Home Optimal Resort to Court-Appointed Experts
Article
Licensed
Unlicensed Requires Authentication

Optimal Resort to Court-Appointed Experts

  • Eve-Angeline Lambert EMAIL logo and Yves Oytana
Published/Copyright: March 13, 2019
Become an author with De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

Departing from the observation that neutral experts are increasingly appointed by courts, this paper investigates the incentives of courts to appoint experts, and the interactions between the judge’s and the expert’s efforts to discover the truth about a given case. Judges seek to make correct decisions and may choose to appoint experts in order to do so. Experts are assumed to be guided by both reputational and truth-finding motives. We highlight the determinants of the judge’s and the expert’s effort levels and of the judge’s decision whether to appoint an expert. We find that the expert’s effort is decreasing in the judge’s effort, which implies potential freeriding from the judge. Moreover, we find that (i) the judge’s effort is generally suboptimal, and (ii) they might resort to an expert appraisal too frequently, thereby contributing to increased court congestion and higher costs for society. Our results therefore suggest that, under conditions that we discuss, it may be socially beneficial to apply a principle of proportionality to the use of expert testimony, depending on the complexity of the case.

JEL Classification: K40; K41; K49

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Christian At, Pierre Bentata, Nathalie Chappe, Giuseppe Dari Mattiacci, Dominique Demougin, Tim Friehe, Yannick Gabuthy, Denis Gromb and Lionel Thomas for their comments on earlier versions of this paper as well as the two anonymous referees who helped improving the quality of this paper.

Appendix

A Proof of Lemma 1

Maximizing ue(ee,ej,η) with respect to ee raises the following first-order condition for an interior solution:

(27)ue(ee,ej,η)ee=0λ(μηej)+(1λ)r(ee)=ce(ee)

This condition implies that if μ>ηej, the utility maximizing effort of E is strictly positive (i.e. eeBej,η>0). The second-order condition is:

(28)2ue(ee,ej,η)ee2=(1λ)r′′(ee)c′′(ee)<0

From the implicit function theorem, we have:

(29)eeej=2ue(ee,ej,η)eeej2ue(ee,ej,η)ee2

With:

(30)2ue(ee,ej,η)eeej=λη0

Thus:

eeej=λη1λr′′eec′′ee0(<0ifη>0)

This condition means that E’s effort decreases in J’s effort (i.e. eeBej,η/ej0). Moreover, we have:

(32)2eeejλ=η1λr′′eec′′ee+ληr′′ee1λr′′eec′′ee20

And:

(33)2eeejη=λ1λr′′eec′′ee<0

These conditions mean that the magnitude of the decrease of E’s effort with respect to J’s effort increases in λ and η (i.e. 2eeBej,η/(ejλ)0 and 2eeBej,η/(ejη)<0). Finally, we have:

(34)2ue(ee,ej,η)eeη=λej0

Thus, from the implicit function theorem:

(35)eeη0(<0ifej>0)

This condition means that E’s effort increases with the complexity of the case at hand (eeBej,η/η0).

B Proof of Lemma 2

Let us define:

(36)L(ηˆ,ej)=GjeeB(ej,ηˆ)μηˆejk

The complexity threshold ηˆB(ej) is found by solving (6) for ηˆ. This is equivalent to solving for ηˆ:

(37)L(ηˆ,ej)=0GjeeBej,ηˆ(μηˆej)=k

The right hand side of this equation is strictly positive since k > 0, which implies that the left hand side should also be strictly positive. This is the case only if μ>ηˆej, which implies (8).

Applying the implicit function theorem on (37), we have:

(38)ηˆej=L(ηˆ,ej)ejL(ηˆ,ej)ηˆ

With:

(39)L(ηˆ,ej)ej=eeB(ej,ηˆ)ejGj(μηˆej)GjeeB(ej,ηˆ)ηˆ<0

And:

(40)L(ηˆ,ej)ηˆ=eeB(ej,ηˆ)ηˆGj(μηˆej)GjeeB(ej,ηˆ)ej<0

This implies:

(41)ηˆej<0

Which means that the complexity threshold chosen by J is decreasing with respect to her own effort (i.e. ηˆB(ej)/ej<0).

Given that ηˆB(ej)/ej<0, J appoints an expert with a strictly positive probability if her effort is not too high, i.e. if:

(42)GjeeB(ej,0)μk>0

Moreover, J does not appoint an expert with a strictly positive probability if her effort is not too low, i.e. if:

(43)GjeeB(ej,1)(μej)k<0

The two conditions (42) and (43) imply that ηˆB(ej)(0,1) only if the following condition holds:

(44)eeB(ej,1)(μej)<k/Gj<eeB(ej,0)μ

It follows that if ejA, then ηˆB(ej)(0,1), and thus F(ηˆB(ej))(0,1).

C Proof of Lemma 3

We have:

(45)Q(ej,ee,η^)ej=0η^f(η)(1ee)ηdη+η^1f(η)ηdη>0
(46)Q(ej,ee,η^)ee=0η^f(η)(μηej)dη>0
(47)Q(ej,ee,η^)η^=f(η^)(μee+(1ee)η^ej)f(η^)η^ej=f(η^)(ee(μη^ej))>0

D Proof of Lemma 4

Maximizing ujej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ with respect to ej raises the following first-order condition:

(48)ujej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆej=0GjQ(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ej=cj(ej)

From Assumption 1, the left hand side of (48) is strictly positive, implying that the right hand side should also be strictly positive, wich is true only if J’s effort is strictly positive (ejBηˆ>0).

Applying the implicit function theorem on (48), we have:

(49)signejBηˆηˆ=sign2ujej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆejηˆ

With:

2ujej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆejηˆ=Gjf(ηˆ)eeB(ej,η)ej(μηˆej)eeB(ej,η)ηˆ

According to (14) and Lemma 1, this expression is negative, thus implying from (49) that ejBηˆ/ηˆ<0.

E Proof of Lemma 5

We have:

cˉe(ee,ηˆ)ee=0ηˆf(η)ce(ee)dη>0cˉe(ee,ηˆ)ηˆ=f(ηˆ)ce(ee)+cs>0

F Proof of Proposition 1

The proof follows from Lemma 1 and Lemma 2.

G Proof of Proposition 2

The proof follows from (24).

H Proof of Proposition 3

The policymaker chooses ex ante the socially optimal complexity threshold ηˆS according to:

ηˆS=argmaxηˆwejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ

By taking the derivative of wejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ with respect to ηˆ, we obtain the following expression:

(54)wejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆηˆ=uj(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆ+(1Gj)Q(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆcˉe(eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆ

The social welfare is decreasing with respect to the complexity threshold if (54) is negative when evaluated for ηˆ=ηˆ.

Consider the first term to the right hand side of (54). We have:

uj(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆ=uj(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ηˆej=ejB(ηˆ)+uj(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ejB(ηˆ)×ejB(ηˆ)ηˆ

Assume the policymaker chooses ex ante a complexity threshold ηˆ=ηˆ. This level of the complexity threshold cancels out uj(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)/ηˆ, because it is the first-order condition resulting from (16). Moreover, from the first-order condition (48), we know that uj(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)/ejB(ηˆ)=0. Thus, for ηˆS=ηˆ, uj(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)/ηˆ=0.

Consider the second term to the right hand side of (54). We have:

(56)Q(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆ=Q(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ejB(ηˆ)×ejB(ηˆ)ηˆ+Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ηˆej=ejB(ηˆ)

From Assumption 1, Q(ejB(ηˆ),eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)/ejB(ηˆ)>0 and, from Lemma 4, we know that ejB(ηˆ)/ηˆ<0. The first term to the right hand side of (56) is thus negative. Moreover, from Lemma 3, we have Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)/ηˆ>0. Thus, (56) is negative if condition (26) is satisfied, and the second term to the right hand side of (54) is negative if (26) is satisfied (not satisfied) and Gj<1 (Gj>1).

Consider the third term to the right hand side of (54). We have:

(57)cˉe(eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)ηˆ=cˉe(eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ηˆej=ejB(ηˆ)+cˉe(eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η)×eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η)ejB(ηˆ)×ejB(ηˆ)ηˆ

From Lemma 5, we know that cˉe(eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)/ηˆ>0 (the first term to the right hand side of (57) is positive), and that cˉe(eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η),ηˆ)/eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η)>0. Finally, we know from Lemma 1 that eeB(ejB(ηˆ),η)/ejB(ηˆ)<0 and from Lemma 4 that ejB(ηˆ)/ηˆ<0. Thus, expression (57) is positive.

Additional comparative statics results

The expert’s effort

For a given J’s effort (ej) and a given level of complexity of the case at hand (η), we obtain the following comparative statics results by applying the implicit function theorem on the expert’s first-order condition (27).

Effect of µ on the expert’s effort

(58)signeeμ=sign(λ),thuseeμ>0

Effect of λ on the expert’s effort.

(59)signeeλ=sign(μηej)r(ee)

Thus:

(60)eeλ>0ifμηej>r(ee)(and conversely)

Others.

(61)2eeejμ=0;eek=0;eeGj=0

The complexity threshold chosen by the judge

For a given J’s effort (ej) and given E’s best reply eeB(ej,ηˆ), we obtain the following comparative statics results by applying the implicit function theorem on (37).

Effect of µ on the complexity threshold

(62)signηˆμ=signeeB(ej,ηˆ)μGj(μηˆej)+GjeeB(ej,ηˆ),thusηˆμ>0

Effect of λ on the complexity threshold

(63)signηˆλ=signeeB(ej,ηˆ)λGj(μηˆej)

Thus:

(64)ηˆλ>0ifμηˆej>r(ee)(and conversely)

Effect of k on the complexity threshold

(65)signηˆk=sign1,thusηˆk<0

Effect ofGjon the complexity threshold

signηˆGj=signeeB(ej,ηˆ)(μηˆej),thusηˆGj>0

The judge’s effort

We obtain the following comparative statics results by applying the implicit function theorem on the equation ej=ejB(ηˆB(ej)), assuming there is a unique solution ej=ejA (which can also be found with (15)).

As a preliminary stage, we need:

(67)2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejμ=0ηˆf(η)eeB(ej,η)ejeeB(ej,η)μηdη<0
(68)2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejλ=0ηˆf(η)2eeB(ej,η)ejλ(μηej)eeB(ej,η)ληdη0
(69)2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆ=f(ηˆ)eeB(ej,ηˆ)ej(μηˆej)eeB(ej,ηˆ)<0

Effect of µ on the judge’s effort

signejμ=signGj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejμηˆ=ηˆB(ej)+Gj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆηˆ=ηˆB(ej)×ηˆB(ej)μ

Thus:

(71)ejμ<0

Effect of λ on the judge’s effort

(72)signejλ=signGj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejληˆ=ηˆB(ej)+Gj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆηˆ=ηˆB(ej)×ηˆB(ej)λ

Thus, the sign of ej/λ is ambiguous.

Effect of k on the judge’s effort

(73)signejk=signGj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆηˆ=ηˆB(ej)×ηˆB(ej)k

Thus:

(74)ejk>0

Effect ofGjon the judge’s effort

(75)signejGj=signQ(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆ=ηˆB(ej)+Gj2Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆηˆ=ηˆB(ej)×ηˆB(ej)Gj

With:

(76)Q(ej,eeB(ej,η),ηˆ)ejηˆ=ηˆB(ej)>0(Assumption 1)

Thus, the sign of ej/Gj is ambiguous.

References

Bourjade, S., and B. Jullien. 2011. “The Roles of Reputation and Transparency on the Behavior of Biased Experts,” 42 (3)The RAND Journal of Economics 575–594.10.1111/j.1756-2171.2011.00146.xSearch in Google Scholar

Cameron, C. M., and L. A. Kornhauser. 2005a. “Appeals Mechanisms, Litigant Selection, and the Structure of Judicial Hierarchies,” 1 Institutional Games and the U.S. Supreme Court 173–204.Search in Google Scholar

Cameron, C. M., and L. A. Kornhauser. 2005b. “Decision Rules in a Judicial Hierarchy,” 161(2)Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 264–302.10.1628/0932456054193630Search in Google Scholar

Crawford, V., and J. Sobel. 1982. “Strategic Information Transmission,” 50 (6)Econometrica 1431–1452.10.2307/1913390Search in Google Scholar

Dewatripont, M., and J. Tirole. 1999. “Advocates,” 107 (1)Journal of Political Economy 1–39.10.1086/250049Search in Google Scholar

Dumoulin, L. 2007. L’expert dans la justice : De la genèse d’une figure à ses usages. Paris: Economica.Search in Google Scholar

Emons, W., and C. Fluet. 2009. “Accuracy Versus Falsification Costs: The Optimal Amount of Evidence under Different Procedures,” 25 (1)The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 134–156.10.1093/jleo/ewm046Search in Google Scholar

Kartik, N., F. X. Lee, and W. Suen. 2017. “Investment in Concealable Information by Biased Experts,” 48(1)The Rand Journal of Economics 24–43.10.1111/1756-2171.12166Search in Google Scholar

Kim, C. 2013. “Adversarial and Inquisitorial Procedures with Information Acquisition,” 30 (4)The Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 767–803.10.1093/jleo/ewt012Search in Google Scholar

Kim, C. 2017. “Centralized Versus Decentralized Institutions for Expert Testimony,” 173 (2)Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 209–238.10.1628/093245616X14664894246848Search in Google Scholar

Krishna, V., and J. Morgan. 2001. “A Model of Expertise,” 116 (2)The Quarterly Journal of Economics 747–775.10.1162/00335530151144159Search in Google Scholar

Levy, G. 2005. “Careerist Judges and the Appeals Process,” 36 (2)The RAND Journal of Economics 275–297.Search in Google Scholar

Lim, C. S. 2013. “Preferences and Incentives of Appointed and Elected Public Officials: Evidence from State Trial Court Judges,” 103 (4)American Economic Review 1360–1397.10.1257/aer.103.4.1360Search in Google Scholar

Morris, S. 2001. “Political Correctness,” Journal of Political Economy, 109(2):231–265.10.1086/319554Search in Google Scholar

Ottaviani, M., and P. N. Sorensen. 2006a. “Professional Advice: The Theory of Reputational Cheap Talk,” 126 Journal of Economic Theory 120–142.10.1016/j.jet.2004.08.005Search in Google Scholar

Ottaviani, M., and P. N. Sorensen. 2006b. “Reputational Cheap Talk,” The Rand Journal of Economics 37:155–175.10.1111/j.1756-2171.2006.tb00010.xSearch in Google Scholar

Oytana, Y. 2014. “The Judicial Expert in a Two-Tier Hierarchy,” 170(3)Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 537–570.10.1628/093245614X14017020626304Search in Google Scholar

Palumbo, G. 2006. “Optimal Duplication of Effort in Advocacy Systems,” 60(1)Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 112–128.10.1016/j.jebo.2003.12.005Search in Google Scholar

Pélisse, J., C. Protais, K. Larchet, and E. Charrier. 2012. Des chiffres, des maux et des lettres. Paris: Armand Colin. 256pages.10.3917/arco.pelis.2012.01Search in Google Scholar

Posner, R. 1999. “The Law and Economics of the Economic Expert Witness,” 13 (2)Journal of Economic Perspective 91–99.10.1257/jep.13.2.91Search in Google Scholar

Posner, R. 2013. Reflections on Judging. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Posner, R. A. 1993. “What Do Judges and Justices Maximize? (the same thing everybody else does),” 3 Supreme Court Economic Review 1–41.10.1086/scer.3.1147064Search in Google Scholar

Shavell, S. 2006. “The Appeals Process and Adjudicator Incentives.” 35 Journal of Legal Studies 1–29.10.1086/500095Search in Google Scholar

Sidak, J. G. 2013. “Court-Appointed Neutral Economic Experts.” 9 (2)Journal of Competition Law & Economics 359–394.10.1093/joclec/nht011Search in Google Scholar

Sobel, J. 1985. “A Theory of Credibility.” 52 (4)Review of Economic Studies 557–573.10.2307/2297732Search in Google Scholar

Suurmond, G., O. H. Swank, and B. Visser. 2004. “On the Bad Reputation of Reputational Concerns.” 88 (12)Journal of Public Economics 2817–2838.10.1016/j.jpubeco.2003.10.004Search in Google Scholar

Tomlin, J. T., and D. Cooper. 2008. “Expert Testimony, Daubert, and the Determination of Damages.” 4 (1)Review of Law & Economics 11.Search in Google Scholar

Vertlieb, A., Q.C., and I. Knapp. 2015. “Experts – Judges Need to Bring Real Change.” 73 (5)The Advocate 665.Search in Google Scholar

Yee, K. 2008. “Dueling Experts and Imperfect Verification.” 28 (4)International Review of Law & Economics 246–255.10.1016/j.irle.2008.09.001Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2019-03-13

© 2019 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 6.10.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/rle-2016-0029/html
Scroll to top button