based on an examination of how knowledge comes about in both an explanatory and empirically descriptive and/or operative manner, or action guiding, way, and how the two approaches can be appropriately linked.

Addressing pragmatic incompleteness in managerial learning

In this section, we will look at a case study. Beham Techn. Handels GmbH is an Upper Austrian SME, specializing in the technical products trade (Gatarik & Born, under review). A couple of years ago, the company’s financial situation was far from favourable. It faced massive liquidity difficulties. To avoid undesirable developments, the company decided to take counter-measures. Following advice from the company’s accountant, the CEO— unacquainted with the finer details of tax law—suggested the problem could be solved by following the expert knowledge of his tax adviser. By establishing a new liquidity plan they ought to be able to avert the unfavourable development. This solution was to have been implemented as a new routine for dealing with similar situations; however, the company lacked the sufficient loan guarantees to do so.

With the help of an experienced external business consultant, a new, more extensive liquidity plan was proposed. This plan included the identification and closure of unprofitable business areas. However, it was rejected on the grounds it would only resolve the problem in the short- to mid-term at best. It was correctly deduced that the new plan would not boost the firm’s development and that a long-term alternative had to be found.

In the end, the CEO and the business consultant set up a team of eight hand-picked co-workers to act as management team from that point onwards. Each team member had a different kind of expertise and headed a different department within the firm. All the team members had a common interest in the firm’s long-term success and respected and trusted each other. This enabled the creation of a new kind of knowledge, a kind of meta-knowledge, and ensured that ideas and expertise from different departments were included in the decision-making and problem-solving processes. A dedicated IT system was used to share important information on these processes and the results was shared across the firm.

The outcome of remodelling the organisational structure at Beham GmbH was analysed a decade later. The changes had increased the company’s turnover threefold and allowed them to replace the capital invested by outside parties with internal equity capital generated over about eight years.

What was behind the firm’s success? Was it possible to identify a principle that put the firm on the road to success? At Beham GmbH, they were able to understand what the core issue was and react accordingly by enacting knowledge based organisational structure for creating solutions and reaching decisions. Not only did the management team transfer their knowledge to other processes but the managers learnt hands-on. When managers and other workforce members interact, the incompleteness of managerial learning systems can be addressed. Instead of just providing the content, we need to communicate and integrate knowledge and experience.

The conclusions of research in managerial learning show that in practice successful management requires more than just knowledge (McKenna, Rooney, & Boal, 2009; Kessler, 2006). Some scholars (e.g. Nonaka & Takeuchi, 2011) argue that the extra something is wisdom. McKenna and Biloslavo (2011) proposed social practice wisdom theory, which sees wisdom as non-rational reason aimed at virtuous practical outcomes. While, Intezari and Pauleen (2013) have argued that a decision is wise so long as it has practical, epistemic and moral virtue. Nonetheless, Alammar and Pauleen (2016) found that senior managers view wisdom quite differently, and focus mainly on its practical side: experience and knowledge, emotional intelligence, mentorship, deliberation and consultation. In fact, senior managers leave ethics and spirituality out of their definitions of wisdom.

Although research into managerial wisdom is ongoing, one can argue, based on the above, that managerial wisdom is about how one uses the knowledge one possesses. We seek to expand the existing managerial research by exploring when we should use certain knowledge. In this paper, we propose that Umberto Eco’s approach to the creation of new knowledge and the transfer of existing knowledge—the narrative—can help managers to determine where the limits of that knowledge lie. These limits—kinds of background knowledge—are necessary to prevent rules, regulations or experiences being incorrectly applied.

Let’s imagine what happened at Beham GmbH when the new solution—implementing the new rule—was proposed. The application of such a rule can succeed only providing the tax advisor’s expertise is still available. If it is not, nobody will be able to use the rules anymore, part of the background knowledge will be missing. Explaining how success was achieved is not a sufficient description of the action to be taken.

The importance of background knowledge

High reliability organisations (HROs) are systems typically operating in hazardous environments where the impacts of failures are very high. Creating an HRO system requires significant investment. However, the pay-off is the prevention of dangerous consequences (Weick, Sutcliffe, & Obstfeld, 1999). There is growing interest in applying high reliability principles (Weick & Sutcliffe, 2015) in organisations and this raises questions: Why are some organisations able to successfully convert to HROs while others are not? How do HROs apply knowledge when solving problems?

A recent study on improving processes (Pronovost et al., 2015) looked at how Johns Hopkins Medicine (JHM), Maryland, had implemented high-reliability infrastructure to better manage system quality and safety. Their efforts led to a significant improvement in the care provided (Pronovost et al., 2015). In sharp contrast, Roberts, Desai, and Madsen (2005) found that the Children’s hospital in Back Bay (BBCH) failed to implement key principles. Why was JHM able to benefit from the introduction of HRO but BBCH failed to maintain high reliability principles? By comparing both examples, we can test some of our assumptions about engagement in (managerial) learning as well as our three-step method (see below) in a new way and setting.

At JHM there are established semi-senior managers and others interested in successes firms have had in experiencing and understanding the learning essential to their organisations that has now been incorporated into their business culture. In the case of BBCH, only the “conclusions” (Eco, 2011, p. 7) were presented so there was little understanding or elaboration of the concepts. Specifically, it was observed that since individuals did not promote high reliability processes, the organisation tended to return to its previous mode of operation (Roberts, Desai, & Madsen, 2005). As can be seen, merely trying to implement changes in a system, especially one as complicated as an HRO, is not enough; instead what is required is a sophisticated approach to applying knowledge and engaging those concerned. Organisations must recognize the need for new ways of learning, a kind of learning that does not just mean understanding and explaining results.

To understand JHM’s success, we will analyse its implementation using a three-step method. Very briefly these three steps are:

  1. Heart (emotions) – Analysis of Exploration: This first step involves exploring the explanations for success and failures, i.e. the limits of those explanations. Here we will discuss cases where a lack of knowledge or understanding was the source of the problem.

  2. Brain (reason) – Constructive Structural Normalization: In this second step the cases are compared and any links between them that could be re-operationalized are identified. To understand what the cases share in common means—in some sense—having to go beyond Aristotelian logic because shared commonalities are intangible and have to be constructed somehow. This is rather like the family resemblance of concepts (Wittgenstein, 1953) and we need to understand the exceptions to the rules.

  3. Hands (manufacturing) – Analysis of Replacement: We need to understand how new applications of the structures constructed/identified are realizations or operationalizations. Again, an understanding of the preconditions required for the application to succeed is needed.

The reason JHM experienced such success is undoubtedly a consequence of the extent of organisational learning. The changes were tailored to each section’s needs, while the focus was on the long-term results. By contrast, BBCH simply accepted HRO principles as means of solving short term issues without altering/changing the user-relevant background knowledge. The main point here is that (both in practice and theory) we must recognize and understand the fact that in many important cases our decisions—especially those leading to short term success—are based on faulty explanations (that act as guiding principles), and we therefore create the wrong background knowledge (which has to be explained before being used to guide our decisions). To demonstrate this idea, let us return to the pebble example at the very beginning of this paper: With a lack of background knowledge, we would seriously expect the pebble to fall out even when the person’s palm is facing upwards because we blindly follow the explanatory conclusion we draw from the previous action and do not understand that the true reason for the observable outcome is—according to modern physics—gravity.

If we want to convey knowledge in an organization, we must therefore understand that just teaching/conveying the cognitive part of knowledge is not enough. Metaphorically speaking, we also have to tend the soil on which, for example, the seed of information falls. We must teach not only the explanations but also the constraints so that the limits of applying the rules can be understood and we can develop a feeling as to how far we can go in applying them.

In practice, a kind of aspect blindness also seems to be important. Consequently, we are far too likely to project our theories, maps or models onto reality in an all too straightforward manner, as if they were action guiding and therefore literal descriptions that fill in (or rather bridge) the blind spots of our perceptions. We cannot see the constructive contributions of our minds and most of the time therefore cannot communicate them. Perhaps the film “Balance” (Lauenstein & Lauenstein, 1989) illustrates this point.

If an organization is about to undergo structural change, the classical sets of managerial rules must be viewed differently—as reproducing hitherto unquestioned economic parameter values, and not simply guiding action but having hypothetical explanatory value. That means that the rules should not be perceived as engraved in stone but as systems to create a free space for fantasy and imagination, so the systems of rules can generate routines that win time to create desirable results or solutions. Fantasy and the imagination, Einstein (1929) said, may be “more important than [documented] knowledge since knowledge is limited” relying on shorthand stories/narratives.

The narrative fallacy

Our point is illustrated by the Air France flight 447 disaster described by Oliver, Calvard, and Potočnik (2017). The crash was caused by the malfunctioning of the pitot tubes, which had become clogged up with ice crystals during the high-altitude flight. Pitot tubes convey information on the plane’s altitude and airspeed to the autopilot. Because the tubes became clogged, the autopilot turned off automatically and the pilots had to revert to manual control. This is where a lack of background knowledge and a lack of knowledge about the limits of rules and systems becomes relevant. The presence of the ice crystals in the pitot tubes caused the system to show the wrong altitude values, suggesting the altitude was lower than it in fact was. The pilots subsequently wrongly decided to gain altitude, which caused them to lose speed. When the pitot tubes eventually became clear of the ice crystals, they began showing the correct values. However, by this point the plane had slowed by 90 knots, and the pilots did not believe the readings. It is likely that the pilots were operating according to rules that stipulated they should take certain actions depending on altitude and airspeed. Had the pilots known the limits of this rule (if the tubes malfunction, an altitude lower than the real altitude may be displayed), they would not have made the fatal decision to climb, which led to the loss of speed. Moreover, had they known that the tubes would eventually clear as the ice crystals warmed up and melted, they would have known the speed readings telling them they were going too slowly were accurate, and would not have disregarded them. One of the things the pilots lacked that would have helped them in this situation was background knowledge of the technical side of how the system works. But since they lacked this knowledge, they were unable to handle the situation, and the plane crashed leaving no survivors.

Let’s return to the case of Umberto Eco (2011, p. 7), accused of a sort of narrative fallacy in his doctoral examination because he had presented his dissertation as if it were a detective novel instead of only presenting the conclusions.

[A] mature scholar, when setting out to do some research inevitably proceeds by trial and error, making and rejecting different hypotheses; but at the end of the inquiry, all those attempts should have been digested and the scholar should present only the conclusions. (Eco, 2011, p. 7)

This is obviously considered to be the appropriate academic approach and behaviour. Discussing the results in the proper way (especially when explaining their validity) should therefore also be a means of transferring/conveying some “knowledge”. However, discussing the results is only the cognitive or generalizable part of what knowledge amounts to, and cognition is only one side of the coin. The other side relates to what should we do with the knowledge, or how should we apply it. When we build up (or convey) just a kind of explanatory understanding, it does not help us to apply knowledge properly especially in new situations.

Umberto Eco’s (2011, p. 7) suggestion that “every scientific book must be a sort of whodunit—the report of a quest for some Holy Grail” is quite fascinating because it involves and supports learning engagement in both research and creating/constructing meaning and the application of knowledge. It can also be interpreted as signifying that we have to be able to fully understand the meaning of a case. Put differently, we have to make an effort to properly understand the core of problem. Maybe this has lain unforgotten since the times of the enlightenment. We need to provide the knowledge in a digestible way but the recipient is also tasked with having to make sense of the information conveyed or build up its meaning. This latter requires them to learn things, to be open to new insights and to the creation of a new epistemic resolution level and even be tolerant. These principles do not only apply only to managerial learning but also to learning in general. The practical problem is of course identifying and selecting the right background knowledge (to create meaning), without exerting pressure, but simply offering it up for discussion instead. We must steer a pathway between the (Socratic) ignorance of blind evolution and the arrogance of pretending to know—like stubborn parents making decisions on behalf of their children (thinking that they—like the senior management of a company—know what is good for their children/employees).

Some theory is needed here to explain the issue. Why do we think Eco is right to reject the accusation that he committed a narrative fallacy or was right not to convey only the conclusions of his research? What could be wrong with following the classical procedure? Are there any examples? Yes, but as you perhaps know, practitioners do not like to be reminded of the roots of their knowledge and theoreticians are not fond of keeping their feet on the ground. However, there is a good example of misusing fiction: the prisoners’ dilemma (Tucker, 1950). It does not even describe reality in its simplest form and we forget that originally it was invented to illustrate the ideas of game theory (Crocker, 2009). The only way to transform this fiction into reality would probably be for it to be enacted on stage. Nonetheless, it has been descriptively misunderstood, as being literally action guiding. A rational analysis indicates that the prisoners’ dilemma only accords with the theory if the prisoners defect. If one wants to do the rational thing, one “has to” defect, according to Crocker (2009), who sarcastically states “but at least you would have done the rational thing”, though you would be worse off. We prefer to think of this action as the faulty projection (operationalization) of theory onto reality. However, this example nicely corresponds to our understanding that an explanation may be valuable in one realm but in need of interpretation in other areas. We therefore need a constructive dialogue involving both expertise and lay knowledge, based upon the perhaps wrong assumption of a universally valid common sense, in which the aim is to understand the limits of application stemming from the simplifications around which our theories are built. The dialogue should include engagement or a willingness to strive to understand the limits of the classifications/categorizations we use (or depend on) to orientate ourselves in the world. The general rule is that the conclusions (of our research) should be conveyed as knowledge (about the world or appropriate parts of reality), but that they represent only a small part of the things that are can or must be used to provide guidance for our actions.

The prisoners’ dilemma can explain economic success in specific situations. However, when it is used in a practical/action-guiding way, it leads to the justification of short-sighted actions that rely upon explanations of economic success in which the maximization of individual profit is taken for granted (i.e. accepted as a sort of universal law of nature). Hence it lacks the corrective power of real life consequences, values and the possibility of innovative changes, obtained due to a better understanding of how our theoretical and explanatory theories come or came about. This is where the missing link in the evolution and application of scientific thinking can be found.

In our attempt to draw upon Umberto Eco’s thinking on the practical side of life, we can consider the relation between heart (emotions), brain (reason) and hands (the idea of manufacturing the world or at least tiny parts of it) outlined above. If we start with the heart, intuitively our values become important and we may reflect on or analyse the explorations which lead to (generalizable) results. In the next step (consciously or not) we may intuitively become aware of structures and concentrate either on reproducing a thing in the world or our understanding of the world (by means of argumentation). Meaning cannot just be created by conveying an explanatory argument. The third step involves applying our knowledge to new problems or situations (depending on the classifications or categorizations we tend to choose). It can also be called the analysis of replacement, because we can project our structural insights onto new cases and see the outcome as the operationalization of those structures. We now have the practical means to overcome the shortcomings of the narrative fallacy, where it is too close to stories about individual or personal experiences, and contains nothing else. However, we can also see that the narrative fallacy helps us to understand the cognitive part of our conclusions in an open and more practical way, which supports the pathway to creativity and beyond. The crude theory behind this triangle of heart, brain and hands (which could be used to help select the appropriate means of conveying meaning) contains a significant amount of model-theoretic knowledge and can be understood as a summary of the ideas underlying the geo example (see Figure 2) and can be projected in Figure 3.

Our geo example demonstrates the limitations of explanations. The shortest airborne distance between the two destinations shown on the flat projection differs from that in the spherical model due to the distortion of the surface. If we try to measure the distance on the flat projection, we will obtain the correct findings in this setting. But the spherical model offers a more accurate method of measuring distance, since it better reflects the reality. If we apply our three-step model, the limitations of the flat projection represent the heart, while the comparison with the globe is the brain and the need for correction is the hands and the associated expertise/experience.

Language-Information-Reality (LIR) is a means of analysing the action and argumentation (Gatarik & Born, 2015) in Figure 3 and this can be demonstrated using the Beham GmbH case referred to above. The lack of an adequate budget (represented as P in Figure 3) is—representationally speaking—summarised as the initial situation (S). The difficulty was identified by applying knowledge of the accountant’s rules/routines (shown at K). Because the CEO had insufficient knowledge in this area (folk knowledge in F), the tax adviser was invited to contribute his expertise/expert knowledge (intuition E), so the desirable result (R) could be achieved. This can be formulated as equation H (hypotheses/background knowledge) = {E, F, K}; S R, that is, intuition, folk knowledge and rules/routines create the background knowledge or hypothesis which can be used in the argumentation on the transition from situation (S) to result (R). Producing a practical, real-life solution (Q*) required a new routine (K) to be established. In the language of our model, to solve the undesirable situation (P ==> Q) we implement rules (K) using the lay knowledge (F). The first solution proposed is that in future new rules/routines (K) should be established.

However, the company did not accept the proposed solution. Instead they introduced a management team that could provide the necessary meta-knowledge (explanations M). Our model can therefore be expanded to H = {E, F, K, M}; S R. The additional segment enabled the extended participation of the other components and led to improvements in the communication process. The solution adopted by Beham GmbH is an example of not obeying the rules of explanation and complying with the principles of narrative fallacy—not just giving it validity but understanding it.

Operationalizing engagement

Let us now look at operationalizing engagement in conveying knowledge. First, we must return to our meta-scheme (see Figure 3) to obtain guidance on the decisions we make when selecting certain learning environments. To do so we consider the triangle (see Figure 1) illustrating the procedure as briefly described in the example of a successful HRO implementation (see above):

Figure 1 
            Transferring expertise.
Figure 1

Transferring expertise.

Figure 2 
            Geo example.
Figure 2

Geo example.

Figure 3 
            LIR (Language-Information-Reality) model-theoretic scheme.
Figure 3

LIR (Language-Information-Reality) model-theoretic scheme.

We start with the “analysis of exploration”—analysing things that worked well to understand how acceptable results were arrived at.

The next step in applying the triangle is a sort of “abstraction”. We consider the background knowledge of the people to be expertise, which—technically speaking—could be understood to lead us to identification and normalization of the structures we think they could explain and reproduce some results under investigation. However, this also should be able to reproduce the acceptance of those results in a group of people living or working together. Thus, we do not only reproduce the results/problem solutions (“best practices”) but also the acceptance of the results as “results” by way of persuasion (i.e. if argumentation as such is not enough!). Bluntly speaking, good results do not come about by chance but we have to identify the causality of the matter.

Re-interpreting (in the sense of operationalizing or materializing the procedure or reviewing it) is the last step, which can be called “analysis of replacement”.

This approach involves looking at the assumptions that are key to explaining the classifications or categorizations of (parts of) reality within our own epistemic possibilities and “gifts” within the resolution level/means of distinction (seeing important differences on the one hand and equivalences on the other), which are available in our own maps or representation of the system. To understand this, we suggest looking at some of Ellen Langer’s (2016) experiments, in which reflective learning (she calls it “sideways learning”) is essential to explain the occurrence and replicability of successful problem solutions (“best practices”) in practice.

Conclusions and recommendations for further research

Imagine a man with a pebble in his fist, palm downwards. He opens his fist and (so) the pebble falls to the ground. He repeats the process with his palm upwards. The pebble remains in his hand.

If you were only presented with the result of the first experiment, you would also expect the pebble to fall out in the second one. If we want to be able to understand the core issue, we need to know more than just the conclusions. We can therefore say that a derived conclusion does not necessary generate knowledge.

The following three propositions build upon some of the ideas that are central to our approach:

  1. In order to look at the formalizations or digitalisations of the routines, rules or heuristics that help us to reproduce observable and acceptable results in real life (especially in the current era), we need to consider the background knowledge in use. It can of course be explained but that presupposes trust and engagement on both sides. The problem is whether it is beneficial to presume the existence of a more or less static and universal common sense—the idea that everything can be fully explained in words and then used with no special background knowledge at all. In this case, we could be said to believe in or assume the existence of blind (or guided by God) evolution, which is enough for the progress of mankind, and we definitely do not need any kind of real endeavour on the side of the users. We never need to change anything about our own assumptions or ideologies. The Enlightenment has achieved its aim and a third or a pragmatic enlightenment in the Hilary Putnam (2004) sense, for example, is out of the question.

  2. In contrast to this bit of irony we think that in managerial learning, but also in other fields, it is essential to consider the idea that in the practice of building up knowledge, success does not necessarily stem from strictly obeying rules (procedures aimed at achieving parameter values set as the characteristics of success). Instead, we think that we need to experience the limits of the application of rules and to understand the fuzziness of our concepts, and this may be achieved by considering the preconditions for the application of those rules. In daily life, however, we also have to take into account the desire for trust. We must learn to place our “trust in the rules” and in our peers (and also perhaps life) so that we can educate ourselves on the limits of the rules in an “open” way. This is the idea that unsaturated concepts, also found in Dummett (2000), are indefinitely extensible.

  3. Finally, we need our reading or projection of theories to be reflected in reality, where both cognitive and emotional social learning as a means of achieving the corrective power of intuition or reflection are essential and should be considered in the way that Antonio R. Damasio’s (2003) brain research on emotions is. This means that “teaching” the skills to optimize the production of the right parameter values (considered key to resolving all problem situations) is not the same as teaching or building on the skills or means to solve problems.

    Empirical research is needed to confirm the conclusions of this paper. It should focus on how best practices (successful managerial problem solutions) and knowledge can be incorporated into practice, and test whether a detailed narrative approach yields better results and if so in which contexts.

Acknowledgements

We gratefully acknowledge the research assistance by Peter Kelemen and Lukas Dohnal, Masaryk University, Brno. All errors are our own.

References

Alammar, F., & Pauleen, D. (2016). Exploring managers’ conceptions of wisdom as management practice. Journal of Management & Organization, 22(4), 550-565.10.1017/jmo.2015.53Search in Google Scholar

Crocker, L. (2009). Flunking the prisoners’ dilemma. Philosophy Now, 75, 22-23.Search in Google Scholar

Damasio, A. R. (2003). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, sorrow and the feeling brain. Orlando: Hartcourt Books.Search in Google Scholar

Drucker, P. F. (1993). Post-capitalist society. New York: Harper Business.Search in Google Scholar

Dummett, M. (2000). Elements of intuitionism (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780198505242.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Eco, U. (2011). Confessions of a young novelist. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.4159/harvard.9780674060876Search in Google Scholar

Gatarik, E., & Born, R. (2015). Managing network economies: The competitive advantage of commons as ecosystems of innovation. Journal of Organisational Transformation and Social Change, 12(3), 287-307.10.1080/14779633.2015.1101246Search in Google Scholar

Gatarik, E., & Born, R. (under review). Innovating for organisational resilience: An epistemological investigation into business continuity practice in an Austrian SME. Economic Research- Ekonomska Istraživanja.Search in Google Scholar

Intezari, A., & Pauleen, D. J. (2014). Management wisdom in perspective: Are you virtuous enough to succeed in volatile times? Journal of Business Ethics, 120(3), 393-404.10.1007/s10551-013-1666-6Search in Google Scholar

Kessler, E. H. (2006). Organizational wisdom: Human, managerial, and strategic implications. Group & Organization Management, 31(3), 296-299.10.1177/1059601106286883Search in Google Scholar

Konno, N. (2013). Revisiting the ‘knowledge creating firm’ in the ‘post-capitalist society’ context. In von G. Krogh, H. Takeuchi, K. Kase, & C. G. Cantón (Eds.), Towards organizational knowledge: The pioneering work of Ikujiro Nonaka (chap. 11, pp. 203-218). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1057/9781137024961_12Search in Google Scholar

Langer, E. (2016). The power of mindful learning (2nd ed.). Boston: Da Capo Press.Search in Google Scholar

Lauenstein, Ch., & Lauenstein, W. (1989). Balance (film). Hochschule für Bildende Künste Hamburg, Gesamthochschule Kassel.Search in Google Scholar

Mason, P. (2016). Postcapitalism: A guide to our future. eBook. London: Penguin Books.Search in Google Scholar

McKenna, B., & Biloslavo, R. (2011). Human flourishing as a foundation for a new sustainability oriented business school curriculum: Open questions and possible answers. Journal of Management & Organization, 17(5), 691-710.10.5172/jmo.2011.17.5.691Search in Google Scholar

McKenna, B., Rooney, D., & Boal, K. B. (2009). Wisdom principles as a meta-theoretical basis for evaluating leadership. The Leadership Quarterly, 20(2), 177-190.10.1016/j.leaqua.2009.01.013Search in Google Scholar

Nonaka, I., & Konno, N. (1998). The concept of “ba”: Building a foundation for knowledge creation. California Management Review, 40(3), 40-54.10.2307/41165942Search in Google Scholar

Nonaka, I., & Takeuchi, H. (2011). The wise leader. Harvard Business Review, 89(5), 58-67.Search in Google Scholar

Oliver, N., Calvard, T., & Potočnik, K. (2017). Cognition, technology, and organizational limits: Lessons from the Air France 447 disaster. Organization Science, 28(4), 729-743.10.1287/orsc.2017.1138Search in Google Scholar

Pronovost, P. J., Armstrong, C. M., Demski, R., Callender, T., Winner, L., Miller, M.R., Austin, J.M., Berenholtz, S.M., Yang, T., Peterson, R.R., Reitz, J.A., Bennett. R.G., Broccolino, V.A., Davis, R.O., Gragnolati, B.A., Green, G.E., & Rothman, P.B. (2015). Creating a high-reliability health care system: Improving performance on core processes of care at Johns Hopkins Medicine. Academic Medicine, 90(2), 165-172.10.1097/ACM.0000000000000610Search in Google Scholar

Putnam, H. (2004). Ethics without ontology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.4159/9780674042391Search in Google Scholar

Roberts, K., Desai, V., & Madsen, P. (2005). Reliability enhancement and demise at Back Bay Medical Centre Children’s Hospital. In P. Carayon (Ed.), Handbook of human factors and ergonomics in healthcare and patient safety (pp. 249-258). London: Erlbaum.Search in Google Scholar

Tucker, A. W. (1950). A two-person dilemma. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

von Krogh, G., Takeuchi, H., Kase, K., & Cantón, C. G. (Eds.). (2013). Towards organizational knowledge: The pioneering work of Ikujiro Nonaka. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1057/9781137024961Search in Google Scholar

Weick, K. E., & Sutcliffe, K. M. (2015). Managing the unexpected: Sustained performance in a complex world (3rd ed.). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.10.1002/9781119175834Search in Google Scholar

Weick, K. E., Sutcliffe, K. M., & Obstfeld, D. (1999). Organizing for high reliability: Processes of collective mindfulness. In R. S. Sutton & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organisational behavior (pp.1-123). Stanford: Jai Press.Search in Google Scholar

What life means to Einstein: An interview by George Sylvester Viereck. The Saturday Evening Post, (1929, October 26). Retrieved from: http://www.saturdayeveningpost.com/wp-content/uploads/satevepost/what_life_means_to_einstein.pdf.Search in Google Scholar

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2018-02-08
Published in Print: 2018-01-26

© 2018 Institute for Research in Social Communication, Slovak Academy of Sciences

Downloaded on 25.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/humaff-2018-0001/html
Scroll to top button