Home 14. Bohr’s Response to the Einstein- Podolsky- Rosen Argument
Chapter
Licensed
Unlicensed Requires Authentication

14. Bohr’s Response to the Einstein- Podolsky- Rosen Argument

View more publications by University of Chicago Press
From Data to Quanta
This chapter is in the book From Data to Quanta
14: bohr’s response to the einstein- podolsky- rosen argumentI know that no living person has looked so deeply into the actual abysses of quantum theory as the two of you, and that nobody else sees how necessary are completely radical new conceptions.— Paul Ehrenfest, commenting on Albert Einstein and Niels Bohr 1A perceived paradox at the heart of the newly established quantum me-chanics was advocated in the famous paper by Einstein, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen in 1935. The usual brief textbook summary of the ar-gument (e.g., Howard 2007; Norton 2018) states that since particles must have defi nite observable properties, such as spin, even before any measure-ment is performed on them, quantum mechanics cannot be complete, as it does not account for hidden properties. This leads to the correlation of the spins of two particles— for example, two atoms leaving the molecules because of electrostatic force (the force that does not disturb their spins). Quantum mechanics gives us possible values of the property (of spin) that we choose when performing the measurement, but it cannot give us a full description of the system. The two particles are really separated and, in principle, the measurements can be performed on each particle indepen-dently. What quantum mechanics offers us is just a statistical account of particle ensembles, not of individual states and their properties which lie hidden in the fabric of physical reality and wait to be discovered by a new and better complete theory. As Bohr correctly summarized it: “Einstein here argues that the quantum- mechanical description is to be considered merely as a means of accounting for the average behaviour of a large num-ber of atomic systems and his attitude to the belief that it should offer an exhaustive description of the individual phenomena” (Bohr 1949, 235).As is well known, Bell’s argument (1964), and subsequent experimental tests of it (Aspect, Grangier, and Roger 1982), demonstrated that if quan-tum mechanics correctly predicted the outcomes of measurements, then there was no set of hidden properties of the type that Einstein assumed to exist, that would be consistent with the set of such outcomes.A striking aspect of the Einstein- Podolsky- Rosen (EPR) paper is its
© 2021 University of Chicago Press

14: bohr’s response to the einstein- podolsky- rosen argumentI know that no living person has looked so deeply into the actual abysses of quantum theory as the two of you, and that nobody else sees how necessary are completely radical new conceptions.— Paul Ehrenfest, commenting on Albert Einstein and Niels Bohr 1A perceived paradox at the heart of the newly established quantum me-chanics was advocated in the famous paper by Einstein, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen in 1935. The usual brief textbook summary of the ar-gument (e.g., Howard 2007; Norton 2018) states that since particles must have defi nite observable properties, such as spin, even before any measure-ment is performed on them, quantum mechanics cannot be complete, as it does not account for hidden properties. This leads to the correlation of the spins of two particles— for example, two atoms leaving the molecules because of electrostatic force (the force that does not disturb their spins). Quantum mechanics gives us possible values of the property (of spin) that we choose when performing the measurement, but it cannot give us a full description of the system. The two particles are really separated and, in principle, the measurements can be performed on each particle indepen-dently. What quantum mechanics offers us is just a statistical account of particle ensembles, not of individual states and their properties which lie hidden in the fabric of physical reality and wait to be discovered by a new and better complete theory. As Bohr correctly summarized it: “Einstein here argues that the quantum- mechanical description is to be considered merely as a means of accounting for the average behaviour of a large num-ber of atomic systems and his attitude to the belief that it should offer an exhaustive description of the individual phenomena” (Bohr 1949, 235).As is well known, Bell’s argument (1964), and subsequent experimental tests of it (Aspect, Grangier, and Roger 1982), demonstrated that if quan-tum mechanics correctly predicted the outcomes of measurements, then there was no set of hidden properties of the type that Einstein assumed to exist, that would be consistent with the set of such outcomes.A striking aspect of the Einstein- Podolsky- Rosen (EPR) paper is its
© 2021 University of Chicago Press
Downloaded on 9.10.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.7208/chicago/9780226798479-014/html?srsltid=AfmBOoqNFL2hSmin9c3jxkcxhSkABu8B1YX7-9iEPQ36L40cc9VQ_fz9
Scroll to top button