Abstract
While implicitly assumed, the restriction that the antecedent of ellipsis cannot be base-merged within the ellipsis site has not to our knowledge been explicitly stated or analysed. In this article we discuss a pattern of ellipsis in Spanish, resembling gapping but we argue distinct from it, where ellipsis in the main clause can find its antecedent in some but not all adverbial clauses. The adverbial clauses that cannot provide the antecedent for ellipsis are, we argue, those that would have to be interpreted within the ellipsis site at LF. We argue that this pattern and its restrictions supports LF-identity theories of clausal ellipsis, and also provides evidence that remnants of clausal ellipsis move at LF.
1 Introduction
The goal of this article is to provide an analysis for the Spanish ellipsis construction that is illustrated in (1).
Cuando | Juan | escribe | un | artículo, | María |
|
una | monografía. |
when | Juan | writes | an | article | María | writes | a | monograph |
‘When Juan writes an article, María writes a monograph.’ |
Si | tú | has | corregido | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
|
50 tesis de máster. |
if | you | have | graded | 50 | exams | I | have | graded | 50 master.theses |
‘Whereas you have graded 50 exams, I have graded 50 master theses.’ |
Mientras | tú | creas | problemas, | yo |
|
soluciones. |
while | you | create | problems | I | create | solutions |
‘Whereas you create problems, I create solutions.’ |
Although similar to gapping on the surface, (1) does not display the properties generally associated with gapping. We will refer to the type of ellipsis in (1) Apparent Gapping across Adverbial Clauses (AGAC). The main difference is that in (1), the ellipsis site and the antecedent are separated by a subordinate clause boundary, while typical gapping is confined to coordinate structures, as in the English examples in (2) (see e.g., Jackendoff 1971; Johnson 2009; Toosarvandani 2013, among many others) and comparative clauses (which may be themselves instances of coordinates; cf. footnote 2).
Mary bought a house and John |
Mary has more books than John |
*Mary bought a house [after John |
*[After John bought a car], Mary |
The close relation between gapping and coordinate structures illustrated in (2) has been attributed to a No Embedding constraint (Hankamer 1979): a gapped clause and its antecedent must be at the same level of syntactic embedding with respect to each other (i.e. must be coordinated). It has been argued that gapping in Spanish can violate this constraint, allowing gapping across complement clauses (Brucart 1999; Bîlbîie and de la Fuente 2019; Bonke and Repp 2022). One of the contributions of this article is to characterize AGAC and compare it to gapping, see Section 2.1.
A second contribution is to determine the distribution of AGAC. Not all types of adverbial clauses may be antecedents for AGAC. Temporal clauses with antes de que ‘before’ or después de que ‘after’ appear to pattern with English, and behave as predicted by the No Embedding constraint, (3).
*Después | de | que | Juan | compró | un | coche, |
María |
una | casa. |
after | of | that | Juan | bought | a | car, | María bought | a | house |
Intended: ‘After Juan bought a car, María bought a house.’ |
*Antes | de | que | tú | corrigieras | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
50 | tesis. |
before | of | that | you | graded.sbj | 50 | exams | I | graded | 50 | theses |
Intended: ‘Before you graded 50 exams, I graded 50 theses.’ |
However, all adjunct clauses can provide the antecedent if the ellipsis site is embedded in a complement clause, (4), as we will see in Section 2.1 below:
Mientras | Juan | corregía | 50 | exámenes, | María | afirmó | [que | ella |
|
while | Juan | graded.impf | 50 | exams | María | claimed | that | she | graded.impf |
100]. | |||||||||
100. | |||||||||
‘While Juan was grading 50 exams, Maria claimed that she was grading 100.’ |
Beyond this empirical contribution, we propose that adjuncts can provide an antecedent for ellipsis provided they are in the right structural configuration with the ellipsis site at LF. The adjunct that provides the antecedent for ellipsis must not itself be interpreted within the domain that is elided. Adjuncts of the type in (1) – which are a subset of the adjuncts that Haegeman (2012) identifies as peripheral adjuncts – are merged outside of the elided domain, while temporal adjuncts as in (3) must be central adjuncts that are merged within it, and so cannot themselves provide the antecedents for ellipsis.
The article proceeds as follows: In Section 2 we describe the empirical pattern of AGAC, investigating the size of the ellipsis site and the height of adjunction. Section 3 lays out our analysis: LF-identity systematically rules out cases of ellipsis-contained antecedents. In Section 4 we discuss implications for crosslinguistic variation and conclude.
2 Spanish ellipsis with adverbial clause antecedents
2.1 Spanish AGAC as TP-ellipsis
We characterize Spanish AGAC as TP-ellipsis, similar to what Fernández-Sánchez (2023) has proposed for modal complement ellipsis. One piece of evidence for this comes from verb movement. Spanish has obligatory V-to-T movement (e.g. Zagona 2002), making the minimal ellipsis site for verb-deleting processes TP. Additionally, auxiliaries, hosted in T, can never surface overtly when gapping (5a) or AGAC (5b) occurs, i.e., when the lexical verb is deleted and two remnants survive. Auxiliaries have to be part of the deleted phrase (Reglero 2006), see (5).
María | había | hablado | con | mi | hermano | y | Juan | (*había) |
María | has | spoken | with | my | brother | and | Juan | has |
|
con | mi | hermana. | |||||
spoken | with | my | sister | |||||
‘María has spoken with my brother and Juan with my sister.’ |
Si | tú | vas | a | corregir | 30 | exámenes, | yo | (*voy) |
a |
if | you | are.going | to | grade | 30 | exams | I | am.going | to grade |
50. | |||||||||
50 | |||||||||
‘Whereas you are going to grade 30 exams, I am going to grade 50.’ |
Additional evidence that AGAC deletes at least up to TP comes from the impossibility of voice mismatches between antecedent and ellipsis site. Neither gapping (6) nor AGAC (7) allow voice mismatches, as expected if the ellipsis site contains Voice.
*Las | ideas | de | Hundertwasser | son | respetadas | por | eruditos | y | ||
the | ideas | of | Hundertwasser | aux.pass | respected | by | experts | and | ||
profanos |
|
su | obra | actual. | ||||||
laypeople | respect.act | his | work | actual | ||||||
Intended: ‘Hundertwasser’s ideas are respected by experts and laypeople respect his actual work.’ |
*Los | laicos | respetan | el | trabajo | real | de | Hundertwasser | ||||
the | laypeople | respect.act | the | work | real | of | Hundertwasser | ||||
y | sus | ideas |
|
|
por | los | estudiosos. | ||||
and | his | ideas | aux.pass | respected | by | the | experts | ||||
Intended: ‘Laypeople respect Hundertwasser’s actual work and his ideas are respected by the experts.’ (based on Merchant 2008:170) |
*Si | tú | corregiste | 30 | exámenes, | 50 |
|
|
por | mí. | |
if | you | graded.pfv | 30 | exams | 50 | aux.pass.pst | graded | by | me | |
Intended: ‘Whereas you corrected 30 exams, 50 were corrected by me.’ |
*Si | 30 | exámenes | fueron | corregidos | por | ti, | yo |
|
50. | |
if | 30 | exams | aux.pass.pst | graded | by | you | I | graded | 50 | |
Intended: ‘Whereas 30 exams were graded by you, I graded 50.’ |
Finally, Spanish AGAC allows non-subject remnants, (8). This confirms that the ellipsis site must be large enough to contain the derived subject position in Spec,TP, therefore supporting the conclusion that AGAC elides a constituent at least as big as TP.
Si | a | su | hija | le | compraron | una | nevera, | a | su | hijo | ||
if | to | their | daughter | her | bought.3pl | a | fridge, | to | their | son | ||
|
una | casa. | ||||||||||
him bought | a | house | ||||||||||
‘Whereas they bought their daughter (only) a fridge, they bought their son a house’ |
As we have described the pattern, Spanish AGAC seems to closely resemble gapping in terms of what is elided. However, Spanish AGAC empirically differs from Spanish gapping with respect to the licensing of determiner sharing, i.e., the interpretation of a single overt determiner on two NPs (e.g., Johnson 2000; Arregi and Centeno 2005). In Spanish, determiner sharing is available across gapped coordinations (9), but not in the cases we have identified as AGAC (10).
Muchos | estudiantes | obtuvieron | becas | y |
|
profesores | |
many | students | received | grants | and | many | professors | |
|
proyectos. | ||||||
received | projects | ||||||
‘Many students received grants and many professors received projects.’ |
*Si | muchos | estudiantes | obtuvieron | becas, |
|
profesores | ||
if | many | students | received | grants | many | professors | ||
|
proyectos. | |||||||
received | projects | |||||||
Intended: ‘If many students received grants, many professors received projects.’ |
We preliminarily conclude from this that there are actually two possible derivations in Spanish for constructions which on the surface look like gapping: a coordinate structure patterning mostly with English gapping (9) and the AGAC structure (10), which elides a bigger constituent than English gapping.[1]
2.2 Premise conditionals and AGAC
As mentioned above, not all types of adverbial clauses can be antecedents for AGAC. Conditional clauses can provide an antecedent, as in (1b) – but only on a particular reading of the conditional clause. Conditionals that license AGAC are not true hypothetical conditionals, but so-called premise or factual conditionals (Castroviejo and Mayol 2024; Iatridou 1991; Schwenter 1999), illustrated in (11). Premise conditionals are used to structure the discourse by making manifest a proposition that is privileged as the context to properly assess the following clause (Haegeman 2003: 317).
If Bill is so unhappy here, he should leave. |
(adapted from Iatridou 1991) |
For instance, in (11) the speaker is not setting a condition for Bill to leave, which the truth value of the proposition depends on. The speaker is highlighting a premise, often one which echoes a previous assertion in context, which is presented as background to assess the speaker’s claim, which is that Bill should leave.
The premise conditional structure which can provide the antecedent for AGAC has recently been thoroughly analysed by Castroviejo and Mayol (2019, 2021, 2024), who term them echoic contrastive conditionals. They are echoic, as the protasis is naturally interpreted as directly reproducing a claim made earlier by the interlocutor (rather than setting up a true conditional relationship between the truth of the protasis and apodosis). In fact, in (1b) above, repeated here as (12), the natural interpretation is that the interlocutor has just boasted or complained that he graded 50 exams.
Si | tú | has | corregido | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
|
50 |
if | you | have | graded | 50 | exams | I | have | graded | 50 |
tesis de máster. | |||||||||
master.theses | |||||||||
‘Whereas you have graded 50 exams, I have graded 50 master theses.’ |
True hypothetical conditionals can be distinguished from such echoic or factual conditionals in various ways. Premise conditionals reject focus particles like only or even as modifiers of the protasis (Bhatt and Pancheva 2006), perhaps because the protasis acts as a theme that sets a background to evaluate the consequent of the conditional. (13) is infelicitous on the ‘premise’ reading, presupposing that Bill is unhappy.
#Only if Bill is so unhappy should he leave. |
Accordingly, adding focus markers to the conditionals in Spanish is incompatible with AGAC, (14), indicating that the antecedent-providing adverbial is not a hypothetical conditional.
(*Solo) | si | tú | has | corregido | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
|
||
only | if | you | have | graded | 50 | exams | I | have | graded | ||
50 | tesis. | ||||||||||
50 | theses. | ||||||||||
Intended: ‘Only if you (really) have graded 50 exams, I have graded 50 theses.’ |
For the same reason, the protasis of premise conditionals cannot be focused by clefting (15a), and again focus by clefting is incompatible with AGAC in Spanish (15b).
*It is if Bill is so unhappy that he should leave. |
*Es | [si | tú | has | corregido | 50 | exámenes] | que | yo |
|
|
|||
it.is | [if | you | have | graded | 50 | exams | that | I | have | graded | |||
50 | tesis. | ||||||||||||
50 | theses | ||||||||||||
Intended: ‘It is only if you have graded 50 exams that I have graded 50 theses.’ |
Sequence of tense and mood also illuminate the contrast. Spanish has a contrast between indicative and subjunctive in finite verbs (Quer 1998). Indicative mood is compulsorily used in premise conditionals, while subjunctive is used in the protasis of true hypothetical conditionals, enforcing a verb in conditional in the consequent (see RAE and ASALE 2009:§47.8 for a detailed description). Again, AGAC is impossible if the protasis contains a verb in subjunctive: (16) sharply contrasts with (12) above.
Si | tú | corrigie-ra-s | 50 | exámenes, | yo | *(corregi-ría) | 50 | tesis. |
if | you | graded-sbjv-2sg | 50 | exams | I | grade-cond.1sg | 50 | theses |
Intended: ‘If you graded 50 exams, I would grade 50 theses.’ |
While the subordinator si allows both hypothetical and non-hypothetical interpretations, other conditional expressions are specialised for hypothetical meanings, with verbs in the subjunctive and always subject to sequence of tense: this is the case of con tal de que ‘provided that’ and en caso de que ‘in case’, as well as siempre y cuando ‘just in case’. None of these subordinators allows a premise conditional interpretation, and none of them licenses AGAC in the apodosis, (17).
#{Con | tal | de | que/ | En | caso | de | que} | Juan | se | sienta | |||
with | such | of | that | in | case | of | that | Juan | se | feel.sbjv.3sg | |||
tan | mal, | debe | irse. | ||||||||||
so | bad | should | leave | ||||||||||
Intended: ‘{Provided that/In case} Juan feels so bad, he should leave.’ |
*{Con | tal | de | que/ | En | caso | de | que} | tú | corrigieras | 50 | |||
{with | such | of | that | in | case | of | that | you | grade.sbjv | 50 | |||
exámenes, | yo |
|
100. | ||||||||||
exams | I | grade.cond | 100 | ||||||||||
Intended: ‘{Provided that/In case} you graded 50 exams, I would grade 50 theses.’ |
2.3 Other adverbial clauses and AGAC
Some non-conditional clauses can provide the antecedent for AGAC, precisely to the extent that they can have such high ‘factual’ or ‘discourse-structuring’ readings. The subordinator cuando ‘when’ allows a temporal reading or a ‘factual’, ‘discourse-structuring’ reading. The temporal reading can be controlled for by adding entonces ‘then’, and is subject to sequence of tense restrictions. (18) with entonces forces the temporal reading where María paints only during the same time period as Juan draws. (18) without entonces is ambiguous between the two readings.
Cuando | Juan | hace | dibujos, | (entonces) | María | hace | cuadros. |
when | Juan | makes | drawings | then | María | makes | paintings |
‘When Juan makes drawings, María makes paintings.’ | |||||||
‘Whereas Juan makes drawings, María makes paintings.’ (only without entonces) |
AGAC is only possible in the non-temporal condition without entonces, (19).
Cuando | Juan | hace | dibujos, | (*entonces) | María |
|
cuadros. |
when | Juan | makes | drawings | then | María | makes | paintings |
‘Whereas Juan makes drawings, María makes paintings.’ |
A similar situation arises with mientras ‘while’. Normatively in modern Spanish, mientras ‘while’ only has a temporal simultaneity reading (20a) which enforces imperfective tenses, and mientras que ‘whereas’ should be used for an adversative contrast reading (20b), which allows perfective tenses. However, many speakers use mientras for both meanings. Only the non-temporal reading of mientras allows AGAC, as (1c), repeated here as (21), illustrates.
Mientras | yo | vivía | en | Madrid, | tú | y | yo | casi | no | |
while | I | live.impf | in | Madrid | you | and | I | almost | not | |
hablábamos. | ||||||||||
talk.impf | ||||||||||
‘While I was living in Madrid, you and I had almost no contact.’ |
Mientras | (que) | yo | viví | en | Madrid, | tú | viviste | en | Barcelona. |
while | that | I | live.pfv | in | Madrid | you | live.pfv | in | Barcelona |
‘Whereas I lived in Madrid, you lived in Barcelona.’ |
Mientras | (que) tú | creas | problemas, | yo |
|
soluciones. |
while | (that)you | create | problems | I | create | solutions |
‘Whereas you create problems, I create solutions.’ |
Concessive clauses also show a contrast. The Spanish literature has identified two main types of concessive clauses (see e.g. Flamenco 1999): restrictive concessives (22a), where the two clauses are temporally autonomous from each other and indicative must be used, and pure concessives (22b), where subjunctive is used and there must be a correlation, parallel to hypothetical conditionals, between the temporal forms used in each.
Aunque | ya | es | tarde, | continuaremos | la | reunión. |
although | already | is | late | continue.fut.1pl | the | meeting |
‘Even though it is late, we will continue the meeting’ |
Aunque | ya | fuera | tarde, | continuaríamos | la | reunión. |
although | already | was.sbjv | late | continue.cond.1pl | the | meeting |
‘Even if it was already late, we would continue the meeting’ |
Only the first reading, which directly expresses opposition between two existing facts, licenses AGAC, (23).
Aunque | tú | corregiste | 50 | exámenes | ayer, | María | (mañana) | ||
although | you | grade.pfv | 50 | exams | yesterday | María | tomorrow | ||
|
100. | ||||||||
grade.fut | 100 | ||||||||
‘Even though you graded 50 exams yesterday, María will grade 100 tomorrow.’ |
*Aunque | tú | corrigieras | 50 | exámenes, | María (mañana) |
|
||
although | you | graded.sbjv | 50 | exams | María tomorrow | grade.cond | ||
100. | ||||||||
100 | ||||||||
Intended: ‘Even if you graded 50 exams, María would grade 100 tomorrow’ |
Temporal clauses with antes de que ‘before’, después de que ‘after’, cada vez que ‘whenever’ cannot provide the antecedent for AGAC (irrespective of whether the verb is in indicative or in subjunctive), see (24).[2]
*Antes | de | que | tú | corrigieras | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
50 | ||
before | of | that | you | graded.sbjv | 50 | exams | I | graded | 50 | ||
tesis. | |||||||||||
theses | |||||||||||
Intended: ‘Before you graded 50 exams, I graded 50 theses.’ |
*Cada | vez | que | tú | corregiste | 50 | exámenes, | yo |
|
50 | ||
each | time | that | you | graded | 50 | exams | I | graded | 50 | ||
tesis. | |||||||||||
theses’ | |||||||||||
Intended: ‘Whenever you graded 50 exams, I graded 50 theses.’ |
We argue that what differentiates the possible antecedents from the impossible ones is the position in the tree to which they are adjoined, with clauses that do not license AGAC being base merged within TP.
2.4 Peripheral versus central adverbial clauses
Haegeman (2012) and Frey (2011), among many others, have divided adverbial clauses into three groups, based on their degree of interaction with the host clause: non-integrated clauses, peripheral clauses, and central clauses. We will limit discussion to the latter two groups. Central adverbial clauses (CACs) are merged low and are dependent on the host clause, for instance with respect to tense, aspect, and mood. Peripheral adverbial clauses (PACs) show a more independent behaviour, and are merged at a higher position. We demonstrate in this subsection that adverbials which can provide the antecedent for ellipsis pattern with PACs, and non-antecedent adverbials pattern with CACs.
Sequence of tense provides one diagnostic (Badan and Haegeman 2022). A configuration like (25), with perfective past in the host clause and perfective future in the adverbial, does not follow a sequence of tense. Correlatively, (25) can only be interpreted in the adversative or premise reading, i.e., the reading associated with PACs. This is the structure that can license AGAC.
{ Mientras/ | si} | tú | publicarás | un | artículo, | el | año | pasado | yo | ||
while | if | you | publish.fut | an | article | the | year | last | I | ||
|
una | monografía. | |||||||||
publish.pfv | a | monograph | |||||||||
‘Whereas/if you will publish an article, last year I published a monograph.’ |
True temporal (26a) or hypothetical conditionals (26b), on the other hand, respect the sequence of tense, indicating that they are in a low enough position to depend on main clause tense; such structures disallow AGAC.
#Mientras | tú | publicabas | un | artículo, | yo |
|
una | |
while | you | publish.impf | an | article | I | publish.impf | a | |
monografía. | ||||||||
monograph | ||||||||
{Whereas/*At the same time that} you were publishing an article, I was publishing a monograph’ |
*Si | tú | publicaras | un artículo, | yo |
|
una | |
if | you | publish.impf.sbjv | an article | I | publish.cond | a | |
monografía. | |||||||
monograph | |||||||
Intended: ‘If you published an article, I would publish a monograph.’ |
For pure concessive aunque ‘although’ clauses, (27a) shows that a present subjunctive clause can receive a future interpretation dependent on the future tense in the main clause, suggesting that these clauses are CACs merged below the tense of the main clause;[3] such configurations also fail to license AGAC (cf. (23b), repeated here as (27b)).
Aunque | el | dolor | disminuya | mañana, | será | importante | |
although | the | pain | reduces.pres.sbj | tomorrow | will.be | important | |
que | consultes | con | un | médico. | |||
that | consult.2sg | with | a | doctor | |||
‘Even if the pain will subside tomorrow, it will be important that you consult with a doctor.’ |
*Aunque | tu | corrigieras | 50 | exámenes, | María | (mañana) |
|
100. | |
although | you | graded.sbjv | 50 | exams | María | tomorrow | grade.cond | 100 | |
Intended: ‘Even if you graded 50 exams, María would grade 100 tomorrow’ |
In addition, AGAC-licensing adjuncts cannot be in the scope of focal operators like only or even. Recall the contrast in (14): ellipsis is only possible without the focal operator.
Furthermore, temporal and adversative readings of mientras differ in binding possibilities. A subject in the host clause can bind a pronoun in the adverbial clause only if it is a CAC. In (28), only the temporal reading of mientras is available under variable binding. This indicates that the temporal adverbial is c-commanded by the subject of the main clause. The adversative reading is impossible, suggesting again that those antecedents that provide antecedents for AGAC, e.g., adversative mientras, are PACs, merged high in the left periphery.
Mientras | proi | tiene | mucho | dinero, | ninguno i | de | los | oligarcas | está | |
while | he | has | a.lot | money | none | of | the | oligarch | is | |
contento. | ||||||||||
happy | ||||||||||
‘At the time when hei has a lot of money, no oligarchi is happy.’ | ||||||||||
*‘Whereas hei has a lot of money, no oligarchi is happy.’ |
This is also true of restrictive concessives: variable binding is impossible with an adverbial headed by aunque ‘although’ in the restrictive indicative reading with indicative mood (29a), while it is available in the pure concessive hypothetical use with subjunctive mood in the adjunct (29b).
*Aunque | proi | tiene | mucho | dinero, | ninguno i | de | los | oligarcas | está |
while | pro | has | a.lot | money | none | of | the | oligarchs | is |
contento. | |||||||||
happy |
Aunque | proi | tenga | mucho | dinero, | ninguno i | de | los | oligarcas | |
while | pro | has.sbjv | a.lot | money | none | of | the | oligarchs | |
está | contento. | ||||||||
is | happy | ||||||||
‘Even if hei has a lot of money, no oligarchi is happy.’ |
The ellipsis-licensing adjuncts thus pattern with Haegeman and Badan’s (2022) characterization of peripheral adjuncts, while the adjuncts that cannot license AGAC show properties of CACs.[4]
2.5 All adverbial clauses license AGAC if outside the ellipsis clause
To complete the empirical picture, the distinction between central and peripheral adverbial clauses dissolves when they are adjoined within a clause which subordinates the AGAC clause, as can be seen in (30).
Mientras | Juan | corregía | 50 | exámenes, | María | afirmó | [que | ella | |
while | Juan | graded.impf | 50 | exams | María | claimed | that | she | |
|
100]. | ||||||||
graded.impf | 100. | ||||||||
‘While [temporal or adversative] Juan was grading 50 exams, Maria claimed that she was grading 100.’ |
In contrast with the examples presented in Section 2.4, the while-clause in (30) provides the antecedent even though it is a central temporal clause with purely temporal reading. Similarly, if the propositional content of the adverbial clause is established in a previous clause, as in (31), AGAC also becomes possible with central adverbial clauses.
Juan | compró | un | coche. | Después | de | que | compró | un | coche, | María | |||
Juan | bought | a | car | after | of | that | bought | a | car | María | |||
|
una | casa. | |||||||||||
bought | a | house | |||||||||||
‘Juan bought a car. After he bought a car, María bought a house. |
The generalisation is that the adverbial clause licenses AGAC provided that it is outside the sentence that undergoes ellipsis. If this condition is met, temporal clauses, hypothetical conditionals, concessives and all other central clauses – which we do not illustrate for reasons of space – can provide the antecedent for AGAC.
3 Analysis
3.1 No antecedents inside ellipsis sites
We adopt the ‘move-and-elide’ or ‘evacuating movement’ approach to clausal ellipsis (e.g., Merchant 2004; Sailor and Thoms 2014; Weir 2014; Broekhuis 2018; Schwarzer 2024). The two remnants of AGAC move to a left-peripheral position in the clause, with the rest of the clause being elided. (For simplicity we show the left periphery as a recursive CP here; of course it may have a more fine-grained cartographic structure à la Rizzi 1997.)[5]
Cuando | Juan | escribe | un | artículo, | María |
|
una | monografía. |
when | Juan | writes | an | article | María | writes | a | monograph |
‘When Juan writes an article, María writes a monograph.’ |
[CP cuando Juan escribe un artículo [CP María1 [CP una monografía2 |
The question is under what circumstances ellipsis can take place, i.e. what can provide the antecedent and how. In the previous section, we have seen that adjunct clauses that can be antecedents for AGAC are merged outside of the elided TP, while adjuncts that cannot be antecedents for AGAC are contained within the elided TP. The generalization we therefore pursue is that adjuncts that cannot be antecedents for AGAC are those that are interpreted within the very material that is elided, while adjuncts that can be antecedents are interpreted external to the ellipsis site.
The generalization that an ellipsis site cannot contain its own antecedent seems intuitively logical and simply stated. However, we believe it is not a trivial conclusion: in particular, if it is correct, it provides evidence (a) that ellipsis identity (at least in AGAC) is calculated specifically over LFs, and (b) that ellipsis remnants move at LF.
To see this, observe that the surface (pronounced) structure of an example like (33) presumably contains a trace of the movement of the después-clause to the left periphery.
[Después | de | que | Juan | compró | un | coche]1 , | María t 1 | compró | una | |
after | of | that | Juan | bought | a | car | María | bought | a | |
casa. | ||||||||||
house | ||||||||||
‘After Juan bought a car, María bought a house.’ |
In general, clausal ellipsis sites can contain traces which their antecedents do not; for example, ‘sprouting’ cases such as (34).
I know he ate it but I don’t know when |
So, in (33), simply copying the verb from the surface structure which is available in the adverbial clause – and ‘sprouting’ the trace of that very adverbial clause itself – should (one might imagine) suffice to license ellipsis in the main clause; but ellipsis is not possible. (The putative antecedent TP is underlined in (35b).)
*Después | de | que | Juan | compró | un | coche, | María |
|
una | ||
after | of | that | Juan | bought | a | car | María | bought | a | ||
casa. | |||||||||||
house | |||||||||||
Intended: ‘After John bought a car, María bought a house’. |
*[CP [CP Después de que [
TP
Juan compró un coche]]1 [María2 [una casa3 [ |
The failure of ellipsis therefore seems to be semantic: the meaning of the elided TP has to contain the meaning of the central adverbial clause (because CACs are interpreted within TPs, i.e. they fully reconstruct in a structure like (33)), but the meaning of the TP inside the CAC obviously then cannot be identical to the meaning of the elided TP (because one contains the other as a part).
Even this, however, is not wholly trivial to capture. We believe, for example, that one prominent semantic identity condition on ellipsis, Merchant (2001)’s e-GIVENness, would incorrectly permit ellipsis in cases like (33).[6] The reason is that Merchant’s e-GIVENness calculates mutual entailment ‘up to’ the existential closure of traces, variables, and focused elements in antecedent and ellipsis site. This can be seen in a contrast sluicing example such as (36).
Mary saw [JOHN]
F
, but I don’t know who ELSE |
Existential closure of antecedent Mary saw [JOHN] F : |
∃x. Mary saw x |
Existential closure of ellipsis site Mary saw t: |
∃x. Mary saw x |
Mutual entailment holds between (b) and (c), so ellipsis is licensed. |
Now consider the LF of (33) – with the CAC reconstructed to its base position. Even when reconstructed, the CAC is presumably in focus here; it is not deaccented, it is new information,[7] and (on the surface) it is pronounced in the clausal left-periphery, as is common for information-structurally distinguished material. Yet if the CAC is in focus, e-GIVENness should – contrary to fact – license ellipsis here, as shown in (37).
LF of (33): |
[[María]F [compró [una casa]F [después de que [Juan] F compró [un coche] F]F ] |
Existential closure of antecedent ( [Juan] F compró [un coche] F , underlined above): |
∃x.∃y.x bought y |
Existential closure of elided clause (i.e. all of (a)): |
∃x.∃y.∃t.x bought y at time t |
Mutual entailment holds between (b) and (c) (because if x bought y, then x must have bought y at some time t), so ellipsis should be licensed, contrary to fact. |
We suggest that the pattern seen in AGAC can be best explained under two assumptions: (a) clausal ellipsis is licensed under identity of LFs (after reconstruction of elements such as CACs),[8] and (b) ellipsis remnants move at LF (that is, they do not themselves reconstruct). In the following sections, we step through how this derives the observed patterns.
3.2 AGAC within the same clause
We have shown in Section 2.4 that the adverbial clauses that can provide antecedents for AGAC are PACs, specifically adverbials that, like the premise conditionals analysed by Castroviejo and Mayol (2019), are used to contrast two situations.
Si | Juan | compró | un | coche, | María |
|
una | casa. |
if | Juan | bought | a | car | María | bought | a | house |
‘Whereas Juan bought a car, María bought a house.’ |
![]() |
We assume that within the LF of the PAC si Juan compró un coche, the contrastive topics Juan and un coche move, so that the LF of CPPAC above is as in (40):
![]() |
The elided TP in (39) is therefore LF-identical to the TP inside the PAC (40), and so ellipsis is licensed. Note that the ellipsis remnants must be taken to move at LF, not just PF (contra Weir 2014); if they did not, the right identity would not be obtained (because Juan ≠ María and un coche ≠ una casa).
By contrast, adjuncts which reconstruct into the ellipsis site at LF cannot be the antecedent for ellipsis. This is the case with central adverbial clauses such as hypothetical si ‘if’, pure concessive aunque, and temporal cuando and mientras ‘when’, as well as clauses introduced by antes de que ‘before’ and después de que ‘after’. (41) represents their position within the TP, at LF.
![]() |
Suppose the following (putative) LF structure in (43), which attempts to create an ellipsis-licensing configuration for (the ungrammatical) (42).
*Después | de | que | Juan | compró | un | coche, | María |
|
una | casa. | |
after | of | that | Juan | bought | a | car | María | bought | a | house | |
Intended: ‘After John bought a car, María bought a house’. |
![]() |
The two TPs that would have to be LF-identical are shown in boxes; but this is obviously impossible, as the higher TP contains the CAC itself, while the lower TP does not.
3.3 AGAC from a different clause
As we saw in Section 2.5, the central versus peripheral distinction dissolves when the antecedent TP is already merged outside the clause which undergoes AGAC. This is predicted by the present account. As long as the antecedent TP is not contained within the ellipsis site, it can provide the antecedent for ellipsis:
Mientras | Juan | corregía | 50 | exámenes, | María | afirmó | [que | ella | |
while | Juan | graded.impf | 50 | exams | María | claimed | that | she | |
|
100]. | ||||||||
graded.impf | 100. | ||||||||
‘While [temporal or adversative] Juan was grading 50 exams, Maria claimed that she was grading 100. |
On the temporal reading, the CAC mientras Juan corregía 50 exámenes is interpreted at LF inside the superordinate clause. Because the TP in this CAC (underlined in (45)) is not contained within the ellipsis site at LF, ellipsis is possible:
[CP [TP María [CAC mientras Juan1 50 exámenes2 [
TP t
1
corregía t
2
]] afirmó [CP que ella3 100 exámenes4 |
The same of course goes for antecedents in preceding sentences in discourse, which will of course not be contained within the ellipsis site. The sentence in (46) is grammatical; the antecedent TP is underlined (we abbreviate by not showing the LF-movement of Juan and un coche).
Juan compró un coche. | Después | de | que | compró | un | coche, | |||||||
Juan | bought | a | car | after | of | that | bought | a | car | ||||
María |
|
una | casa. | ||||||||||
María | bought | a | house | ||||||||||
‘Juan bought a car. After he bought a car, María bought a house. |
Note that the empirical pattern illustrated by (44) indicates that it is not characteristics of the adjunct clauses themselves which account for the asymmetry originally noted between central and peripheral adverbial clauses as antecedents for AGAC. One could imagine arguing, for example, that peripheral adverbial clauses can affect the Question-under-Discussion (QUD, Roberts 2012) while central adverbials cannot, and that clausal ellipsis is anaphoric to the QUD or something similar (AnderBois 2014; Barros 2014; Weir 2014; Griffiths 2019 a.o.). Alternatively, one might argue that PACs, but not CACs, allow for the kind of internal movement that creates the relevant variable-binding configurations at LF (e.g. the movement of Juan and 50 exámenes in (45); see in particular Haegeman 2012 for discussion of movement inside CACs and PACs). However, it appears that any adverbial clause, including central ones, can provide the antecedent for AGAC once it is in the correct syntactic configuration, suggesting that the apparent asymmetry between the classes of adverbial clause is strictly a matter of their syntactic position, rather than their internal syntax or their semantics.[9]
4 Conclusion and implications
In this article, we have examined a to date unnoticed distribution of ellipsis in Spanish: verbal ellipsis with two remnants (termed AGAC) can take an adjoined clause as its antecedent. While superficially similar to gapping, this type of ellipsis differs from it in its distribution and its inability to license determiner sharing. We have argued that the pattern shows that the antecedent cannot be itself contained in the ellipsis site. This pattern is not trivially derived in existing approaches to ellipsis, but it can be derived in an analysis which assumes (a) an LF-identity condition between antecedent and ellipsis site, and (b) LF-movement of the remnants. The identity condition can only be obeyed if the LF of the ellipsis site can find a suitable antecedent in a distinct constituent, concretely either a peripheral adjunct or a superordinate clause.
At this point, a natural question is why this pattern is not freely available in other languages. English disallows adverbial clauses as antecedents for AGAC. We have the impression that gapping in English is truly restricted to coordinate contexts. Johnson’s (2009) non-elliptical, across-the-board-movement analysis of English gapping attempts to capture this. We are inclined to follow this line of thought and assume that AGAC is derived by fundamentally different underlying processes than English gapping (though see Toosarvandani (2013) for criticism): the AGAC we have analysed here for Spanish is true ellipsis of a clause, while the English pattern should be derived in some other way.
Other languages pattern not as straightforwardly. German, for instance, allows gapping-like ellipsis with conditionals (Romero 2000; Schwarz 1998), but not other types of adverbial clauses, (47).
Wenn | einer | hier | irgendwen | besucht, | dann |
|
der | |||
if | anyone.nom | here | anyone.acc | visits | then | visits | the | |||
Peter | die | Anne. | ||||||||
Peter | the | Anne | ||||||||
‘If anybody visits anybody else, then it’s Peter who visits Anne.’ |
*Während | ein | Student | ein | Bier | bestellt, |
|
ein | Professor | |||
whereas | a | student | a | beer | orders | orders | a | professor | |||
einen | Cocktail. | ||||||||||
a | cocktail | ||||||||||
Intended: ‘Whereas a student orders a beer, a professor orders a cocktail.’ |
This raises questions for the comparative analysis of adverbials and ellipsis in these languages that we leave to future research. We hope that this paper will contribute to more crosslinguistic investigation of the properties of gapping and the No Embedding constraint, the nature of identity constraint, as well as potentially different paths to similar surface structures in the realm of ellipsis.
Funding source: NTNU
Funding source: University of Konstanz
Acknowledgements
We are grateful to the editors, to Jeroen van Craenenbroeck and an anonymous reviewer, to the audiences of Sinfonija 17 at the University of Nova Gorica and the workshop on Form and Meaning of Coordination at the university of Göttingen, and to the ForMAAL group at NTNU. All disclaimers apply.
-
Research funding: This research has been supported by NTNU and the University of Konstanz.
References
AnderBois, Scott. 2014. The semantics of sluicing: Beyond truth-conditions. Language 90(4). 887–926. https://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2014.0110.Search in Google Scholar
Arregi, Karlos & Naiara Centeno. 2005. Determiner sharing and cyclicity in wh-movement. In Randall Gess & Edward J. Rubin (eds.), Theoretical and experimental approaches to Romance Linguistics, 1–19. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/cilt.272.02arrSearch in Google Scholar
Badan, Linda & Liliane Haegeman. 2022. The syntax of peripheral adverbial clauses. Journal of Linguistics 58(4). 697–738. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0022226721000463.Search in Google Scholar
Barros, Matthew. 2014. Sluicing and identity in ellipsis. Rutgers University PhD thesis.Search in Google Scholar
Bhatt, Rajesh & Roumyana Pancheva. 2006. Conditionals. In Martin Everaert & Henk van Riemsdijk (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to syntax, 638–687. Oxford: Blackwell.10.1002/9780470996591.ch16Search in Google Scholar
Bîlbîie, Gabriela & Israel de la Fuente. 2019. Can gapping be embedded? Experimental evidence from Spanish. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 4(1). 110. 1–39. https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.782.Search in Google Scholar
Bonke, Max & Sophie Repp. 2022. Complementizer deletion in embedded gapping in Spanish. The Linguistic Review 39(2). 525–555. https://doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2022-2096.Search in Google Scholar
Broekhuis, Hans. 2018. The syntax of Dutch gapping. In Janine Berns & Bert Le Bruyn (eds.), Linguistics in The Netherlands 2018, 19–33. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.10.1075/avt.00002.broSearch in Google Scholar
Brucart, José María. 1999. La elipsis. In Ignacio Bosque & Violeta Demonte (eds.), Gramática descriptiva de la lengua española, 2787–2863. Madrid: Espasa.Search in Google Scholar
Castroviejo, Elena & Laia Mayol. 2019. Echoicity and contrast in Spanish conditionals. The Linguistic Review 36(4). 601–635. https://doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2019-2039.Search in Google Scholar
Castroviejo, Elena & Laia Mayol. 2021. Why premise questions? In P. G. Grosz, L. Martí, H. Pearson, Y. Sudo & S. Zobel (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 25, 205–222. University College London and Queen Mary University of London.Search in Google Scholar
Castroviejo, Elena & Laia Mayol. 2024. Premise conditionals are echoic thematic conditionals. Journal of Pragmatics 225. 34–47. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2024.03.010.Search in Google Scholar
Chung, Sandra, William Ladusaw & James McCloskey. 1995. Sluicing and logical form. Natural Language Semantics 3(3). 239–282. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf01248819.Search in Google Scholar
Chung, Sandra, William Ladusaw & James McCloskey. 2011. Sluicing: Between structure and inference. In Rodrigo Gutiérrez, Line Mikkelsen & Eric Potsdam (eds.), Representing language: Essays in honor of Judith Aissen, 31–50. California: Linguistic Research Center, UC Santa Cruz.Search in Google Scholar
Fernández-Sánchez, Javier. 2023. Spanish modal ellipsis is not null complement anaphora. Linguistics 61(4). 885–913. https://doi.org/10.1515/ling-2021-0077.Search in Google Scholar
Flamenco García, Luis. 1999. Las construcciones concesivas y adversativas. In Ignacio Bosque & Violeta Demonte (eds.), Gramática descriptiva de la lengua española, 3805–3879. Madrid: Espasa.Search in Google Scholar
Fox, Danny & Howard Lasnik. 2003. Successive-cyclic movement and island repair: The difference between sluicing and VP ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 34(1). 143–154. https://doi.org/10.1162/002438903763255959.Search in Google Scholar
Frey, Werner. 2011. Peripheral adverbial clauses, their licensing and the prefield in German. In Eva Breindl, Gisella Ferraresi & Anna Volodina (eds.), Satzverknüpfungen. Zur Interaktion von Form, Bedeutung und Diskursfunktion, 41–79. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110252378.41Search in Google Scholar
Griffiths, James. 2019. A Q-based approach to clausal ellipsis: Deriving the Preposition Stranding and Island Sensitivity generalizations without movement. Glossa 50(3). 571–607.10.5334/gjgl.653Search in Google Scholar
Griffiths, James & Volker Struckmeier. 2021. What does a plausible ‘in-situ’ theory of ellipsis look like? Talk presented at GLOW 44. 15–17. April (fully online).Search in Google Scholar
Haegeman, Liliane. 2003. Conditional clauses: External and internal syntax. Mind and Language 18(4). 317–339. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00230.Search in Google Scholar
Haegeman, Liliane. 2012. Adverbial clauses, main clause phenomena, and the composition of the left periphery. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199858774.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Hankamer, Jorge. 1979. Deletion in coordinate structures. New York: Garland.Search in Google Scholar
Iatridou, Sabine. 1991. Topics in conditionals. MIT PhD thesis.Search in Google Scholar
Jackendoff, Ray. 1971. Gapping and related rules. Linguistic Inquiry 2(1). 21–35.Search in Google Scholar
Johnson, Kyle. 2000. Gapping determiners. In Kerstin Schwabe & Nina Zhang (eds.), Ellipsis in conjunction, 95–115. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110952155-006Search in Google Scholar
Johnson, Kyle. 2009. Gapping is not (VP) ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 40(2). 289–328. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2009.40.2.289.Search in Google Scholar
Lechner, Winfried. 2001. Reduced and phrasal comparatives. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19(4). 683–735. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1013378908052.10.1023/A:1013378908052Search in Google Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2001. The syntax of silence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780199243730.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2004. Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy 27(6). 661–738. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-005-7378-3.Search in Google Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2008. An asymmetry in voice mismatches in VP-ellipsis and pseudogapping. Linguistic Inquiry 39. 169–179. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2008.39.1.169.Search in Google Scholar
Moltmann, Friederike. 1992. Coordination and comparatives. MIT PhD thesis.Search in Google Scholar
Ott, Dennis & Volker Struckmeier. 2018. Particles and deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 49(2). 393–407. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00277.Search in Google Scholar
Quer, Josep. 1998. Mood at the interface. Utrecht: LOT.Search in Google Scholar
RAE and ASALE. 2009. Nueva gramática de la lengua española. Madrid: Espasa.Search in Google Scholar
Reglero, Lara. 2006. Spanish subcomparatives: The “obligatory gapping” strategy. In Nuria Sagarra & Almeida Jacqueline Toribio (eds.), Selected proceedings of the 9th Hispanic linguistics symposium, 67–78. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings.Search in Google Scholar
Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The fine structure of the left periphery. In Liliane Haegeman (ed.), Elements of grammar: Handbook of generative syntax, 281–337. Dordrecht: Kluwer.10.1007/978-94-011-5420-8_7Search in Google Scholar
Roberts, Craige. 2012. Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantic and Pragmatics 5. 1–69. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.5.6.Search in Google Scholar
Romero, Maribel. 2000. Reduced conditionals and focus. In Brendan Jackson & Tanya Matthews (eds.), Proceedings of SALT 10, 149–166. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.10.3765/salt.v10i0.3108Search in Google Scholar
Sailor, Craig & Gary Thoms. 2014. On the non-existence of non-constituent coordination and non-constituent ellipsis. In Robert LaBarge (ed.), Proceedings of WCCFL 31, 361–371. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Search in Google Scholar
Schwarz, Bernhard. 1998. Reduced conditional in German: Event quantification and definiteness. Natural Language Semantics 6(3). 271–301. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1008233732255.10.1023/A:1008233732255Search in Google Scholar
Schwarzer, Luise. 2024. Determiner sharing in German. An argument for movement-based approaches to ellipsis. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783111353746Search in Google Scholar
Schwenter, Scott. 1999. Pragmatics of conditional marking. London: Garland Publishing.Search in Google Scholar
Shen, Zheng. 2017. Fragment answers and movement. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 36(1). 309–321. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9369-9.Search in Google Scholar
Thoms, Gary. 2015. Syntactic identity, Parallelism and accommodated antecedents. Lingua 166. 172–198. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2015.04.005.Search in Google Scholar
Toosarvandani, Maziar. 2013. Gapping is low coordination (plus VP-ellipsis): A reply to Johnson. Santa Cruz: University of California MS.Search in Google Scholar
Vicente, Luis. 2006. Short negative replies in Spanish. In Jeroen van de Weijer & Bettelou Los (eds.), Linguistics in The Netherlands 2006, 199–211.10.1075/avt.23.20vicSearch in Google Scholar
Weir, Andrew. 2014. Fragments and clausal ellipsis. Amherst: University of Massachusetts PhD thesis.Search in Google Scholar
Zagona, Karen. 2002. The syntax of Spanish. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511613234Search in Google Scholar
© 2025 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Articles
- AGREEment and ellipsis
- Coerced inflected infinitives in Portuguese
- Agreement without agree: scattered, not distributed, agreement across modules
- Two routes to predicate ellipsis in Spanish: the clitic versus focus strategy
- Rethinking Right-node Raising
- No ellipsis-contained antecedents: adjunct-licensed ellipsis in Spanish
- Sloppy symmetry under ellipsis
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Articles
- AGREEment and ellipsis
- Coerced inflected infinitives in Portuguese
- Agreement without agree: scattered, not distributed, agreement across modules
- Two routes to predicate ellipsis in Spanish: the clitic versus focus strategy
- Rethinking Right-node Raising
- No ellipsis-contained antecedents: adjunct-licensed ellipsis in Spanish
- Sloppy symmetry under ellipsis