The evolution and activities of all professions have been driven and directed primarily by their responsibility to the societies they serve [1]. Medicine is no exception and there is broad consensus that the medical profession exists to serve both individual patients and society in general [2]. Schön has broadly defined these professional activities in medicine as “instrumental problem-solving made rigorous by the application of scientific theory and technique” [3]. Implicit in this definition are two concepts: The activities that the profession performs and the knowledge base that supports those activities. We believe, in the case of medicine, that the instrumental problem-solving activity is diagnostic reasoning and that there is much to be gained from further understanding how that activity and the knowledge base interact with one another to influence learning and practice.
Diagnostic reasoning offers the ultimate value that physicians add to the healthcare equation, as it is the one competency that still sets the medical profession apart from most other health care professional activities. A comprehensive summary of research into diagnostic reasoning is well beyond the scope of this essay, but we would summarize a couple of key themes by stating that diagnosis is heavily dependent on context specific knowledge/experience and that the reasoning processes that are engaged for any given case shift in response to many variables including age, time pressure, fatigue, and similarity to previously seen cases [4]. Despite considerable study into how knowledge is organized and how different forms of knowledge are used, there has been little exploration of how these two concepts of activity and knowledge interact. In the interest of prompting new domains of exploration, we would like to make some observations on specific epistemological issues we feel need clarification in this regard.
One distinction that is derived from cognitive psychology, but has not generally made its way into the diagnostic reasoning literature, is between a) procedural, or problem-solving knowledge [knowledge of how to do things] and b) declarative, semantic or conceptual knowledge [knowledge of things] [5, 6]. By way of analogy, to ride a bicycle effectively (procedural knowledge) does not require knowledge of the mathematical relationship between power, torque and angular velocity in the crank set of the bike (conceptual knowledge). Further, those with such knowledge cannot necessarily ride at a high level. In a medical context, it might be the case that diagnostic reasoning (problem-solving) utilizes a fundamentally different kind of knowledge from one’s conceptual knowledge (e.g., declarative knowledge of the biomedical sciences such as anatomy, physiology and microbiology). Extensive knowledge of these domains in isolation would not enable one to make a diagnosis. Conversely, many lay people, without any formal biomedical knowledge, can diagnose simple conditions they have encountered in their personal experience (i.e., they can problem-solve, albeit at a superficial level). When examining diagnostic practice, the medical education community has not generally distinguished rigorously between these two domains.
For example, Blisset et al. conducted a study asking whether schemas should be used in teaching [7]. The educational psychology literature defines a schema as ‘an organized body of information about some distinct domain of knowledge’ (i.e., in terms that indicate purely conceptual knowledge) [5]. Blisset et al. defined schema-based reasoning as ‘a process in which key clinical features are used to include or exclude sets of diagnoses.’ They randomized second year medical students to learn four cardiac diagnoses using either schema-based or traditional instruction on a high-fidelity cardiopulmonary simulator and found that although learning time and factual knowledge gain did not differ, diagnostic success was higher in the schema-based instruction group. These are practically useful findings, but it is clear that the authors used the word ‘schema’ to refer not only to conceptual knowledge and its arrangement in memory, but also to specific problem-solving algorithms (procedural knowledge), without attempting to distinguish between the two.
Most often when doing things on a day-to day basis we just have to know ‘how to’. How many of us, for example, could explain the detailed workings of an internal combustion engine while driving to work? But sometimes, particularly in situations demanding expertise we have to know the concepts behind the ‘how to’. To succeed in the Tour de France not only requires one to be an expert cyclist in a ‘how do I ride a bike’ sense but also requires detailed conceptual knowledge of determinants of maximum sustainable power. Research in the field of mathematics education suggests that paying closer attention to the relationship between procedural and declarative knowledge might help optimize teaching strategies. Using qualitative methodologies, Voutsina investigated the different types of arithmetic knowledge that young children utilize when solving a multiple-step addition task [8]. The study revealed a dynamic relationship between children’s developing representation of the task, their improved procedures and eventually their more explicit grasp of the conceptual aspects of their strategy, suggesting that conceptual and procedural knowledge in mathematics develop iteratively. Turning such models into an educational intervention, Rittle-Johnson and Koedinger evaluated the instructional benefits of an iterative lesson sequence (alternating between concepts and procedures) compared to a concepts-before-procedures sequence for students learning concepts related to decimals and associated arithmetic procedures [9]. Students in the iterative condition gained significantly more knowledge of arithmetic procedures, including the ability to transfer the procedures to problems with novel features.
In medicine, none of the many studies on the role that basic science knowledge plays in diagnostic reasoning have specifically cast diagnostic reasoning as a distinct form of procedural or problem-solving knowledge that might best be learned iteratively with conceptual knowledge [10, 11]. The work of Woods et al. comes closest in that they broke the mould of looking for the influence of conceptual biomedical knowledge by examining when such concepts are mentioned during diagnostic activity and turned their attention instead to how conceptual knowledge might influence learning in a way that impacts on such activity [12]. To continue the above analogy, the Tour de France rider might benefit greatly from layering learning about mechanical and physical concepts iteratively with physical training; whether or not such concepts would be thought of by the riders during the actual race while gritting their way up a mountain is another matter entirely.
We would suggest that what has traditionally been called ‘vertical’ integration more appropriately be viewed pedagogically as the relationship between procedural and conceptual knowledge [13]. If the integrated teaching and learning of biomedical science and medical problem-solving can be shown to be more effective than their separation in the classroom, this would provide the ultimate repudiation of the century-old Flexnerian ‘two-plus-two’ doctrine while also supplying additional cogent evidence for the value of basic science even if experienced practitioners’ descriptions of their reasoning processes were completely void of biomedical concepts. Recent calls for pedagogical innovations supporting integrated learning in medicine are a move in this direction, but they await formal evaluation of educational effectiveness [14].
While biomedical knowledge might support diagnostic reasoning, where the optimal balance lies remains unclear. As will be well recognized by readers of this new journal, there has been an exponential increase in the amount of biomedical knowledge in recent decades, thereby making it unreasonable to expect any medical student or practitioner to “know” everything in the traditional sense of the word. A century of educational practice since the Flexner report has helped promote the inclusion of much of this material in undergraduate medical curricula despite the real potential for information overload, dooming some of what is learned to be forgotten [15]. While everyone wants their favourite topic to be included in medical school curricula, none of the reports we have seen with regard to the biomedical knowledge that should be taught in medical schools have attempted to define or classify this conceptual biomedical knowledge in the context of the reasoning process of expert physicians. All these reports have either been opinion surveys or simply opinions of students, practicing physicians, or biomedical scientists teaching in medical schools [16–18]. How much of this biomedical knowledge is necessary for solving clinical problems, and how it might be classified, is unclear and awaits further investigation. What is clear from a cognitive load perspective is that the more biomedical knowledge students are forced to keep active in working memory, the less working memory will be available for problem-solving.
In sum, we have argued that diagnostic reasoning is the raison d’etre par excellence for the medical profession, but more importantly, that diagnostic reasoning as a defining professional activity likely requires two kinds of supporting knowledge: conceptual and procedural. We believe that the medical literature to date has not clearly made this epistemological distinction. We also believe that what has traditionally been called vertical integration should be more accurately viewed (and investigated) as the iterative integration of conceptual and problem-solving knowledge, and that the biomedical knowledge taught in medical schools should be defined in the context of diagnostic reasoning. As in the animal and plant kingdoms, we hope that the cross-pollination of ideas (in this case from mathematics education) will strengthen our own medical education species and help advance research in diagnostic reasoning.
Conflict of interest statement The authors declare no conflict of interest.
References
1. Cruess SR, Cruess RL, Steinert Y. Linking the teaching of professionalism to the social contract: a call for cultural humility. Med Teach 2010;32:357–9.10.3109/01421591003692722Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
2. Woollard B, Boelen C. Seeking impact of medical schools on health: meeting the challenges of social accountability. Med Educ 2012;46:21–7.10.1111/j.1365-2923.2011.04081.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
3. Schon DA. The Reflective Practitioner. Basic Books, Inc., 1983. p. 21.Suche in Google Scholar
4. Eva KW. What every teacher needs to know about clinical reasoning. Med Educ 2005;39:98–106.10.1111/j.1365-2929.2004.01972.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
5. Schraw G. Knowledge: Structures And Processes. In: Alexander PA, Winne PH, editors. Handbook of Educational Psychology, 2nd ed. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, 2006:245–63.Suche in Google Scholar
6. De Jong T, Ferguson-Hessler MG. Types and qualities of knowledge. Educ Psychol 1996;31:105–13.10.1207/s15326985ep3102_2Suche in Google Scholar
7. Blissett S, Cavalcanti RB, Sibbald M. Should we teach using schemas? Evidence from a randomised trial. Med Educ 2012;46:815–22.10.1111/j.1365-2923.2012.04311.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
8. Voutsina C. Procedural and conceptual changes in young children’s problem solving. Educ Stud Mathematics 2011;79:193–214.10.1007/s10649-011-9334-1Suche in Google Scholar
9. Rittle-Johnson B, Koedinger K. Iterating between lessons on concepts and procedures can improve mathematics knowledge. Brit J Educat Psychol 2009;79:483–500.10.1348/000709908X398106Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
10. Patel VL, Groen GJ, Scott HM. Biomedical knowledge in explanations of clinical problems by medical students. Med Educ 1988;22:398–406.10.1111/j.1365-2923.1988.tb00774.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
11. Boshuizen H, Schmidt HG. On the role of biomedical knowledge in clinical reasoning by experts, intermediates and novices. Cognitive Sci 1992;16:153–84.10.1207/s15516709cog1602_1Suche in Google Scholar
12. Woods NN, Neville AJ, Levinson AJ, Howey EH, Oczkowski WJ, Norman GR. The Value of basic science in clinical diagnosis. Acad Med 2006;81(10 Supl):S124–7.10.1097/00001888-200610001-00031Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
13. Kulasegaram KM, Martimianakis MA, Mylopoulos M, Whitehead CR, Woods NN. Cognition before curriculum: rethinking the integration of basic science and clinical learning. Acad Med 2013;88:1–8.10.1097/ACM.0b013e3182a45defSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
14. Prober CG, Khan S. Medical education reimagined: a call to action. Acad Med 2013;88:1–4.Suche in Google Scholar
15. Custers EJ, Ten Cate OT. Very long-term retention of basic science knowledge in doctors after graduation. Med Educat 2011;45:422–30.10.1111/j.1365-2923.2010.03889.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
16. Koens F, Custers EJ, Ten Cate OT. Clinical and basic science teachers’ opinions about the required depth of biomedical knowledge for medical students. Med Teach 2006;28:234–8.10.1080/01421590500271183Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
17. Rudland JR, Rennie SC. The determination of the relevance of basic sciences learning objectives to clinical practice using a questionnaire survey. Med Educat 2003;37:962–5.10.1046/j.1365-2923.2003.01671.xSuche in Google Scholar PubMed
18. Bull S, Mattick K. What biomedical science should be included in undergraduate medical courses and how is this decided? Med Teach 2010;32:360–7.10.3109/01421590903434144Suche in Google Scholar PubMed
©2014 by Walter de Gruyter Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Masthead
- Masthead
- Editorials
- Diagnosis: A new era, a new journal
- Essays – Introduction
- Diagnosis – Where It’s Been and Where It’s Going
- Medical diagnosis – the promise
- Imperatives, expediency, and the new diagnosis
- Diagnosing diagnostic failure
- Diagnostic errors: central to patient safety, yet still in the periphery of safety’s radar screen1)
- Foundations of Diagnosis
- Bias: a normal operating characteristic of the diagnosing brain
- Figure and ground in physician misdiagnosis: metacognition and diagnostic norms
- Improving diagnostic performance: some unrecognized obstacles
- Understanding evidence-based diagnosis
- A unified conceptual model for diagnostic errors: underdiagnosis, overdiagnosis, and misdiagnosis
- Perspectives – Patients
- Let patients help with diagnosis
- What’s in a story? Lessons from patients who have suffered diagnostic failure
- The diagnostic field’s players and interactions: from the inside out
- Telltale signs of patient-centered diagnosis
- Perspectives – Physicians – Internal Medicine and Pediatrics
- Stumbling towards a diagnosis
- Connecting the dots: like watching a movie…critically
- Perspectives from a pediatrician about diagnostic errors
- Perspectives – Physicians – Psychiatry
- Detecting diagnostic error in psychiatry
- Perspectives — Physicians – Radiology
- Radiologic errors, past, present and future
- Perspectives – Physicians – Laboratory Medicine
- Errors in clinical laboratory test selection and result interpretation: commonly unrecognized mistakes as a cause of poor patient outcome
- Laboratory-associated and diagnostic errors: a neglected link
- The current and ideal state of anatomic pathology patient safety
- Perspectives — Physicians – Surgery
- Diagnostic conversations: Clinical Decision Making in surgery – Part 1
- Minimizing premature closure and diagnostic error in the Operating Room
- Diagnostic Error – Moving Toward Solutions
- Differential diagnosis: the key to reducing diagnosis error, measuring diagnosis and a mechanism to reduce healthcare costs
- Assessing clinical reasoning: moving from in vitro to in vivo
- What can be done to increase the use of diagnostic decision support systems?
- Learning sciences principles that can inform the construction of new approaches to diagnostic training
- “Preflight Checklists” for diagnosis: a personal experience
- How might mathematics education be used to improve diagnostic reasoning?
- The critical step to reduce diagnostic errors in medicine: addressing the limitations of human information processing
Artikel in diesem Heft
- Masthead
- Masthead
- Editorials
- Diagnosis: A new era, a new journal
- Essays – Introduction
- Diagnosis – Where It’s Been and Where It’s Going
- Medical diagnosis – the promise
- Imperatives, expediency, and the new diagnosis
- Diagnosing diagnostic failure
- Diagnostic errors: central to patient safety, yet still in the periphery of safety’s radar screen1)
- Foundations of Diagnosis
- Bias: a normal operating characteristic of the diagnosing brain
- Figure and ground in physician misdiagnosis: metacognition and diagnostic norms
- Improving diagnostic performance: some unrecognized obstacles
- Understanding evidence-based diagnosis
- A unified conceptual model for diagnostic errors: underdiagnosis, overdiagnosis, and misdiagnosis
- Perspectives – Patients
- Let patients help with diagnosis
- What’s in a story? Lessons from patients who have suffered diagnostic failure
- The diagnostic field’s players and interactions: from the inside out
- Telltale signs of patient-centered diagnosis
- Perspectives – Physicians – Internal Medicine and Pediatrics
- Stumbling towards a diagnosis
- Connecting the dots: like watching a movie…critically
- Perspectives from a pediatrician about diagnostic errors
- Perspectives – Physicians – Psychiatry
- Detecting diagnostic error in psychiatry
- Perspectives — Physicians – Radiology
- Radiologic errors, past, present and future
- Perspectives – Physicians – Laboratory Medicine
- Errors in clinical laboratory test selection and result interpretation: commonly unrecognized mistakes as a cause of poor patient outcome
- Laboratory-associated and diagnostic errors: a neglected link
- The current and ideal state of anatomic pathology patient safety
- Perspectives — Physicians – Surgery
- Diagnostic conversations: Clinical Decision Making in surgery – Part 1
- Minimizing premature closure and diagnostic error in the Operating Room
- Diagnostic Error – Moving Toward Solutions
- Differential diagnosis: the key to reducing diagnosis error, measuring diagnosis and a mechanism to reduce healthcare costs
- Assessing clinical reasoning: moving from in vitro to in vivo
- What can be done to increase the use of diagnostic decision support systems?
- Learning sciences principles that can inform the construction of new approaches to diagnostic training
- “Preflight Checklists” for diagnosis: a personal experience
- How might mathematics education be used to improve diagnostic reasoning?
- The critical step to reduce diagnostic errors in medicine: addressing the limitations of human information processing