Abstract
Much writing on Donor Advised Funds (DAFs) relates to whether they ‘unduly’ delay the direct application of donated funds to achieve public benefit. However, the discussion rarely touches on a normative basis for determining what is ‘undue’ or that can be used to shape potential reforms, which are typically framed with reference to a private foundation payout rate or time limit for expending contributions. Research on charity accumulation conducted across the United States, United Kingdom, Canada, Australia and New Zealand, suggests that the normative principle of intergenerational justice is helpful for grounding such discussions (Murray, I. 2021. Charity Law and Accumulation: Maintaining an Intergenerational Balance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). This article considers intergenerational justice in the context of DAFs and considers whether the principle can be implemented in ways that support DAF sponsor independence and flexibility. One way that this could be achieved is by imposing (or enforcing existing) procedural obligations on decision-makers to give genuine consideration to intergenerational justice when making decisions about how much to spend and retain.
1 Introduction
Philanthropic intermediaries in the form of ‘donor advised funds’ (DAFs) are the fastest growing recipients of charitable donations in the United States, with the largest DAF sponsors rivalling the size of the endowments of universities such as Harvard and Yale (Hopkins 2020: Ch 1). While not at the same scale, they are also increasing in popularity in other countries, especially Canada, but also the United Kingdom (UK) and Australia (Murray 2020: 263–4; Phillips, Dalziel, and Sjogren 2021). When considered as substitutes for private foundations or as (temporal) substitutes for public charities (see, e.g. Colinvaux 2017; Murray 2020), DAFs have a number of potential advantages and disadvantages. Noteworthy advantages include their administrative simplicity and lower cost, their flexibility, ability to permit on-going donor involvement and, potentially, expertise in handling non-cash donations (Colinvaux 2017; Grennan 2022; Murray 2020). The most commonly identified disadvantage is the potential – inherent in DAF’s role as intermediaries – for there to be ‘too much’ delay between the DAF receiving a donation and the DAF distributing the funds onto a charity to more directly employ the funds in carrying out charitable activities (see, e.g. Colinvaux 2017; Galle 2016; Madoff 2014; Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector 2019).
While there may be legitimate reasons for delay, this concern underpins the work of the Accelerating Charitable Giving Initiative and is the reason that United States Senators Angus King and Chuck Grassley introduced Senate Bill 1981 (the Accelerating Charitable Efforts Act, or ‘ACE Act’) which would cap the time for distributing DAF contributions at 15 or 50 years, with more generous tax treatment for donors opting into the 15 year model.[1] A corresponding Bill was introduced in the House of Representatives in February 2022: House Bill 6595. The rationale for the ACE Act is to:
ensure Donor-Advised Funds make resources available to working charities in [a] reasonable period of time (King 2021).
Views and empirical data about whether there is in fact ‘too much’ delay appear mixed, as set out in Section 2 below. However, it is clear that while many DAF sponsors make substantial distributions on an aggregate basis, there is significant heterogeneity, with a substantial minority of DAF accounts paying out nothing in a given year. Further, discussion about whether there is ‘too much’ delay typically lacks a normative reference point.
This article unpacks intergenerational justice to address that reference point gap. Intergenerational justice has recently been applied to the accumulation of assets by charities more broadly (Murray 2021) and in particular to philanthropic intermediaries in the form of foundations to justify, and limit, accumulation (Cordelli and Reich 2016: 228, 234–8; Reich 2018: Ch 5). There are various alternative conceptions of intergenerational justice principles, but a ‘sufficientarian’ interpretation is proposed as the preferable approach for DAFs.
If intergenerational justice principles are adopted as a reference point for judging whether DAF sponsors unduly delay the direct application of donations, this directly raises a secondary question about how to incorporate those principles into our social institutions. While there are some advantages, there are also material impediments to implementing intergenerational justice principles via payout rates or time limits or by way of the tax and transfer system. This is partly due to the range of potential reasonable interpretations of intergenerational justice principles.
An alternative method for implementing intergenerational justice explored in this article is a procedural approach. That is, ensuring that charity directors or trustees genuinely consider on a principled basis when their charity should deliver benefits to the community. Such an approach has advantages for a sector as heterogeneous as the charity sector, which appears to be reflected in the heterogeneity of DAFs. It also reminds us of a unique aspect of DAFs. That is, while donors retain advisory privileges, the DAF sponsor owns the assets and legally decides what to do with them. Reminding DAF sponsors of their rights and duties when exercising their discretions to disburse or retain DAF contributions can unlock other mechanisms for addressing concerns about delay.
While intergenerational justice is relevant to the broader charity sector, this article focuses on DAFs because they are one of the fastest growing philanthropic forms and, as philanthropic intermediaries, they encompass the potential for delay. Further, while wealth disparities within the current generation raise pressing issues of intragenerational justice, they are beyond scope.
The article is therefore structured as follows. Section 2 explains what a DAF is and provides some context about delay. Section 3 outlines the principle of intergenerational justice, why it should apply to DAFs and why a ‘sufficientarian’ interpretation is preferred for DAFs. Section 4 examines how the principle might be implemented for DAFs, focussing on a procedural approach that requires DAF sponsor directors and trustees to give due regard to sufficientarian principles, as reasonably understood by them, when making accumulation and spending decisions. Section 5 concludes.
2 DAFs and Delay
In each of the United States, Canada, the UK and Australia, a DAF or ‘sub-fund’ is not itself a separate legal entity, but rather a management account maintained by a legal entity – a public charity. In some jurisdictions that legal entity is more likely to be a charitable corporation (e.g. the United States), in others, it is more likely to be a trustee, with the DAF or sub-fund maintained within the charitable trust (e.g. Australia) (IRS 2022; Murray 2020; Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector 2019: 109–13). The arrangement between the donor and the charity is that the donor retains no ownership interest in donated property, but that the charity will provide administrative assistance to the donor and will grant the donor advisory privileges (including on investment options). The advisory privilege is an ability for the donor to recommend to the charity when to distribute donated property and to whom, amongst a list of eligible recipients. Accordingly, while donors have no right to direct the distribution of property, there is an incentive for the legal entity, or ‘DAF sponsor’, to act in accordance with lawful recommendations so as to encourage future donations. For DAF sponsors with affiliated financial services firms providing wealth management advice to the same donor, there can be an even stronger commercial incentive to follow the donor’s wishes (Murray 2020).
The degree of incentive to follow a donor’s wishes – and potentially countenance delay – might well therefore be influenced by the form of the DAF sponsor. For instance, community foundations that are charities with purposes focussed on a particular geographic region or universities that maintain DAF accounts may have other constituencies that apply pressure to distribute funds more quickly than do DAF sponsors that are national financial services organisations. Nevertheless, as the data and commentary below demonstrate, concerns about DAF delays apply to all DAF sponsors, even if the concerns are enhanced for some types.
Such concerns led to the ACE Act referred to in the Introduction and are a key reason for the recent Canadian government consultation on increasing the disbursement quota that applies across the board to Canadian tax-registered charities (Blumberg and Lang 2021; Department of Finance 2021; Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector 2019: 110–113). Ultimately, the government decided to increase the rate of the disbursement quota in a graduated fashion so as to ‘boos[t] charitable spending’ (Canadian Government 2022: 196).
The empirical data, most of which comes from the United States, paints a mixed picture. Some commentators suggest that when compared with private foundation or charitable endowment payout rates, DAF aggregate payout rates compare favourably (Heist and Vance-McMullen 2019; Hopkins 2020: 255–260). Heist and Vance-McMullen have also pointed to ‘flow rates’ of contributions being converted into grants for DAFs that are high compared to private foundations (2019). Others point to large distortions in the typical commercial DAF sponsor calculation of the payout rate and to substantial DAF to DAF distributions, which are often counted as part of the payout (Andreoni and Madoff 2020; Flannery and Collins 2021). The ‘flow rate’ has also been criticised as failing to show whether DAF assets are increasing or decreasing (Andreoni and Madoff 2020).
Two things are, however, clear. First, while many DAF sponsors make substantial distributions on an aggregate basis, a substantial minority of DAF sponsors pay out less than 5% in a given year (Andreoni and Madoff 2020; Arnsberger 2015: 62). This heterogeneity is even more pronounced at the DAF account level, with a recent study by the Council of Michigan Foundations (focussed on community foundations) finding that 35% of Michigan DAF accounts paid out nothing in the COVID-year of 2020 (Williams and Kienker 2021). Vance-McMullen and Heist’s larger DAF account level study (which focussed on community foundations and religious organisation sponsors, not financial services-linked DAF sponsors) also found that just under 30% of DAF accounts paid out nothing in a given year and that 35% of DAF accounts paid out less than 5% per year over a four year period (Vance-McMullen and Heist 2022). These findings are broadly consistent with Steele and Steuerle (2015: 6–7).
Vance-McMullen and Heist also found that around 10% of DAF accounts were formally designated as ‘endowed’ meaning that they were explicitly intended to last for the very long term, with a further proportion of account holders informally treating their DAF account like an ‘endowed’ account (Vance-McMullen and Heist 2022: 14, 24). Over 20% of DAF accounts were thus predicted to still be making distributions from their original contributions over 20 years later (Vance-McMullen and Heist 2022: 26). Williams and Kienker found an even higher percentage of endowed DAF accounts (over 50%) in their study of Michigan community foundations (2021: 21–22). In the Canadian context, it has also been suggested that while DAF sponsors have payout rates averaging between 12 and 17%, no distributions at all may be made for many years from a substantial minority of DAF accounts (Sjögren 2018: 91).
Second, discussion about whether there is ‘too much’ delay typically lacks a normative point of reference (other than sporadic references to agency costs – see, e.g. Galle 2021). Typically the reference point is the payout rate or flow rate of private foundations.
3 Intergenerational Justice
As intermediaries, DAF sponsors inevitably result in some delay in the application of donations. Building up funds in this way can enhance public benefit by supporting the sustainability of services, pluralism, effectiveness and efficiency, including in realizing illiquid assets (Murray 2021: Ch 2; Hemel, Bankman, and Brest 2021: 291–292; see also Reich 2018: 184–90 in relation to the role of foundation accumulation). As DAF assets are invested, they may also grow at a faster rate than inflation (Hemel, Bankman, and Brest 2021: 291; Klausner 2003). Further, as argued by Reich, an independent (from government) source of support for the charity sector and for altruistic modes of acting can, at a societal level, also help the reproduction of social capital (2018: 179–84).
However, accumulation means that the delivery of some benefits will also be deferred; with the data in Section 2 indicating that deferral may take place along intergenerational timelines in respect of a substantial minority of DAF accounts. A focus on the sustainability and longevity of the charity itself may also result in decreased attention to potential benefit recipients in the current generation or to efficiency in distributing benefits (Murray 2021: 38–9). Using intermediaries also adds the risk of increased agency costs (Galle 2021). Further, if a small group of intermediaries, such as DAF sponsors start to receive very material portions of annual donations and to hold material portions of charity sector assets – which corresponds to the maturing DAF sector in the United States – the effect is likely to be that a material portion of these assets are temporally displaced from operating charities. This has the potential to reduce the financial resilience of operating charities due to their lack of control over when and whether they will receive DAF distributions (compare Cloutier 2005: 99).
The benefits and harms from building up funds in DAFs can make us question whether this accumulation enhances the net public benefit and whether the accumulation is – or to what extent such accumulation can be – fair as between different generations. Especially so as, aside from intergenerational deferral within DAF accounts, DAF sponsors themselves would be expected to last for long periods of time. The concerns can be viewed as concerns about whether the current DAF settings reflect a fair system of social cooperation (see e.g. Murray 2020; Klausner 2003).
‘Intergenerational justice’ is a normative basis that could be used to determine what is a ‘fair’ balance between generations to determine the extent to which DAF rules should demand public benefit for the present generation or permit accumulation for the benefit of future generations (Murray 2020). After all, from a social contract perspective, the notion of ‘justice’ is intended to articulate ‘principles that provide a public basis for justification all [members of the society] can accept, in order to sustain willing social cooperation’ (Freeman 2007: 24). Theories of intergenerational justice set out the obligations owed by the present generation in relation to people in the past and the future (Gosseries and Meyer 2009; Tremmel 2006), with most theorists giving equal consideration to present and future persons (Klausner 2003: 54; Rawls 1999, 259–62).[2]
This Part explains that there are various interpretations of intergenerational justice, but expresses a preference for ‘sufficientarian’ approaches as these better allow for the potential institutional role of DAFs in supporting the reproduction of social capital and supporting long-term and risky approaches. Additionally, ‘sufficientarian’ approaches encompass the existing approaches of Cordelli, Reich and Rawls discussed below, and align with common approaches to the narrower question of the distribution of decision-making freedom between generations.
It is to intergenerational justice that Reich and Cordelli turn to evaluate and shape the use of private foundations (Cordelli and Reich 2016; Reich 2018). They apply a particular conception of intergenerational justice, John Rawls’ ‘just savings’ principle, which requires society to preserve capital so as to enable the establishment and then maintenance of ‘just institutions’ (Rawls 1999: 251–8). These ‘institutions’ or the ‘basic structure’ of society are the ‘main political and social institutions of society [that] fit together into one system of social cooperation, and [that] assign basic rights and duties and regulate the division of advantages that arises from social cooperation over time’ (Rawls 2001: 10–12). ‘Just institutions’ are those that assign rights and duties and divide advantages in ways that formally and substantively correspond to principles that enable public justification of social cooperation (Rawls 1999: 47–52).
Reich and Cordelli argue that private foundations have a role in establishing and maintaining just institutions because they enable: the reproduction of social capital (by supporting civil society over time); accumulation of resources so as to respond to remote catastrophic risks to society; and social innovation and problem solving due to the long-term and risky approaches that are open to them as a result of limited accountability mechanisms and lack of a profit motive or political cycle (Cordelli and Reich 2016; Reich 2018: Ch 5). They therefore recommend that foundations should spend or accumulate assets to pursue these three functions.
However, as set out above, there are reasons to question whether a large DAF sector, which temporally displaces direct donations, supports or weakens civil society by undermining its financial resilience. It is also open to question whether a management account from which distributions can be made to a list of potential donees is likely to lead to the degree of social innovation and problem solving that might be anticipated from private foundations with their own staff and funding programs. In a recent analysis of a United States-wide data set of DAF sponsors, Grennan discusses some innovative features of DAF sponsors, focussing on the way in which a minority of DAF sponsors offer matching/vetting services for pools of recipients aligned to donor interests and aimed at addressing inequality and promoting diversity, as well as offering impact investing before distribution (Grennan 2022). This provides some evidence of a longer-term focus (e.g. via impact investing) and of risky approaches (e.g. by way of increased grants to charities serving more marginalised groups). Yet at present, this seems a far cry from long-term risky investments such as the Gates Foundation’s goal of a world free of malaria (Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation 2022) or funding for the creation of the classic children’s educational television programme, Sesame Street, by the Ford Foundation and the Carnegie Corporation (Sesame Workshop 2019).
In any event, the just savings principle acts as a fairly limited concept of intergenerational justice and as a substitute for broader principles of distributive justice (i.e. principles for the allocation of resources and costs amongst members of society: Rawls 1999: 52–58, 78–81; Cohen 1997) that apply within a generation. Political philosophers have shown that distributive justice principles can be applied between generations, that cooperation can take place across generations and that it is possible to transfer resources between generations, although there are greater difficulties than exist between contemporaries (English 1977; Gaspart and Gosseries 2007: 193, 201–3; Thompson 2009: Ch 3, 113–14, 117). Thus, intergenerational justice is often conceived in a broader way to mean that the current generation is obliged to redistribute resources to persons, whether in the same or in future generations, based on the degree to which this would satisfy their fundamental social and economic needs (Birnbacher 2006: 34; Gaspart and Gosseries 2007: 201–04, 209, 211–12). These demands will clearly depend very much on the circumstances and context of the relevant society and require regard to issues such as whether future generations might be wealthier, or burdened by environmental degradation (see, e.g. Revesz 1999; Klausner 2003).
An alternative approach to intergenerational justice is to extend a ‘prioritarian’ interpretation of distributive justice principles (as between contemporaries, see, e.g. Rawls 1999: 57–73; Parfit 1997: 212–14). That is, socio-economic differences are tolerated only to the extent that these differences improve the absolute position of the most disadvantaged members of society, for instance because they incentivise greater productivity and hence greater societal wealth. If they do not, resources should be redistributed to the disadvantaged persons. Its effect on DAF sponsors will depend on matters such as the strength of the priority given to the most disadvantaged and expectations about the degree of well-being of future generations (see, e.g. Meyer and Roser 2009: 234–5). For example, if the priority given to the most disadvantaged is very strong and it is assumed that future generations will be wealthier, prioritarianism would likely favour small improvements for more disadvantaged members of the present generation, than large increases in well-being for slightly less disadvantaged members of future generations (Adler and Treich 2015: 294–7). Such an approach would favour very material DAF distributions that are proximate in time to donations into the DAF, although the risk of catastrophic shocks (such as the Covid-19 pandemic) would justify some saving (compare Gaspart and Gosseries 2007: 203–4, 209, 211–12).
However, a prioritarian approach like the one outlined above, takes little regard for the reproduction of social capital role of DAFs or the potential for DAFs to support longer-term approaches to societal problems. As noted above, there are real questions about the extent to which DAFs presently perform such roles. Nevertheless, it may be preferable to adopt an approach to intergenerational justice that would more easily enable DAFs to undertake the roles. From a ‘sufficientarian’ perspective to the allocation of costs and benefits (Benbaji 2006; Crisp 2003; Sher 2014: Ch 8–9), intergenerational justice demands that the current generation avoid the pursuit of benefits that would impose costs on future generations, where this would result in the world being handed on in a state that fails to meet a ‘sufficientarian’ threshold standard for members of future generations (Laslett 1992: 29–30, 44–45; Meyer 2021). Once the threshold has been reached, sufficientarianism can permit a ‘shift’ to another set of principles, such as prioritarianism, that apply to allocate resources above the threshold (Meyer 2021; Shields 2016: ch 2). In an intergenerational context, this might mean saving enough for future generations to achieve the threshold but then applying prioritarian principles to allocate the surplus amongst the current generation (in the context of a DAF sponsor, within the limits of its charitable purpose).
Rawls’ ‘just savings’ principle is a particular interpretation of sufficientarianism focused on a threshold comprised of just institutions (Meyer 2021). However, the threshold could be articulated in terms of a level of resources to meet basic needs, which could include sufficient resources to support civil society and its role in maintaining social capital, as well as to undertake long-term approaches to societal problems. If the threshold is low and relates to fundamental needs, then this approach does not demand that current generations materially sacrifice their own wellbeing by saving to benefit future generations, nor require future generations to level themselves down to the position of earlier generations, since the sufficientarian threshold simply sets a minimum (Benbaji 2006: 338–42; Meyer 2021; Meyer and Roser 2009: 222–5).
Sufficientarianism might, for instance, oblige a DAF sponsor intended to support educational charities to distribute heavily to schools and universities to enable a higher rate of funding of scholarships or other assistance aimed at providing educational opportunities for particularly disadvantaged students. However, the DAF sponsor would need to do so mindful of whether that DAF sponsor, or other bodies, can remain able to fund educational access for future generations of students and to fund educational civil society bodies that will enable the reproduction of social capital and long-term and risky approaches to educational issues. This might, for instance, cause a DAF sponsor to seek assurances about support for current potential students before distributing to universities with large and growing endowments (see, e.g. Eaton 2021).
A community foundation DAF sponsor focussed on a broad range of charitable purposes in a particular geographic region might likewise need to consider the extent to which the basic needs (linked to those charitable purposes) of future generations of community members are likely to be well-served. This would involve some analysis of whether current community members are well-served and whether material support is required to build up civil society bodies to meet existing or anticipated basic needs. If, however, basic needs are relatively well-served and, over the long term, it is anticipated that those needs will remain stable, that per capita GDP is expected to increase, and that material ongoing donations are expected, then a sufficientarian approach might suggest that most existing DAF funds should be spent over the short to medium term.
These processes also require regard to matters beyond the DAF sponsor’s own circumstances that might impact on future generations, such as state education, social welfare, etc. policies and funding, and the broad intergenerational effect of wider systems such as the tax and transfer system and environmental policies.[3] Single issue DAF sponsors focussed on a particular charitable area (like education) and community foundations focussed on a particular geographic community probably have a good sense of likely levels of need for their services over time and of the likely impacts of government policy and of other actors. Larger DAF sponsors might also be anticipated to understand how broader systems might impact future generations, since this would indirectly impact on the level of need. Conversely, national DAF sponsors that exist for general charitable purposes may not have a good sense of these issues, though that would likely be required by the director and trustee duties discussed in Section 4.
The examples also raise two further matters. First, it seems inevitable that reasonable interpretations of these principles will differ. For instance, one DAF sponsor may consider that economic growth and government policy are likely to decrease need for the services of their funded charities over time, while a further DAF sponsor may allocate a heavier weighting to the detrimental impacts of climate change such that a lower payout rate might be justified to conserve resources for greater future need. Second, we have been working on the assumption that funds distributed by a DAF sponsor will largely benefit the current generation, rather than future generations. However, educational charities might invest in long-lasting infrastructure that benefits students decades into the future (Murray 2021: 202–3). DAF sponsors focused on environmental protection charities might justify high payout rates to reduce the effects of climate change, to the benefit of future generations. Community foundation supported charities might purchase a piece of land to preserve as open space for the community across generations (Klausner 2003: 8). Intergenerational justice is focused on the distribution of these benefits across generations, to which the initial distribution is only a guide. For intermediaries, such as DAF sponsors, that invest and distribute funds to other charities, the assumption seems not entirely unreasonable, particularly as much deferral is unlikely to extend to intergenerational timelines. Nevertheless, there is some basis for expecting DAF sponsors to select a slightly higher target rate of distribution to account for the fact that some benefits will be deferred (see Section 4.1). Also, the potentially long-term impact of current expenditure highlights the initial point about the range of potential reasonable interpretations of the demands of sufficientarian principles.
Moving beyond resources, if we conceptualise the fundamental needs to which our sufficientarian threshold responds as including a need for some degree of decision-making freedom, then we might also require that the DAF sponsor decision-making about how to support educational charities or community charities would pass on from one generation to the next (as to intergenerational justice and the distribution of decision-making freedom, see Murray 2021: Ch 8). As we will see, this is a dimension in which DAFs appear preferable to private foundations.
Finally, as Henry Hansmann’s discussion of ‘intergenerational equity’ (Hansmann 1990) has deterred some writers from employing intergenerational justice to accumulation of assets by charities (Booth et al. 2014), it is worth noting that intergenerational justice is a different concept to intergenerational equity. Hansmann (1990) construed the concept to mean the consumption of accumulated assets at a rate that is neutral between generations so that the accumulated assets will last indefinitely and fund the same set of activities indefinitely. That is clearly different to the concept of intergenerational justice, whether from a prioritarian or sufficientarian perspective.
4 Implementing Intergenerational Justice for DAFs
Despite arguing for a more expansive conception of intergenerational justice than Rawls’ ‘just savings’ principle, the approach to intergenerational justice in Section 3 is still conceived in terms of Rawlsian notions of ‘justice’. We would therefore expect these rules of intergenerational justice to be reflected in society’s basic structure. However, there are a variety of different ways in which intergenerational justice principles could be embedded in social institutions.
One option is to rely on the tax and transfer system to embody the state’s interpretation of what intergenerational sufficientarianism requires. After all, the state is probably better placed than most DAF sponsors to form a view on the intergenerational implications of broad systems and policies such as the tax and transfer system and environmental policies. However, arguments along these lines are typically based on unrealistic assumptions about the administrative cost and political will to amend tax rules to respond to the myriad of charity actions, especially where charities serve socio-economically disadvantaged groups that have less political clout (Adler 2012: 563–565; Murray 2021: 211–213).
Minimum payout rates or timeframes (the ACE Act approach) reflect another method of embodying such rules. However, it is difficult to formulate disbursement or timing rules to reflect the range of reasonable interpretations of intergenerational justice principles and their application in a charity’s specific context (Murray 2021: 213–216). Indeed, we noted in Section 3 how different (reasonable) views on the impacts of climate change on future generations and differences in the type of charities supported by a DAF sponsor, could lead to differing interpretations of the demands of sufficientarianism. Further, we may wish to retain the advantages of DAF sponsor independence and flexibility because they enable pluralism in support of civil society, or the taking of a longer-term approach, or permit a sufficientarian standard to change over time as needs vary. Yet, it is challenging to set a rate that permits independence and flexibility whilst also stopping material accumulation. Indeed, Deep and Frumkin’s research on large United States private foundations suggests that the private foundation 5% minimum disbursement rate may have resulted in uniformity of distribution levels and material accumulation across several decades (Deep and Frumkin 2005).
A further alternative is to shape charity or tax law (part of society’s basic structure) to ensure that DAF directors and trustees genuinely consider issues of intergenerational justice, as reasonably understood by them, when making accumulation and spending decisions (see e.g. Murray 2021: Ch 7). This procedural approach permits greater independence and flexibility and would not require a set payout rate or timing limit. It also neatly fits with the legal reality that donors have given away their property to the DAF sponsor – that is, it is the DAF sponsor officers who must make the ultimate decisions.
4.1 Implementation Through Director/Trustee Duties
Perhaps due to a common focus on tax rules, a point less commonly emphasised is that DAF sponsor directors or trustees are subject to fiduciary duties in exercising their discretionary powers to retain or distribute DAF assets, which would enable (and perhaps require) consideration of principles of intergenerational justice. These duties place similar demands on both directors (of DAF sponsor corporations) and trustees (for DAF sponsor trusts), which reflects a broader coalescence in the duties of those governing charities (American Law Institute 2021).
For DAF sponsors in the form of corporations, directors must typically give genuine consideration in the exercise of their powers and exercise independent judgement, thus needing to take account of – at least to some extent – considerations relevant to the decision and not act capriciously (Langford 2013: 130–1, 134; Companies Act 2006 (UK) s 173; Canada Not-for-profit Corporation Act, SC 2009, c 23 s 124; Stern v Lucy Webb Hayes National Training School for Deaconesses 381 F Supp 1003, 1014, 1016 (D DC, 1974); Fishman, Schwarz, and Mayer 2021: 152–3; Barker, Gousmginoett, and Lord 2013: 534–5. Compare Teck Corp Ltd v Millar [1972] 33 DLR (3d) 288, [161]–[164] (BCSC)). In the United States, this requirement has typically been viewed as falling within the duty of care and of requiring attention to the charity’s activities and informed decision-making (American Law Institute 2021: §2.03).
For DAF sponsors in the form of charitable trusts,[4] trustees are required to act upon ‘genuine consideration’, which again means taking some account of considerations relevant to the decision and not acting ‘irrationally’, ‘irresponsibly’, ‘capriciously’, or ‘wantonly’ (Lutheran Church of Australia v Farmers’ Co-operative Executors and Trustees Ltd (1970) 121 CLR 628; Tucker et al. 2015: [29–263]–[29–288]). In Canada, this has been expressed as making a reasonable effort to obtain and review the pertinent (and not irrelevant) factors to the exercise of a discretion (Hunter Estate v Holton (1992) 7 OR (3d) 372, [19] (Steele J, Ont Gen Div); Nichols v Wevill Estate (1995) 13 BCLR (3d) 137, [35]–[36] (Quijano J, BCSC)) and as not acting so unreasonably that no honest trustee could have come to the relevant decision (Martin v Banting (2001) 37 ETR (2d) 270, [25] (Low J, Ont SCJ) (affirmed on appeal); Waters et al. 2021: §18.IV). In the United States, case law provides that trustees’ discretionary powers must be ‘exercised after serious and responsible consideration’ and not ‘arbitrarily’, ‘capriciously’ or ‘beyond the bounds of a reasonable judgment’ (Boston Safe Deposit and Trust Company v Stone 203 NE 2d 547, 552 (Mass 1965); Ascher, Scott, and Fratcher 2006: §18.2).
It is unclear precisely how far these duties require directors and trustees to have regard to the intergenerational allocation of benefits (see, e.g. Murray 2021: 217–219). However, it is clear that they require directors and trustees to have regard to material considerations when exercising powers and that when exercising powers to distribute or accumulate DAF assets, the intergenerational allocation of costs and benefits may often be a material factor. It is therefore open to courts to interpret (or to legislatures to mandate) these duties as requiring regard to principles of intergenerational justice.
One thing that is peculiar about DAFs is that these powers of distribution and accumulation rest with the DAF sponsor, but the commercial practice is to provide advisory privileges and hence practical decision-making to the donor. It is questionable whether a DAF sponsor, especially in the form of a trust, can delegate expenditure decisions to donors in this way (for a good discussion, see Brody 2005: 666–8; American Law Institute 2021: §2.02, reporters’ note on comment c).[5] In any event, although directors and trustees are typically now able to delegate a range of powers, they cannot abdicate their responsibilities and must exercise oversight of delegates (Brody 2005: 666–8; American Law Institute 2021: §2.02 reporters’ note on comment c, §2.03 reporters’ note on comment c; National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws 2010: §807; American Bar Association 2008: §8.01(b), §8.30; American Bar Association 2022: §801(b), §830). As noted by the court in the Sibley Hospital case (Stern v Lucy Webb Hayes National Training School for Deaconesses 381 F Supp 1003, 1014, (D DC, 1974)):
While a director is, of course, permitted to rely upon the expertise of those to whom he has delegated investment responsibility, such reliance is a tool for interpreting the delegate’s reports, not an excuse for dispensing with or ignoring such reports.
What might an application of intergenerational justice principles to powers of distribution and accumulation involve? DAF sponsor directors and trustees would not be expected to undertake detailed consideration of each individual DAF account decision to distribute or retain assets. However, the activity of grant-making must be considered fundamental to an intermediary such as a DAF sponsor. Directors and trustees could be expected to give genuine consideration to intergenerational justice in setting the scope and terms of the delegation of decision-making to (or recommendations as to expenditure decisions received from) officers and donors. Directors and trustees could also be expected to consider intergenerational justice principles in implementing systems for reviewing and monitoring compliance with delegation authorities. Decisions about how much to distribute and the time period for which DAF account holder advice might be followed might therefore be expected to shape grant-making and succession policies as set out below. Additionally, directors/trustees might also be expected to specifically ensure compliance with sufficientarian principles for individual distribution/accumulation decisions above a materiality threshold. For instance, US federal administrative agencies are required to undertake a benefit-cost analysis for major regulatory actions, which include actions that are likely to have an annual effect of $100 million or more (Adler 2012). Other jurisdictions adopt lower limits; $10 million in New South Wales in Australia (Treasury (NSW) 2017).
A key decision-making tool enabling DAF sponsors to apply intergenerational justice to the distribution of DAF assets either at the aggregate DAF sponsor level (in setting policies) or, for sufficiently material DAF accounts, at the DAF account level, are social welfare functions derived from welfare economics. Social welfare functions operate by applying a mathematical function (the social welfare function) to represent the utilities of individuals across generations as numbers, in order to rank the potential outcomes from an action, such as a resource allocation to the present generation, based on the “utility” numbers generated by the mathematical function (Boadway and Keen 2000: 680–683). These utility numbers are meant to reflect the well-being of each person. This enables the outcome utilities to be ranked over the selected time frame so that the optimal courses of action can be selected (Adler 2012: Ch 5). Social welfare functions can provide insights into how to maximise wellbeing (promoting efficiency) in pursuit of a particular distributional preference (promoting fairness) (Adler 2012: Ch 5).
Intergenerational applications of social welfare functions have already occurred in areas such as environmental regulation and energy policy (forming the basis of the policy responses to climate change, Stern 2007: Ch 2, 2A, 6); tax policy (optimal tax theory has influenced tax bases and rates, Salanié 2003) and health policy (allocation of resources within healthcare systems: Williams 1997). They have also been proposed for development and use by philanthropists and government policy makers as an addition to cost-benefit analysis for health and development programs in developing countries (Robinson et al. 2019: Ch 7).
However, social welfare functions require significant information and are complex to apply. They are therefore typically used only for major decisions. This is consistent with the approach suggested above, with a DAF sponsor using a social welfare function to identify a default approach to distribution levels for its grant-making policies. For the very largest DAF accounts, donors might also be given the option of applying DAF sponsor approved social welfare functions to determine distribution levels for their individual DAF account.
It appears that some DAF sponsors are already taking steps, at least along the lines of developing a grant-making policy that imposes pressure on donors to recommend distributions. For instance, the National Standards for United States Community Foundations is a self-regulation accreditation program created by the Council on Foundations for community foundations (Community Foundations National Standards Board 2022). Accreditation includes review of constituent documents and policies and National Standard 3 contains the following requirement:
3.3 Does that policy outline a process to ensure that a fund remains active with regard to grant activity, unless otherwise specified by the donor and is approved by the board or the staff to which this responsibility is delegated. Does the applicant ensure this policy is shared with the donor and is made available to the public?
Some DAF sponsor organisations also have policies that impose active grant making requirements, though again, there is no reference to a normative basis (see, e.g. Hemel, Bankman, and Brest 2021: 291). For example, Fidelity Charitable’s Program Guidelines (2021) state, under the heading ‘grantmaking’.
Minimum Fidelity Charitable grant activity
…Fidelity Charitable policy requires that minimum annual grants, on an overall basis, be greater than 5% of average net assets on a fiscal five-year rolling basis. If this requirement is not met in a fiscal year, Fidelity Charitable will ask for grant recommendations from Giving Accounts that have not had grant activity of at least 5% of the Giving Account’s average net assets over the same five-year period. If Account Holders on these Giving Accounts do not make grant recommendations within 60 days, Fidelity Charitable will grant the required amounts out in accordance with the Fidelity Charitable Trustees’ Initiative ….
Minimum Giving Account grant activity
Active charitable grantmaking is required for every Giving Account. If no grants are distributed from a Giving Account for one year, Fidelity Charitable will make every effort to contact the Account Holder to encourage grant recommendations from the Giving Account. After two years in which no grants are distributed from a Giving Account, Fidelity Charitable will make grants from the Giving Account to Qualified Charitable Organizations approved by the Trustees of Fidelity Charitable.
Such guidelines could be amended to apply principles of intergenerational justice. For instance, a DAF sponsor could determine a particular proportion of assets that should be distributed so as to comply with sufficientarian principles of intergenerational justice (say, e.g. 25% of assets) and could set that as the default minimum giving proportion for each DAF account (other than major DAF accounts that individually apply a social welfare function). Adjustments to the rate could be incorporated to account for the likelihood that some DAF account holders will distribute at a higher rate and of the countervailing likelihood (identified in Section 3) that some benefits from the distribution will not be realised until a later point in time. DAF sponsors could obtain data for these adjustments from their records of distribution rates and possibly from the charity selection tools that many DAF sponsors are already developing (Grennan 2022) to identify predicted uses of distributions by different classes of charity recipients (e.g. medical research institutes versus soup kitchens).
Some flexibility could also be attained by adopting a multi-year rolling basis (as adopted by Fidelity Charitable). If a particular DAF account holder wishes further flexibility to retain assets, they could be required to justify that approach by applying principles of intergenerational justice, with the DAF sponsor needing to be satisfied that genuine consideration has been provided.
An approach relying on DAF sponsor officers to give genuine consideration to principles of intergenerational justice when making distribution and retention decisions might be described as vague and undemanding. There are two responses. First, getting officers and donors to think about the intergenerational implications of their decisions is likely to be a major change from present practice. For instance, the active grant-making guideline example above makes no reference to intergenerational concerns. There is also a likely bias for some DAF sponsors to accumulate assets and not think too hard about intergenerational matters if their related entities receive management and investment fees that reflect the level of DAF assets (Murray 2020). Research by the Charity Commission for England and Wales on the UK charity sector indicates that many charity officers do not consider the intergenerational implications of their decisions. The research showed that many charities that held reserves of assets did not have any formal policy for the retention and use of those reserves and even for large charities required to have reserves policies, significant proportions failed to state why reserves were held or what assets were held as reserves (Charity Commission for England and Wales 2006; Charity Commission for England and Wales 2018). Second, the law on what it means to give genuine consideration provides guidance on what might otherwise be perceived as a vague standard. Linked to this, the requirements could be tied to reporting to demonstrate and explain compliance (see Section 4.3).
4.2 Strengthen DAF Sponsor Independence from Donors
Section 3 of this article identified that principles of intergenerational justice can be applied not just to the distribution of DAF assets as between generations, but also more specifically to the distribution of decision-making freedom between the donor and subsequent generations. While some respect is due to donors’ lifetime transcending interests in their favoured charitable causes, materially limiting the decision-making freedom of future generations is likely to undermine social cooperation and respect for DAFs as key elements of civil society (in the broader charity context, see Murray 2021: Ch 8; Thompson 2009). This could further undermine the reproduction of social capital role of DAFs. Indeed, while most writers suggest respect for donor intent, they recommend that future generations have the power to make their own decisions once the burden of respecting donor intent becomes material (Murray 2021: Ch 8). This is consistent with a sufficientarian approach.
DAF sponsors have an institutional advantage over many other charities in ensuring adequate levels of decision-making freedom for future generations. That advantage arises because donors can only advise, while the DAF sponsor holds the powers of distribution and accumulation. However, a desire to gain more donor ‘customers’ can work against the institutional form. One area in which this can be seen is under succession policies for DAFs. For instance, Fidelity Charitable’s Program Guidelines (2021: 22–27) provide a DAF account holder with three options for their advisory privileges on their death. Pass the privileges onto one or more named individual successors; recommend eligible charities for immediate distribution of the remaining funds; or recommend an ‘endowed giving program’. The endowed giving program involves specification of eligible charities to receive ongoing distributions, with annual distributions required to amount to at least 5% of the DAF account balance. While Fidelity Charitable, as the DAF sponsor, explicitly ‘reserve[s] the right to modify, amend and/or terminate the Endowed Giving Program at any time’, a 5% minimum payout rate potentially permits the program to last in perpetuity. This risks giving too much respect to donor decision-making freedom.
There are various ways for achieving greater DAF sponsor independence in relation to succession, including through the tax code, or via the director/trustee duties considered in Section 4.1. Arguably, in giving consideration to intergenerational justice in setting DAF program guidelines on succession, directors or trustees might be acting capriciously or beyond the bounds of a reasonable judgment if they fail to articulate limits on when account holder endowment wishes will be followed. To ensure appropriate oversight of delegates, those limits ought to be more specific than a very general reservation of the right to modify, or terminate an endowed giving program.
For example, the guidelines could impose a time limit for distributing the funds, with leftover amounts distributed from the DAF Sponsor’s default account, such as the Fidelity Charitable Trustees’ Initiative (Fidelity Charitable 2021: 27). If the time limit was around 20–40 years, this would reflect the time period between generations and is also long enough that socio-economic circumstances are likely to have changed sufficiently that the initially chosen charities may no longer be efficient vehicles for pursuing a charitable purpose or that the rate of ultimate application of the distributions no longer reflects the new generation’s application of intergenerational justice. Thus, the approach would provide some respect for donors’ wishes, but would curb that respect once material burdens are imposed. There are some parallels with the ACE Act, though this Section 4.2’s focus is on decision-making power, such that it would not stop advisory privileges being passed on by an account holder to their children and the continuation of a DAF, with that new set of advisers in place.
4.3 Enforcement and Accountability
Enforcement and accountability are key for an approach based on DAF sponsor officers’ duties. Accountability might require additional steps, such as for a DAF sponsor to submit its grant-making and succession policies to a regulator, explaining how they have been set by reference to considerations of intergenerational justice. This could also include reporting on the degree of compliance with those policies each year (as well as the reasons why individual DAF accounts have not distributed in accordance with the default distribution requirement).
Some analogies can be drawn to reporting requirements in the UK. UK company directors are required to have regard to a range of stakeholder interests (including ‘the impact of the company’s operations on the community and the environment’) in acting in the way that they consider, in good faith, would be most likely to achieve the company’s charitable purposes (Companies Act (UK) s 172). Practical compliance with this requirement to ‘have regard’ (which could just as easily be applied to ‘principles of intergenerational justice’) is achieved by requiring large companies to include a statement in their annual report explaining how the directors have done so. While there is room for improvement, it appears that the statement has had a behavioural impact on many companies (Financial Reporting Council 2021). Additionally, in England and Wales, large charities are required to report on their level of assets held in reserves and to provide a statement explaining their reserves policy, why they hold their particular levels of reserves and how this complies with their reserves policy (Charities (Accounts and Reports) Regulations 2008 (UK) reg 40(3) (p)).
This sort of information is not currently required under the DAF Form 990 lodged with the Internal Revenue Service (IRS) (see, e.g. Fishman, Schwarz, and Mayer 2021: 736). However, the Tax Cuts and Jobs Act Bill in the form in which it was introduced in the United States House of Representatives originally included an obligation on DAF sponsor organisations to include in the Form 990, amongst other things, confirmation of ‘whether the organization has a policy relating to the frequency and minimum level of distribution from DAFs’ (Fishman, Schwarz, and Mayer 2021: 736–737).
Enforcement would require a regulatory response for ongoing non-compliance. To the extent that non-compliance is with differentially enforced state/provincial fiduciary duties, rather than national standards policed by a national regulator, the above approach will likely be harder to implement, for various reasons, including a jurisdictional race to the bottom (for a more fulsome discussion of potential reasons, see, e.g. Murray 2021: Ch 9). For this reason, it seems easier to implement in jurisdictions like Australia, the UK and New Zealand, than in Canada and the United States. That is because Australia has a charity commission which enforces national governance standards, New Zealand does not have separate states and, while the UK has several jurisdictions and charity commissions, there is a fair degree of uniformity in the governance duties and regulatory approaches adopted.
Canada and the United States do have de facto national regulators of charities, including DAFs: the Canada Revenue Agency and the IRS. While there may be difficulty in enforcing varying state/provincial fiduciary duties, it is entirely possible to create a tax rule that mirrors these fiduciary duties. This is already an established practice in both jurisdictions (Ascher 2014; Buckles 2012). Indeed, Colinvaux has already identified, in the context of DAFs, an existing tax rule that could be applied in this way: the ‘commensurate in scope’ rule (2017).
To understand how this might work, recall that United States charities are subject to an ‘operational’ test due to the wording of Internal Revenue Code section 501(c)(3), which requires that a 501(c)(3) charity be ‘organized and operated exclusively for… charitable… purposes’.[6] The IRS has interpreted this requirement for entities that raise and pass on funds to other charities as requiring the entity to distribute or expend assets ‘commensurate in scope with its financial resources’ (IRS 1989; Siegel 2008). Colinvaux and Hopkins suggest that this test could be used to compel DAFs to increase their distributions (Colinvaux 2017; Hopkins 2020: 390, though Hopkins does not advocate doing so). However, other commentators indicate that the test would only apply to accumulation in narrow circumstances, for instance where distribution/expenditure rates are extremely low or trustees/directors have breached their duties by diverting material funds to their own private benefit (Siegel 2009: 11–12, 16; Simon, Dale, and Chisolm 2006: 283). Indeed, it seems that the IRS’s main concern is that charitable assets will be diverted to private purpose, for instance as remuneration payments to controllers (IRS 1989: 14–15). While Colinvaux’s and Hopkins’ views seem to be minority views on the current law, a robust interpretation of the rule would give the IRS a test that could be used to respond to lack of oversight on the part of DAF sponsors.
However, there are also material concerns about the effectiveness of the Canada Revenue Agency and IRS as DAF regulators. First, some commentators have questioned whether tax regulators are appropriately oriented to monitor the ‘public-welfare compliance’, rather than revenue leakage, of charity projects (Chan 2016: 113–117; O’Connell 2018: 416). That is in large part because, in contrast to charity commissions, tax agencies do not have an institutional focus on charities (Boris and Lott 2017: 97; Gillen 2016: 136, 156–157; Owens 2017: 82). In addition, the IRS, which is underfunded for its charity regulatory role, is still experiencing the reputational damage suffered due to perceptions of politicisation in its regulation of political activities (Ascher 2014: 1597; Owens 2017: 91). The Canada Revenue Agency’s reputation has also been affected by the political activity audits it undertook from 2012 to 2016 and by perceived bias arising from its role as a tax collector (Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector 2019: 109).
It might be possible to ameliorate these concerns about effectiveness if the IRS or Canada Revenue Agency can develop stronger track records of working with state and provincial regulators through coordinated action and education. A coordinated approach could materially reduce the administrative costs for a tax agency, since the agency could also rely on the contribution of some resources by state regulators. In addition, participation by non-revenue authorities might also reduce perceptions of a revenue-collection bias that is typically ascribed to tax agencies. Establishing regular interaction and information sharing with state and provincial regulators could also help generate a base level of institutional focus on charities. This could occur, for instance, under inter-agency memoranda of understanding. A multi-regulator, coordinated, approach would also be consistent with federalism and would be aligned with more recent academic work on charity regulation within a federation (Mayer 2016: 944–945; Simon, Dale, and Chisolm 2006: 270). However, this is not likely to prove easy and is likely to be far more cumbersome than bright line payout rules (e.g. for private foundations) or timing rules (e.g. the ACE Act). Indeed, even after the Pension Protection Act 2006 expanded the IRS’s ability to disclose information to state regulators, information-sharing arrangements between the IRS and state regulators appears limited (Boris and Lott 2017: 106; Owens 2017: 83). Nevertheless, the benefits of supporting federalism and of pluralism, flexibility and independence that result may make the effort worthwhile.
5 Conclusion
This article has argued that intergenerational justice can provide a normative basis for evaluating whether DAFs are ‘unduly’ delaying the more direct application of funds by other public charities. Further, that DAF sponsor directors and trustees have duties to give genuine consideration in exercising their powers to distribute and retain assets and that this could involve consideration of the principles of intergenerational justice. The benefit of this procedural method for implementing intergenerational justice is that rather than imposing a one-size fits all model via a payout rate or limited timeframe for distributions, it would promote independence and flexibility for DAF sponsors. The procedural approach would, however, remind DAF sponsors of their role in decision-making and of the need for oversight of distribution recommendations made by DAF donors. This process, could involve the formulation and monitoring of grant-making and succession policies that are based on principles of intergenerational justice. Individual application of intergenerational justice principles (via a social welfare function) would only arise for very large DAF accounts. The key challenge to this more flexible and autonomy-enhancing approach is the need to strengthen the enforcement abilities of the chief charity regulators in jurisdictions such as the United States and, potentially, Canada. Further consideration would therefore need to be given to mechanisms for better coordination between state and federal regulators.
References
Adler, M. 2012. Well-Being and Fair Distribution: Beyond Cost Benefit Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195384994.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Adler, M., and N. Treich. 2015. “Prioritarianism and Climate Change.” Environmental and Resource Economics 62 (2): 279–308, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-015-9960-7.Search in Google Scholar
American Bar Association. 2008. Model Nonprofit Corporation Act 3d. Chicago: ABA Publishing.Search in Google Scholar
American Bar Association. 2022. Model Nonprofit Corporation Act 4d. Chicago: ABA Publishing.Search in Google Scholar
American Law Institute. 2021. Restatement of the Law, Charitable Nonprofit Organizations. Philadelphia: American Law Institute.Search in Google Scholar
Andreoni, J., and R. Madoff. 2020. Calculating DAF Payout And What We Learn When We Do it Correctly. NBER Working Paper Series. Also available at https://www.nber.org/system/files/working_papers/w27888/w27888.pdf.10.3386/w27888Search in Google Scholar
Arnsberger, P. 2015. Donor-Advised Funds: An Overview Using IRS Data. Washington: Boston College Law School.Search in Google Scholar
Ascher, M. 2014. “Federalization of the Law of Charity.” Vanderbilt Law Review 67 (6): 1581–619.Search in Google Scholar
Ascher, M. L., A. W. Scott, and W. F. Fratcher. 2006. Scott and Ascher on Trusts, 5th ed. New York: Aspen Publishers.Search in Google Scholar
Barker, S., M. Gousmginoett, and K. Lord. 2013. The Law And Practice of Charities in New Zealand. Wellington: LexisNexis.Search in Google Scholar
Benbaji, Y. 2006. “Sufficiency or Priority.” European Journal of Philosophy 14 (3): 327–48, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2006.00228.x.Search in Google Scholar
Bill & Melinda Gates Foundation. 2022. Malaria. Also available at https://www.gatesfoundation.org/our-work/programs/global-health/malaria.Search in Google Scholar
Birnbacher, D. 2006. “Responsibility for Future Generations.” In Handbook of Intergenerational Justice, edited by J. Tremmel, 23. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.10.4337/9781847201850.00009Search in Google Scholar
Blumberg, M., and J. Lang. 2021. Should the Disbursement Quota for Registered Charities in Canada Change or Be Left Alone? Also available at https://www.canadiancharitylaw.ca/wp-content/uploads/2021/09/Should-the-disbursement-quota-for-registered-charities-in-Canada-change-or-be-left-alone-final.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
Boadway, R., and M. Keen. 2000. “Redistribution.” In Handbook of Income Distribution, Vol. 1, edited by A. B. Atkinson and F. Bourguignon, 677. Amsterdam: North Holland.10.1016/S1574-0056(00)80015-9Search in Google Scholar
Booth, M. S., M. Mcgregor-Lowndes, C. M. Ryan, and H. Irvine. 2014. “Financial Reserves: A Necessary Condition for Not-for-Profit Sustainability?” In Performance Management In Nonprofit Organizations, edited by Z. Hoque and L. Parker. New York: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar
Boris, E., and C. Lott. 2017. “Reflections on Challenged Regulators.” In Regulating Charities: The Inside Story, edited by M. McGregor-Lowndes and B. Wyatt, 97. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315563923-6Search in Google Scholar
Brody, E. 2005. “Charity Governance: What’s Trust Law Got to Do with it?” Chicago Kent Law Review 80 (2): 641–87.Search in Google Scholar
Buckles, J. R. 2012. “The Federalization of Fiduciary Obedience Norms in Tax Laws Governing Charities: An Introduction to State Law Concepts and an Analysis of Their Implications for Federal Tax Law.” Estate Planning & Community Property Law Journal 4 (2): 197–256.Search in Google Scholar
Canadian Government. 2022. Budget 2022. Department of Finance. Also available at www.canada.ca/budget.Search in Google Scholar
Chan, K. 2016. The Public-Private Nature of Charity Law. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Search in Google Scholar
Charity Commission for England and Wales. 2006. Tell it like it Is: The Extent of Charity Reserves And Reserve Policies. (Research Report No RS13). London: Charity Commission for England and Wales.Search in Google Scholar
Charity Commission for England and Wales. 2018. Reserves Policies: Demonstrating And Building Resilience. (Accounts Monitoring Review Report). London: Charity Commission for England and Wales.Search in Google Scholar
Cloutier, C. 2005. “Donor-Advised Funds in the US: Controversy and Debate.” Philanthropist 19 (2): 85–108.Search in Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 1997. “Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 26 (1): 3–30, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1997.tb00048.x.Search in Google Scholar
Colinvaux, R. 2017. “Donor Advised Funds: Charitable Spending Vehicles for 21st Century Philanthropy.” Washington Law Review 92 (1): 39–85.Search in Google Scholar
Community Foundations National Standards Board. 2022. National Standards for US Community Foundations. Webpage. Also available at https://www.cfstandards.org/the-program.Search in Google Scholar
Cordelli, C., and R. Reich. 2016. “Philanthropy and Intergenerational Justice.” In Institutions for Future Generations, edited by I. Gonzalez-Ricoy and A. Gosseries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198746959.003.0014Search in Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 2003. “Equality, Priority and Compassion.” Ethics 113 (4): 745–63, https://doi.org/10.1086/373954.Search in Google Scholar
Deep, A., and P. Frumkin. 2005. The Foundation Payout Puzzle: Working Paper No. 9. Cambridge: Hauser Center for Nonprofit Organizations, Harvard University.10.2139/ssrn.301826Search in Google Scholar
Department of Finance. 2021. Backgrounder for Disbursement Quota Consultation. Webpage. Also available at https://www.canada.ca/en/department-finance/programs/consultations/2021/boosting-charitable-spending-communities/backgrounder-disbursement-quota-consultation.html.Search in Google Scholar
Eaton, C. 2021. “Elite Private Universities Got Much Wealthier while Most Schools Fell behind. My Research Found out Why.” The Washington Post. Also available at https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/2021/11/04/elite-private-universities-got-much-wealthier-while-most-schools-fell-behind-my-research-found-out-why/.Search in Google Scholar
English, J. 1977. “Justice between Generations.” Philosophical Studies 31 (2): 91–104, https://doi.org/10.1007/bf01857179.Search in Google Scholar
Fidelity Charitable. 2021. Fidelity Charitable Program Guidelines. Cincinnati: Fidelity Investments Charitable Gift Fund. Also available at https://www.fidelitycharitable.org/content/dam/fc-public/docs/programs/fidelity-charitable-program-guidelines.pdf.Search in Google Scholar
Fidelity Investments Charitable Gift Fund. 2013. Schedule 13D. United States Securities and Exchange Commission. Also available at www.sec.gov/Archives/edgar/data/0001589001/000110465913075415/a13-22183_1sc13d.htm.Search in Google Scholar
Financial Reporting Council. 2021. Reporting on Stakeholders, Decisions and Section 172. London: Financial Reporting Council.Search in Google Scholar
Fishman, J. J., S. Schwarz, and L. H. Mayer. 2021. Nonprofit Organisations: Cases and Materials, 6th ed. New York: Foundation Press.Search in Google Scholar
Flannery, H., and C. Collins. 2021. More than One Billion Dollars in DAF Grants Went to Other Commercial DAFs in 2019. Washington: Charity Reform Initiative, Institute for Policy Studies.Search in Google Scholar
Freeman, S. 2007. Justice and the Social Contract. New York: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar
Galle, B. 2016. “Pay it Forward? Law and the Problem of Restricted-Spending Philanthropy.” Washington University Law Review 93 (5), 1143–207.Search in Google Scholar
Galle, B. 2021. “The Quick (Spending) and the Dead: The Agency Costs of Forever Philanthropy.” Vanderbilt Law Review 74 (3): 757–96.10.2139/ssrn.3624925Search in Google Scholar
Gaspart, F., and A. Gosseries. 2007. “Are Generational Savings Unjust?” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 6 (2): 193–217, https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594x07073006.Search in Google Scholar
Gillen, M. 2016. “A Proposal for Flexibility in Private and Public Express Trust Enforcement.” Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 2 (1): 115–84.Search in Google Scholar
Gosseries, A. and L. Meyer, eds. 2009. Intergenerational Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199284238.003.0019Search in Google Scholar
Grennan, J. 2022. “Social Change through Financial Innovation: Evidence from Donor-Advised Funds.” The Review of Corporate Finance Studies 11 (3): 694–735.10.1093/rcfs/cfac017Search in Google Scholar
Hansmann, H. 1990. “Why Do Universities Have Endowments?” Journal of Legal Studies 19 (1): 3–42, https://doi.org/10.1086/467841.Search in Google Scholar
Hemel, D., J. Bankman, and P. Brest. 2021. “Are Donor-Advised Funds Good for the Nonprofit Sector.” Exempt Organization Tax Review 87: 287–303.Search in Google Scholar
Heist, D. H., and D. Vance-McMullen. 2019. “Understanding Donor-Advised Funds: How Grants Flow during Recessions.” Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector Quarterly 48 (5): 1066–93, https://doi.org/10.1177/0899764019856118.Search in Google Scholar
Hopkins, B. R. 2020. Donor-Advised Funds: Law and Policy. Pittsburgh: Dorrance Publishing.Search in Google Scholar
Internal Revenue Service. 1989. Exempt Organizations Continuing Professional Education Technical Instruction Program for Fiscal Year 1989, Special Emphasis Program: Charitable Fund-Raising. Internal Revenue Service.Search in Google Scholar
Internal Revenue Service. 2022. Donor Advised Funds. Webpage. Also available at https://www.irs.gov.Search in Google Scholar
King, A. 2021. King, Grassley Introduce Legislation to Ensure Charitable Donations Reach Working Charities. Also available at www.king.senate.gov.Search in Google Scholar
Klausner, M. 2003. “When Time Isn’t Money: Foundation Payout Rates and the Time Value of Money.” Stanford Social Innovation Review 1 (1): 51–9.10.2139/ssrn.445982Search in Google Scholar
Kotlikoff, L. 1993. Generational Accounting: Knowing Who Pays And when, for what We Spend. New York: Free Press.Search in Google Scholar
Langford, R. 2013. “Solving the Fiduciary Puzzle – the Bona Fide and Proper Purposes Duties of Company Directors.” Australian Business Law Review 41 (3): 127–41.Search in Google Scholar
Laslett, P. 1992. “Is There a Generational Contract?” In Philosophy, Politics, and Society, Vol 6: Justice between Age Groups and Generations, edited by P. Laslett and J. Fishkin. New Haven: Yale University Press.10.2307/j.ctt211qw3x.5Search in Google Scholar
Madoff, R. 2014. “5 Myths about Payout Rules for Donor-Advised Funds.” The Chronicle of Philanthropy. Also available at: www.philanthropy.com/article/5Myths-About-Payout-Rules-for/153809.Search in Google Scholar
Mayer, L. H. 2016. “Fragmented Oversight of Nonprofits in the United States: Does it Work – Can it Work?” Chicago Kent Law Review 91 (3): 937–63.Search in Google Scholar
Meyer, L. 2021. “Intergenerational Justice.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E. N. Zalta. Also available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/justice-intergenerational/.10.4324/9781315252100Search in Google Scholar
Meyer, L., and D. Roser. 2009. “Enough for the Future.” In Intergenerational Justice, edited by A. Gosseries and L. Meyer, 219. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199282951.003.0009Search in Google Scholar
Murray, I. 2020. “Donor Advised Funds: What Can North America Learn from the Australian Approach?” Canadian Journal of Comparative and Contemporary Law 6 (1): 260–304.10.2139/ssrn.3889449Search in Google Scholar
Murray, I. 2021. Charity Law and Accumulation: Maintaining an Intergenerational Balance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781108854283Search in Google Scholar
National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. 2006. Uniform Prudent Management of Institutional Funds Act. Chicago: National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws.Search in Google Scholar
National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. 2010. Uniform Trust Code. St Chicago: National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws.Search in Google Scholar
O’Connell, A. 2018. “Taxation and the Not-for-Profit Sector Globally: Common Issues, Different Solutions.” In Research Handbook on Not-For-Profit Law, edited by M. Harding, 88. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.10.4337/9781785369995.00028Search in Google Scholar
Owens, M. 2017. “Challenged Regulators.” In Regulating Charities: The inside Story, edited by M. McGregor-Lowndes and B. Wyatt, 81. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9781315563923-5Search in Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1997. “Equality and Priority.” Ratio 10 (3): 202–21, https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00041.Search in Google Scholar
Phillips, S. D., K. Dalziel, and K. Sjogren. 2021. “Donor Advised Funds in Canada, Australia and the US: Differing Regulatory Regimes, Differing Streams of Policy Drift.” Nonprofit Policy Forum 12 (3): 409–41, https://doi.org/10.1515/npf-2020-0061.Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice, Revised edn. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.4159/9780674042582Search in Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.10.2307/j.ctv31xf5v0Search in Google Scholar
Reich, R. 2018. Just Giving: Why Philanthropy is Failing Democracy and How It Can Do Better. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.2307/j.ctvc77jz8Search in Google Scholar
Revesz, R. 1999. “Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Discounting of Human Lives.” Columbia Law Review 99 (4): 941–1017, https://doi.org/10.2307/1123481.Search in Google Scholar
Robinson, L. A., J. K. Hammitt, M. Cecchini, K. Chalkidou, K. Claxton, M. Cropper, P. H. Eozenou, D. de Ferranti, A. B. Deolalikar, F. Guanais, D. T. Jamison, S. Kwon, J. A. Lauer, L. O’Keeffe, D. Walker, D. Whittington, T. Wilkinson, D. Wilson, and B. Wong. 2019. Reference Case Guidelines for Benefit-Cost Analysis in Global Health And Development. Cambridge: Harvard T.H. Chan School of Public Health.10.2139/ssrn.4015886Search in Google Scholar
Salanié, B. 2003. The Economics of Taxation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar
Sesame Workshop. 2019. Sesame Street: 50 Years And Counting. New York: Sesame Workshop.Search in Google Scholar
Sher, G. 2014. Equality for Inegalitarians. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511841859Search in Google Scholar
Shields, L. 2016. Just Enough: Sufficiency As a Demand of Justice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.10.3366/edinburgh/9780748691869.001.0001Search in Google Scholar
Siegel, J. 2008. “Commensurate in Scope: Myth, Mystery, or Ghost? – Part One.” Taxation of Exempts 20 (3): 26–36.Search in Google Scholar
Siegel, J. 2009. “Commensurate in Scope: Myth, Mystery, or Ghost? – Part Two.” Taxation of Exempts 20 (4): 8–17.Search in Google Scholar
Simon, J., H. Dale, and L. Chisolm. 2006. “The Federal Tax Treatment of Charitable Organizations.” In The Nonprofit Sector: A Research Handbook. 2nd ed., edited by W. Powell and R. Steinberg, 267. New Haven: Yale University Press.10.12987/9780300153439-015Search in Google Scholar
Sjögren, K. 2018. Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector, Minutes of Proceedings, 42:1, No 6.Search in Google Scholar
Special Senate Committee on the Charitable Sector. 2019. Catalyst for Change: A Roadmap to a Stronger Charitable Sector. Canada: Senate.Search in Google Scholar
Steele, E., and E. Steuerle. 2015. Discerning the True Policy Debate over Donor-Advised Funds. Washington: Urban Institute.Search in Google Scholar
Stern, N. 2007. The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511817434Search in Google Scholar
Thompson, J. 2009. Intergenerational Justice: Rights and Responsibilities in an Intergenerational Polity. New York: Routledge.10.4324/9780203878682Search in Google Scholar
Treasury (NSW). 2017. NSW Government Guide to Cost-Benefit Analysis: Policy And Guidelines Paper 17-03. Sydney: NSW Government.Search in Google Scholar
Tremmel, J., ed. 2006. Handbook of Intergenerational Justice. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.10.4337/9781847201850Search in Google Scholar
Tucker, L., N. Le Poidevin, J. Brightwell, T. Fletcher, and C. Lloyd. 2015. Lewin on Trusts. London: Thomson Reuters.Search in Google Scholar
Vance-McMullen, D., and D. Heist. 2022. Donor-Advised Fund Account Patterns and Trends (2017–2020). Donor Advised Fund Research Collaborative. Also available at https://www.dafresearchcollaborative.org/dafrc-research.Search in Google Scholar
Waters, D. W. M., M. R. Gillen and L. D. Smith, eds. 2021. Waters’ Law of Trusts in Canada. 5th ed. Toronto: Carswell.Search in Google Scholar
Weisbach, D., and C. Sunstein. 2009. “Climate Change and Discounting the Future: A Guide for the Perplexed.” Yale Law and Policy Review 27 (2): 433–57.10.2139/ssrn.1223448Search in Google Scholar
Williams, A. 1997. “Intergenerational Equity: An Exploration of the “Fair Innings” Argument.” Health Economics 6 (2): 117–32, https://doi.org/10.1002/(sici)1099-1050(199703)6:2<117::aid-hec256>3.0.co;2-b.10.1002/(SICI)1099-1050(199703)6:2<117::AID-HEC256>3.0.CO;2-BSearch in Google Scholar
Williams, J., and B. Kienker. 2021. Analysis of Donor Advised Funds from a Community Foundation Perspective. Michigan: Council of Michigan Foundations.Search in Google Scholar
© 2022 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Research Articles
- The Role of the Nonprofit Sector within the Climate Change Discourse: The View Through Russian News Media
- Greenpeace, Political Purposes – “There and back Again”; Reflections on New Zealand Charity Law
- Donor Advised Funds & Delay: An Intergenerational Justice Solution?
- Policy Brief
- A Tax Credit Proposal for Profit Moderation and Social Mission Maximization in Long-Term Residential Care Businesses
Articles in the same Issue
- Frontmatter
- Research Articles
- The Role of the Nonprofit Sector within the Climate Change Discourse: The View Through Russian News Media
- Greenpeace, Political Purposes – “There and back Again”; Reflections on New Zealand Charity Law
- Donor Advised Funds & Delay: An Intergenerational Justice Solution?
- Policy Brief
- A Tax Credit Proposal for Profit Moderation and Social Mission Maximization in Long-Term Residential Care Businesses