Home Very true operators on MTL-algebras
Article Open Access

Very true operators on MTL-algebras

  • Jun Tao Wang , Xiao Long Xin EMAIL logo and Arsham Borumand Saeid
Published/Copyright: December 10, 2016

Abstract

The main goal of this paper is to investigate very true MTL-algebras and prove the completeness of the very true MTL-logic. In this paper, the concept of very true operators on MTL-algebras is introduced and some related properties are investigated. Also, conditions for an MTL-algebra to be an MV-algebra and a Gödel algebra are given via this operator. Moreover, very true filters on very true MTL-algebras are studied. In particular, subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebras are characterized and an analogous of representation theorem for very true MTL-algebras is proved. Then, the left and right stabilizers of very true MTL-algebras are introduced and some related properties are given. As applications of stabilizer of very true MTL-algebras, we produce a basis for a topology on very true MTL-algebras and show that the generated topology by this basis is Baire, connected, locally connected and separable. Finally, the corresponding logic very true MTL-logic is constructed and the soundness and completeness of this logic are proved based on very true MTL-algebras.

MSC 2010: 03F50; 06F99

1 Introduction

Basic fuzzy logic (BL for short) is the many-valued residuated logic introduced by Hájek [1] to handle continuous t-norms and their residua. The fuzzy logics such as Łukasiewicz, Gödel and Product logic can be regarded as schematic extensions of BL. It is a well-known result that a t-norm has a residuum if and only if it is left-continuous; so this shows that BL is not the most general t-norm based logic. In fact, a logic weaker than BL, called monoidal t-norm-based logic (MTL for short), was introduced by Esteva and Godo in [2] and Jenei and Montagna [3] proved that MTL is indeed the logic of all left-continuous t-norms and their residua. In connection with the MTL logic, a new class of algebras is defined, called MTL-algebras [2]. In the last few years, the theory of MTL-algebras has been enriched with structure theorems [4, 5]. Many of these results have a strong impact with its algebraic structure. For example, Vetterlein [4] proved that most of MTL-algebras can be embeddable into the positive cone of a partially ordered group. He also proved that an MTL-algebra is a bounded, commutative, integral, prelinear residuated lattice [5]. As a more general residuated structure based on left-continuous t-norm logic, an MTL-algebra is a BL-algebra without the identity xy = x ⊙ (xy). Thus, MTL-algebras are the most fundamental residuated structures containing all algebras induced by (left) continuous t-norms and their residua. Therefore, MTL-algebra play an important role in studying fuzzy logics and their related structures. The filter theory of the MTL-algebras plays an important role in studying these algebras and the completeness of the MTL. From a logic point of view, various filters have natural interpretation as various sets of provable formulas. Recently, the filters on MTL-algebras have been widely studied and some important results have been obtained [2,6-8]. In particular, Esteva introduced the idea of filters and prime filters in MTL-algebras to prove the completeness and chain completeness of MTL [2]. After then, the concepts of implicative, positive and fantastic filters were defined in MTL-algebras in [6]. In [7], Borzooei was the first to systematically study filter theory in MTL-algebras, in which the relations between kinds of filters were obtained and some of their characterizations were presented. It was also proved that there exists at most one proper associative filter in any MTL-algebra, which is composed of all non-zero elements in this MTL-algebra in [8].

The concept of “very true” was introduced by Hájek [9] as an answer for the question “whether any natural axiomatization is possible and how far can even this sort of fuzzy logic be captured by standard methods of mathematical logic?”. In other words, very true operator as a tool for reducing the number of possible logical values in many-valued fuzzy logic. In fact, it is the same as the concept of hedge introduced by Zadeh [10], who gives some examples of handling these fuzzy truth values that seems uninterested in any sort of axiomatization. Apart from their important application in many valued fuzzy logic, very true operators were successfully used to formal concept analysis (FCA, in brief) (see [11]), which is another important branch of mathematics and becoming an popular method for analysis of object-attribute data. The main aim in FCA is to extract interesting clusters (called formal concepts) from tabular data, formal concepts correspond to maximal rectangles in a data table, hence the number of formal concepts in data can be extremely large. In order to reduce the number of formal concepts, Bělohlávek and Vyhodil [12] used the so called hedges, which are special cases of very true operators used in reducing the number of formal concepts in concept lattice. Since very true operator was successful in several distinct tasks in various branches of mathematics [10,12-14], it has been extended to other logical algebras such as MV-algebras [15], Rℓ-monoids [16], commutative basic algebras [17], equality algebras [18], effect algebras [19] and so on.

As we have mentioned in the above paragraph, very true operators have been studied on MV-algebras, BL-algebras, Rℓ-monoids and commutative basic algebras, etc. All the above-mentioned algebraic structures satisfy the divisibility condition xy = x ⊙ (xy). In this case, the conjunction ⊙ on the unit interval corresponds to a continuous t-norm. However, there are few research about the very true operators on residuated structures without the divisibility condition so far [19]. In fact, MTL-algebras are the more general residuated structure without the divisibility condition since it is an algebra induced by a left continuous t-norm and its corresponding residuum. Therefore, it is meaningful to study very true operators on MTL-algebras for treating a variant of the concept of very true operators within the framework of universal algebras and providing a solid algebraic foundation for reasoning about very true MTL logic. This is the motivation for us to investigate very true operators on MTL-algebras.

Based on the above considerations, we enrich the language of MTL by adding a very true operator to get algebras named very true MTL-algebras, which are the algebraic counterpart of very true MTL logic. This paper is structured in five sections. In order to make the paper as self-contained as possible, we recapitulate in Section 2 the definition of MTL-algebras, and review their basic properties that will be used in the remainder of the paper. In Section 3, we introduce very true operators on MTL-algebras and study some of their properties. Also, we give some characterizations of MV-algebra and Gödel algebra via such operator. In Section 4, we investigate very true filters of very true MTL-algebras and focus on an analogous of representation theorem for very true MTL-algebras and characterize subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebras by very true filters. Then, we introduce the left and right stabilizers of very true MTL-algebras and construct stabilizer topology via them. In Section 5, the corresponding very true MTL-logic is constructed, the soundness and completeness of this logic are proved based on the variety of very true MTL-algebras.

2 Preliminaries

In this section, we summarize some definitions and results about MTL-algebras, which will be used in the following and we shall not cite them every time they are used.

Definition 2.1

([2]).

An algebraic structure (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0, 1) of type (2, 2, 2, 2, 0, 0) is called an MTL-algebra if it satisfies the following conditions:

  1. (L, ∧, ∨, 0,1) is a bounded lattice,

  2. (L, ⊙, 1) is a commutative monoid,

  3. xyzif and only ifxyz,

  4. (xy) ∨ (yx) = 1,

    for anyx, y, zL.

In what follows, by L we denote the universe of an MTL-algebra (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1). For any xL, we define ¬x = x → 0.

Proposition 2.2

([5]). In any MTL-algebra L, the following properties hold: for allx, y, zL,

  1. xyif and only ifxy = 1,

  2. xyxy,

  3. 1 → x = x,

  4. x → (yz) = (xy) ∧ (xz),

  5. (xy) → z = (xz) ∧ (yz),

  6. xyimpliesxzyz,

  7. xy = x → (xy),

  8. xy = (xy) → y,

  9. xyz = (xz) ∨ (yz),

  10. iI(xiy) = ∨iIxiy, provided that both infimum as well as supremum exist,

  11. xy = ((xy) → y) ∧ ((yx) → x),

  12. (xy) → z = x → (yz).

Definition 2.3

([5]). Let L be an MTL-algebra. Then L is called:

  1. a BL-algebra if xy = x ⊙ (xy) for anyx, yL.

  2. an MV-algebra if (xy) → y = (yx) → xfor anyx, yL.

  3. a Gödel algebra ifxx = xfor anyxL.

A nonempty subset F of L is called a filter of L if it satisfies: (1) x, yF implies xyF;(2)xF, yL and xy implies yF. We denote by F[L] the set of all filers of L. A filter F of L is called a proper filter if FL. A proper filter F of L is called a prime filter if for each x, yF and xyF, implies xF or yF. For any filter F of L we can associate a congruence on L defined by x ~ Fy if and only if (xy) ∧ (yx) ∈ F. We denote by L/F the set of congruence classes and L/F becomes an MTL-algebra with the natural operations induced by those of L. Note that a filter F of L is prime iff L/F is a linearly ordered MTL-algebra ([2, 6, 7]).

Definition 2.4

([20]). A Heyting algebra is an algebra (H, ∨, ∧, →, 0,1) of type (2, 2, 2, 0,0) for which (H, ∨, ∧, 0,1) is a bounded lattice and fora, bH, abis the relative pseudocomplement of a with respect to b, i.e., acb if and only ifcab.

Definition 2.5

([20]). Let L be a complete lattice andaL. Then element a is said to be compact if for every subset S of L, a ≤ ∨ Simplies thata ≤ ∨ Ffor some finite subset F of S.

Definition 2.6

([21]). A topological space (X, T) is calleda Baire space if for each countable collection of open dense sets, their intersection is dense.

At the end of this section, we review the known main results about representation theory of MTL-algebras, which is helpful for studying very true analogous representation theorem of MTL-algebras.

Definition 2.7

([22]). An element b of a lattice L is meet irreducible ifX = b implies bX, for any finite subset X of L.

A filter F of an MTL-algebra L is called prime if F is a finitely meet-irreducible element in the lattice F[L]. A prime filter F is called minimal if F is a minimal element in the set of prime filters of L ordered by inclusion. By Zorn’s lemma, every prime filter contains a minimal prime filter ([24]).

Let L be a MTL-algebra, and XL. The set

X={aL|ax=1,for eachxX}

is called the co-annihilator of X in L[23]. For any aL, we write a instead of {a}.

Theorem 2.8

([24]). ForPF[L], the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. P is a minimal prime,

  2. P = ∪{a|aP}.

Theorem 2.9

([24]). For an MTL-algebra L, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. L is representable,

  2. There exists a set S of prime filters such thatS = {1}.

3 Very true operators on MTL-algebras

In this section, inspired by Hájek [9], we enlarge the language of MTL-algebra by introducing a very true operator, and investigate some related properties. As applications of very true operator, we discuss the structures of the fixed point set of a very true operator and give conditions for an MTL-algebra to be an MV-algebra and a Gödel algebra.

Definition 3.1

Let L be an MTL-algebra. The mapping τ : LL is called a very true operator if it satisfies the following conditions:

(∨l) τ(1)=1,

(∨2) τ(x) ≤ x,

(∨3) τ(xy) ≤ τ (x) → τ(y),

(∨4) τ(x) ≤ τ τ(x),

(∨5) τ(xy) ∨ τ (yx)=1.

The pair (L, τ) is said to be a very true MTL-algebra.

Such a proliferation of conditions deserves some explanation. Then “1” seen in (∨l) is considered as the logical value absolutely true. First note that (∨l) means that absolutely true is very true, which is sound for each natural interpretation in many valued logic system. (∨2) means that if φ is very true then it is true. (∨3) means that if both φ and φψ are very true then so is ψ, that means the connective τ preserve modus ponens. (∨4) says that if φ is very true then τ(φ) is very true, which is a kind of necessitation. To obtain very true MTL-algebras that are representable as subdirect products of very true MTL-chains, we using (∨5).

Example 3.2

  1. Let L be an MTL-algebra. One can easily check that idL is a very true operator on L, that is to say, every MTL-algebra can be seen as a very true MTL-algebra.

  2. Any linearly ordered MTL-algebra L can admit a very true operator; i.e., τ(1) = 1 and τ(x) = 0 for any x < 1.

  3. Let L = {0, a, b, 1} with 0 ≤ ab ≤ 1. Consider the operationandgiven by the following tables:

    0ab10ab1
    0000001111
    a000aab111
    b00bbbaa11
    10ab110ab1

    Then (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1) is an MTL-algebra. Now, we define τ as follows: τ(0) = 0, τ(a)=τ(b) = a, τ(1) = 1. One can easily check that τ is a very true operator on L. However, τ is not a homomorphisms onLsince τ(bb) = a ≠ 0= τ(b) ⊙ τ (b) and τ (ba) = a ≠ 1 = τ(b) → τ(a).

Proposition 3.3

Let τ be a very true operator on L. Then for any x, yL we have,

  1. τ(0) = 0,

  2. τ(x) = 1 if and only if x = 1,

  3. xy implies τ (x) ≤ τ (y),

  4. τ (¬ x) ≤ ¬ (τ x),

  5. τ(x) ⊙ τ (y) ≤ τ (xy),

  6. τ (xy) = τ(x) ∧ τ (y),

  7. τ (xy) = τ(x) ∨ τ (y),

  8. τ (xy) ∨ (yx ) = 1,

  9. τ2 (x) = τ (x),

  10. τ (x) ≤ yif and only if τ(x) ≤ τ(y),

  11. τ (L) = Fixτ (L), whereFixτ (L) = {xL | τ (x) = x},

  12. Fixτ (L) is closed under ⊙, ∧, ∨,

  13. If τ (L) = L, then τ = idL,

  14. Ker(τ) = {1}, where Ker(τ) = {xL|τ(x)=1},

  15. Ker(τ) is a filter of L.

Proof

  1. Applying (V2), we have τ(0) ≤ 0 and hence τ(0) = 0.

  2. If τ(x) = 1 for some xL then by (V2), 1 = τ(x) ≤ x giving x = 1. The converse follows by (Vl).

  3. If xy, then xy = 1. It follows from (Vl) and (V3) that τ(x) → τ (y) = 1. Thus, τ(x) ≤ τ (y).

  4. It follows from (1) and (V3) that τ (¬ x) = τ (x→ 0) ≤ τ(x) → 0 = ¬ τ(x).

  5. From xyxy, we get yx →(xy). By (V3) and (3), we have τ(y) ≤ τ (x →(xy)) ≤ τ(x) → τ(xy) and hence τ(x) ⊙ τ (y) ≤ τ (xy).

  6. On one hand, it is easy to see that τ(xy) ≤ τ(x) ∧ τ (y). On the other hand, by (V2),(V4) and Proposition 2.2 (4), we obtain, for all x, yL, 1 = τ (xy) ∨ τ (yx) = τ(x→ (xy)) ∨ τ (y→(xy))≤ (τ(x) → τ (xy))∨(τ(y) → τ (xy) and hence by Proposition 2.2 (9), we get 1 = (τ(x) ∧ τ (y)) → τ (xy). Therefore, τ(xy) = τ(x) ∧ τ (y).

  7. By(6) and Proposition 2.2 (11), we obtain, for all x, yL, τ (xy) = τ((xy) → y) ∧ τ ((yx) → x). By (3) and (V3), we get τ(xy) ≤ τ((xy) →(τ(x) ∨ τ (y))) ∧ (τ(yx) → (τ(x) ∨ τ(y))). Hence by Proposition 2.2 (10), we obtain τ(xy) ≤ (τ(xy)) ∨ (τ(yx)) →(τ(x)∨ τ(y)) and hence τ(xy) ≤ τ (x) ∨ τ(y). The other inequality follows easily from (3).

  8. Applying (V2) and (V5), we get τ (xy)∨(yx)≥ τ(xy) ∨ τ (yx) = 1.

  9. By (V2) and (V4), we have τ2(x) = τ(x).

  10. For all x, yL, assume that τ(x) ≤ y, we have τ τ(x) ≤ τ (y). By the (9), we get τ2(x) = τ(x). Thus τ (x) ≤ τ(y). Conversely, suppose that τ(x) ≤ τ (y), we have τ(x) ≤ τ(y) ≤y.

  11. Let y ∈ τ(L), so there exists xL such that y = τ(x). Hence τ(y) = τ τ (x) = τ(x) = y. This follows that yFixτ(L). Conversely, if y ∈ Fixτ(L), we have y ∈ τ(L). Therefore, τ(L) = Fixτ(L).

  12. It follows from (5)-(7).

  13. For any xL, we have x = τ(x0) for some x0L. By (9), we have τ(x) = τ (τ (x0)) = τ(x0) = x. Therefore, τ = idL.

  14. Assume that xL but x ≠ 1 such that τ(x) = 1. Applying (V2), we have 1 = τ(x) ≤ x and hence x = 1, which is a contradiction. Therefore, Ker(τ) ={1}.

  15. This is easy to check. Hence we omit the proof.

The assertion (7) of above proposition gives us an idea of introducing a very true operator on an MTL-algebra in a different way. Namely, we can consider a mapping τ : LL satisfying (1) – (4) and the following axiom (5′) which replaces the axiom (5): (5′) τ(xy) = τ(x) ∨ τ (y). From this point, one can check that the very true MTL-algebra essentially generalize very true BL-algebra, which was introduced by Hájek in 2001. A very true operator τ on an MV-algebra L was introduced in Leuştean (2006) as a mapping τ : LL satisfying conditions (∨1)-(∨3) and (8) in Proposition 3.3. From this point of view, the notion of very true MTL-algebra also generalizes that of very true MV-algebra.

Although the Fixτ(L) is not necessary a subalgebra of an MTL-algebra in general (in Example 3.2 (c), one can check that Fixτ(L) is not a subalgebra of L since it is not closed under →), while it forms an MTL-algebra after redefined its fuzzy implication.

Theorem 3.4

Let τ be a very true operator on L. Then (Fixτ(L), ∧, ∨, ⊙, ⇝, 0,1) is an MTL-algebra, where xy = τ(xy) for all x, yFixτ(L).

Proof

First, we show that (Fixτ(L), ∧, ∨, 0,1) is a bounded lattice with 0 as the smallest element and 1 as the greatest element. From Proposition 3.3 (6),(7), we have that Fixτ(L) is closed under ∨ and ∧. Thus (Fixτ (L), ∧, ∨) is a lattice. For all x ∈ τ(L), one can easily check that x∨ 1 = 1 and x ∧ 0 = 0. Thus, 0 is the smallest element and 1 is the greatest element in Fixτ(L), respectively. Therefore (Fixτ(L), ∧, ∨, 0,1) is a bounded lattice.

Next, we prove that (Fixτ(L), ⊙, 1) is a commutative monoid with 1 as neutral element. By Proposition 3.3 (5), we have Fixτ(L) is closed under ⊙. It follows that (Fixτ(L), ⊙) is a commutative semigroup. For all xFixτ(L), we obtain that x ⊙ 1 = x, that is, 1 is a unital element.

Then, we prove that ⇝ and ⊙ form an adjoint pair. For all x, yFixτ(L), we define Xy = τ(xy). Now, we will show that xyz if and only if yXz for all x, y, zFixτ(L). From Proposition 3.3 (10), we have τ(x) ≤ y if and only if τ(x) ≤ τ(y). Hence we have xyz if and only if yxz if and only if τ(y) ≤ xz if and only if τ(y) ≤ τ (xz) if and only if τ(y) ≤ xy if and only if yxz for all x, y, zFixτ(L).

Finally, we prove that the prelinearity condition holds. For all x, yFixτ(L), by (∨5), we have (xy) ∨ (Yx) = τ (xy) ∨ τ(yx) = 1.

Therefore, we obtain that (Fixτ(L), ∧, ∨, ⊙,⇝, 0,1) is an MTL-algebra.

The result of Theorem 3.4 shows that the fixed point set Fixτ(L) of very true operator in an MTL-algebra L has the same structure as L, which reveals the essence of the fixed point set.

In the following, using the properties of very true operators, we give some conditions for an MTL-algebra to be an MV-algebra and a Gödel algebra.

Theorem 3.5

Let (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1) be an MTL-algebra and τ be a very true operator on L. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1) is an MV-algebra,

  2. every very true operator τ satisfies τ (xy) = (τ(x) → τ(y)) → τ(y) = (τ(y) → τ(x)) → τ(x) for all x, yL.

Proof

(1) ⇒ (2) We note that an MV-algebra satisfies (xy) → y = (yx) → x for all x, yL. By Proposition 2.2 (11) and 3.3(7), we have τ(xy) = τ(x) ∨ τ (y) = ((τ(x) → τ(y)) → τ (y). In the similar way, we can prove τ(xy) = τ(x) ∨ τ(y) = ((τ(y) → τ(x)) → τ (x). Thus τ(xy) = (τ(x) → τ(y)) → τ(y) = (τ(y) → τ(x)) → τ(x).

(2) ⇒ (1) Suppose that every very true operator τ satisfies τ(xy) = (τ(x) → τ (y)) → τ(y) = (τ(y) → τ(x)) → τ (x) for all x, yL. Taking τ = idL, we have xy = (xy) → y = (yx) → x for all x, yL. Therefore, L is an MV-algebra.

Theorem 3.6

Let (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1) be an MTL-algebra and τ be a very true operator on L. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (L, ∧, ∨, ⊙, →, 0,1) is a Gödel algebra,

  2. every very true operator τ satisfies τ(xy) = τ(x) ⊙ τ(y) for allx, yL,

  3. every very true operator τ satisfies τ(xy) = τ(x) ⊙ τ(xy) for all x, yL.

Proof

(1) ⇒ (2) Suppose that L is a Gödel algebra. Then one can obtain that xy = xy = x ⊙(xy) for any x, yL. By Proposition 3.3 (6), we have τ(xy) = τ(x) ∧ τ(y) = τ(x) ⊙ τ (y). Thus τ (xy) = τ(x) ⊙ τ(y).

(2) ⇒ (1) Suppose that every very true operator τ satisfies τ(xy) = τ(x) ∧ τ(y) for all x, yL. Taking τ = idL, we have xy = xy for any x, yL. Taking x = y, we get xx = x for all xL. Therefore, L is a Gödel algebra.

(1) ⇒(3) From (1) ⇒ (2), one can obtain that τ(xy) = τ (x) ⊙ τ (y) for any x, yL. Hence τ(xy) = τ(x ⊙ (xy) = τ(x) ⊙ τ (xy).

(3) ⇒(1) Suppose that every very true operator τ satisfies τ(xy) = τ(x) ⊙ τ (xy) for all x, yL. Taking τ = idL, we have xy = x ⊙(xy) for any x, yL. Taking x = y, we get xx = x for all xL. Therefore, L is a Gödel algebra.

4 Very true filters of very true MTL-algebras

In this section, we introduce very true filters of very true MTL-algebras. In particular, we focus on algebraic structures of VF(L) of all very true filters in the very true MTL-algebras and obtain that VF(L) forms a complete Heyting algebra. Moreover, we characterize subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebras and prove a representation theorem for very true MTL-algebras via very true filters.

Definition 4.1

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra and F be a filter of L. Then F is called a very true filter of (L, τ) ifxFimplies τ (x) ∈ Ffor allxL.

We will denote the set of all very true filters of (L, τ) by VF[L].

Example 4.2

ConsideringExample 3.2 (c), one can easily check that the very true filters of (L, τ) are {a, b, 1} and {1} and L. However, {b, 1} is a filter of L but not a very true filter of (L, τ).

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. For any nonempty set X of L, we denote by 〈Xτ the very true filter of (L, τ) generated by X, that is, 〈Xτ is the smallest very true filter of (L, τ) containing X. If F is a very true filter of (L, τ) and xF, we put 〈F, xτ := 〈F ∪ {x}〉τ.

The next theorem gives a concrete description of the very true filter generated by a subset of very true MTL-algebra (L, τ).

Theorem 4.3

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra and X be a nonempty set of L. ThenXτ = {xL|x≥ τ(y1) ⊙ … τ (yn), yiX, n ≥ 1}.

Proof

The proof is easy, and we hence omit the details.

Example 4.4

ConsideringExample 3.2(c), one can easily obtain that 〈0, aτ = 〈0, bτ = 〈0, a, bτ = {a, b, 1}, 〈Lτ = 〈a, b, 1〉τ = 〈0, a, 1〉τ = 〈0, b, 1〉τ = {1} and 〈0〉τ = L.

Theorem 4.5

LetF, F1, F2be very true filters of (L, τ) andaF. Then:

  1. aτ = {xL|x ≥ (τa)n, n ≥ 1},

  2. Faτ = {xL|xf ⊙(τ a)n, fF} = F ∨ [τ a),

  3. F1F2τ = {xL|xf1f2, f1F1, f2F2},

  4. ifab, thenbτ ⊆ 〈aτ,

  5. 〈τ(a)〉τ = 〈aτ,

  6. aτ ∨ 〈bτ = 〈abτ = 〈abτ,

  7. aτ ∩ 〈bτ = 〈τ(a)∨ τ(b)〉τ.

Proof

The proof of (1) – (5) are obvious.

(6) Since ababa, b, we deduce that 〈aτ, 〈bτ ⊆ 〈abτ ⊆ 〈abτ. It follows from that 〈aτ ∨ 〈bτ⊆ 〈abτ ⊆ 〈abτ. Conversely, let a ∈ 〈abτ. Then for some natural number n≥ 1, a ≥(τ(ab))n ≥( τ a ⊙ τ b)n = (τ a)n ⊙ (τ b)n. Hence a ∈ 〈aτ ∨ 〈bτ, we deduce that 〈 abτ ⊆ 〈aτ ∨ 〈bτ. Therefore 〈aτ ∨ 〈bτ = 〈abτ = 〈abτ.

(7) Since τ(a)≤ τ(a) ∨ τ(b), we deduce that 〈 τ(a) ∨ τ(b)〉τ ⊆ 〈 τ(a)〉τ = 〈aτ. Analogously, 〈 τ(a) ∨ τ(b) 〉τ⊆ 〈 τ(b) 〉τ = 〈bτ. It follows that 〈 τ(a) ∨ τ(b) 〉τ ⊆ 〈aτ ∩ 〈bτ. Moreover, let t ∈ 〈aτ ∩ 〈bτ. Then for some natural number n, m ≥ 1, t ≥(τ(a))m and t ≥(τ(b))n. Hence t≥(τ(a))m∨ (τ(b))n ≥ (τ(a) ∨ τ(b))mn = (τ(ab))mn, we deduce that a∈ 〈 τ(a)∨ τ(b)〉τ, that is, 〈aτ ∩ 〈bτ ⊆ 〈τ(a) ∨ τ(b) 〉τ. Therefore 〈aτ ∩ 〈bτ = 〈 τ(a)∨ τ(b)〉τ.

The next results shows that the algebraic structure of VF(L) of all very true filters in very true MTL-algebras forms a complete Heyting algebra.

Theorem 4.6

Let(L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. Define binary operations ∧, ∨, ↦ on VF(L) as follows : for allF1, F2VF(L), F1F2 = F1F2, F1F2 = 〈 F1F2τ, F1F2 = {xL|τ(x)∨ f1F2for anyf1F1}. Then (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L) is a complete Heyting algebra.

Proof

Suppose that {Fi}i∈ I is a family of very true filters of (L, τ) . From Theorem 4.5, it is easy to check that the infimum of {Fi}iI = ∩iIFi and the supermum is ∨iIFi= {xL|xfi1fi2 ⊙ … fim, f1jFij, ijI, 1 ≤ jm}. Therefore, (VF(L), ∧, ∨, 1, L) is a complete lattice under the inclusion order ⊆. Next, we define F1F2 = {xL|τ(x)∨ f1F2 for any f1F1 〉 for any F1, F2VF(L). And, we shall prove that F1F2F3 if and only if F2F1F3 for all F1, F2, F3VF(L), that is, (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L) is a complete Heyting algebra. In order to do this, we first show that F1F2 is a very true filter of (L, τ).

Now, we will show that F1F2 is a very true filter of (L, τ). Clearly 1∈ F1F2. Let xF1F2 and xy, then for any f1F1 such that τ(x)∨ f1F2. Since τ(x)∨ f1 ≤ τ(y)∨ f1F2 and hence yF1F2. Assume that x, yF1F2, then for any f1F1, τ(x)∨ f1, τ(y)∨ f1F2 and hence f1 ∨ τ(xy)∈ F2. So xyF1F2. Obviously, if xF1F2, then τ(x)∈ F1F2 and thus F1F2 is a very true filter of (L, τ).

Next, we will prove that F1F2F3 if and only if F1F2F3. Assume that F1F2F3. Let f1F1. Then τ(f1)∈ F1 and for any f2F2, we have τ(f2)∨ f1f1, τ(f2) ∨ f1 ≥ τ(f2). Hence τ(f2)∨ f1F1F2F3 and hence f1F1F2. Conversely, assume that F1F2F3. Let xF2F3, then xF2F3. For any f3F3, we have τ(x) ∨ f3F3. Taking f3 = xF3, we have x ∨ τ(x) = xF3. Thus F1F2F3.

Therefore, (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L) is a complete Heyting algebra.

Theorem 4.7

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra and FVF(L). Then thefollowing conditions are equivalent:

  1. F is a compact element of VF(L),

  2. F is a principal very true filter of (L, τ).

Proof

(1) ⇒ (2) Suppose that F is the compact element of VF(L). Since F = ∨xFxτ, then there exist x1, x2xn such that F = 〈x1τ ∨ 〈x2τ ∨…∨ 〈xnτ. By Proposition 4.5 (6), we have F = 〈x1x2 ⊙ … ⊙xnτ. Therefore, F is a principal very true filter of (L, τ).

(2) ⇒(1) Let F be a principal very true filter of (L, τ) . Then there exists xL such that F = 〈xτ. Suppose that {Fi}iIVF(L) and F = 〈xτ ⊆ ∨iI {Fi}. Then x ∈ ∨iIFi= 〈∪iIFiτ. It follows that there exist ijI, fijFij for all 1 ≤ jm such that xfi1fi2 ⊙ … fim, that is, x ∈ 〈Fi1Fi2 ∪ … ∪ Finτ = fi1Fi2 ∨ … ∨ Fin. Hence F= 〈xτFi1Fi2 ∨ … ∨ Fin. Therefore, F is a compact element of VF(L).

Definition 4.8

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra andθ be a congruence on L. Then θ is called a very true congruence on (L, τ) if (x, y)∈ θimplies (τ(x), τ(y)) ∈ θ, for anyx, yL.

Example 4.9

ConsideringExample 3.2 (c), one can see thatR = {{0,0}, {a, a}, {b, b}, {1,1}, {a, b}, {b, a}, {a, 1}, {1, a}, {b, 1}, {1, b}} is a very true congruence on (L,τ).

Theorem 4.10

For any very true MTL-algebra there exists a one to one correspondence between its very true filters and its very true congruences.

Proof

The proof is easy, and we hence omit the details.

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra and F be a very true filter. We define the mapping τF : L/FL/F such that τF([x])= [τ(x)] for any xL.

Proposition 4.11

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra and F a very true filter of (L, τ). Then (L/F, τF) is a very true MTL-algebra.

Proof

The proof is easy, and we hence omit the details.

Definition 4.12

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. A proper very true filter F of (L, τ) is called a prime very true filter of (L, τ), if for all very true filterF1, F2of (L, τ) such thatF1F2F, then F1F orF2F.

Example 4.13

ConsideringExample 3.2(c), one can easily obtain that {a, b, 1} is a prime very true filter of (L, τ).

Theorem 4.14

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra andFbe a proper very true filter of (L, τ). Then the following are equivalent:

  1. F is a prime very true filter of (L, τ),

  2. if τ(x) ∨ τ(y) ∈ Ffor somex, yL, thenxFor yF,

  3. (L/F, τF) is a chain.

Proof

(1) ⇒(2) Let τ(x) ∨ τ(y) ∈ F for some x, yL. Then 〈xτ ∩ 〈yτ = 〈 τ(x) ∨ τ(y) 〉τF. Since F is a prime very true filter of (L, τ), then 〈xτF or 〈yτF. Therefore, xF or yF.

(2) ⇒ (1) Suppose that F1,F2MF[L] such that F1F2F and F1F and F2F. Then there exist xF1 and yF2 such that x, yF. Since F1, F2 are very true filters of (L, τ), then τ(x)∈ F1 and τ(y) ∈ F2. From τ(x), τ(y) ≤ τ(x) ∨ τ(y), we obtain that τ(x)∨ τ (y) ∈ F1F2 = F. By (2), we get xF or yF, which is a contradiction. Therefore, F is a prime very true filter of (L, τ).

(1) ⇔(3) From (2), one can obtain that every prime very true filter of (L, τ) must be a prime filter of L. Based on this, the equivalence of (1) and (3) is clear.

For proving the subdirect representation theorem of very true MTL-algebras we will need the following theorem.

Theorem 4.15

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra andaL. If a≠ 1, then there exists a prime very true filterPof (L, τ) such thataP.

Proof

Denote Fa= {F|F is a proper very true filter of (L, τ) such that FF, aF}. Then fa ≠  since F is a very true filter not containing a and Fa is a partially set under inclusion relation. Suppose that {Fi|iI} is a chain in Fa, then ∪ {Fi|iI} is a very true filter of (L, τ) and it is the upper bounded of this chain. By zorn’s Lemma, there exists a maximal element P in Fa. Now, we shall prove that P is the desire prime very true filter of ours. Since PFa, then P is a proper very true filter and aP.

Let xyP for some x, yL. Suppose that xP and yP. Since P is strictly contained in 〈P, xτ and 〈P, yτ and by the maximality of P, we deduce that 〈P, xτFa and 〈P, yτFa. Then a∈ 〈P, xτ = P ∨[τ x) and a ∈ 〈P, yτ = P ∨[τ(y)) . Then we have a ∈(P ∨[τ(x)))∧(P ∨[τ(y))) = P ∨([τ(x))∧[τ(y))) = P∨[τ(x)∨τ(y)) = P ∨[τ(xy))∈ P, which implies that aP, a contradiction. Therefore, P is a prime very true filter such that FP and aP. Put F = { 1 }, the result is easy to obtain.

Now, we will prove that every very true MTL-algebra is a subdirect product of linearly ordered very true MTL-algebras.

Theorem 4.16

Each very true MTL-algebra is a subalgebra of the direct product of a system of linearly ordered very true MTL-algebras.

Proof

The proof of this theorem is as usual and the only critical point is the above Theorem 4.15.

The next results shows that MTL-algebra is representable if and only if very true MTL-algebra is representable.

Theorem 4.17

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. L is representable;

  2. (L, τ) is a subdirect product of linearly ordered very true MTL-algebras.

Proof

(1) ⇒(2) Suppose that the MTL-algebra L is representable. Then by Theorem 2.9, there exists a system S of prime filter of L such that ∩ S= {1}. Since every prime filter of L contains a minimal prime filter, we get that in our case the intersection of all minimal prime filter is equal to {1}. Moreover, we will show that every minimal prime filter in (L, τ). Let P be a minimal prime filter of L. Then by Theorem 2.8, P = ∪ {a|aP}. If xP, then there is aP such that xa = 1, hence 1 = τ(xa) = τ(x)∨ τ(a). Since aP, we get τ(a)∉ P, therefore τ(x)∈ P, that means that P is a very true filter in (L, τ). Therefore, (L, τ) is a subdirect product of linearly ordered very true NM-algebras.

(2) ⇒ (1) The converse is trivial and we hence omit this.

Theorem 4.18

LetLbe an MTL-algebra. Then the following condition are equivalent:

  1. L is representable,

  2. L can be embedded in a very true MTL-algebra (L, τ).

Proof

(1) ⇒(2) If L is representable, then L is a subdirect product of MTL-chain. By Example 3.2 (b), any MTL-chain has a structure of very true MTL-algebra. Moreover, the class of very true MTL-algebras is a variety, so a direct product of very true MTL-algebra is still a very true MTL-algebra.

(2) ⇒(1) is straightforward, since any very true MTL-algebra is a subdirect product of very true MTL-chains.

Definition 4.19

A very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) is said to bea subdirectly irreducible if it has the least nontrivial very true congruence.

Let (L, τ) be subdirectly irreducible. Then by Theorem 4.10, there is a very true filter F of (L, τ) such that θF = F, that means, F is the least very true filter of (L, τ) such that F ≠ {1}. Thus, we can conclude that a very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) is said to be subdirectly irreducible if among the nontrivial very true filters of (L, τ) there exists the least one, i.e., ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} ≠ {1}.

Example 4.20

ConsideringExample 3.2 (c), one can easily check that the very true MTL- algebra (L, τ) is subdirectly irreducible.

Next, we will show that every subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra is linearly ordered. To prove this important result, we need the following several propositions and theorems.

Proposition 4.21

Let(L, τ) be a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra andF1, F2VF(L). IfF1F2= {1}, thenF1= {1} orF2= {1}.

Proof

Suppose F1 ≠ {1} and F2 ≠ {1}, i.e., F1, F2 ∈ ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}}≠ {1}, then ∩{FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} ≠ {1} ⊆ F1F2. By F1F2 = {1}, we can get ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} = {1}, which contradicts the fact that (L, τ) is subdirectly irreducible. Hence, F1 = {1} or F2 = {1}.

Theorem 4.22

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra,

  2. there exists an elementaL,a < 1, such thatfor anyxL, x < 1 anda ∈ 〈xτ.

Proof

(1) ⇒ (2) Suppose that (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra, i.e., ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} ≠ {1}, then ∩ {〈xτ|x <1} ≠ {1}. Take a ∈ ∩ {〈xτ|x<1} satisfying a ≠ 1, then for any xL, x ≠ 1, a ∈ 〈xτ, by Theorem 4.5 (1), there exists mN, such that a ≥(τ(x))m. Clearly, a is the element that we need.

(2) ⇒(1) Conversely, we need to prove that for any FVF(L), if F ≠ {1}, then aF. In fact, by F ≠ {1}, it follows that there exists xF, x <1, and then, by the known condition, a∈ 〈xτ, furthermore, aF, so a ∈ ∩ {FVF(L)|F≠ {1}}. Hence, ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} ≠ {1}, i.e., (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra.

We recall that a non-unit element aL is said to be a coatom of L if ab, then b ∈ {a, 1}, i.e. b = a or b = 1 ([25]). In the following proposition, we will show that every subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra has at most one coatom.

Proposition 4.23

Let (L, τ) be a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra. For anyx,yL, ifxy = 1, thenx = 1 ory = 1.

Proof

For any x, yL, if xy = 1, then by Theorem 4.5, we have 〈xτ ∩ 〈yτ = 〈τ(x)∨ τ(y)〉τ = 〈τ(xy)〉τ= 〈1〉τ= {1}. By Proposition 4.21, we have 〈xτ = {1} or 〈yτ= {1}, hence x = 1 or y = 1.

The following Theorem shows that the subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) is linearly ordered, that is to say, the fuzzy truth value of all propositions in very true MTL logic are comparable. This is of key importance from the logical point of view.

Theorem 4.24

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra,

  2. (L, τ) is a chain.

Proof

(1) ⇒(2) Suppose (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra. Applying Definition 2.1, we have (xy)∨(yx) = 1 for any x, yL, then by Proposition 4.23, we have xy = 1 or yx = 1, i.e., xy or yx, so (L, τ) is a chain.

(2) ⇒ (1) Since (L, τ) is a chain and nontrivial, there exists a unique dual atom, denoted as a. Suppose F is any very true filter of (L, τ) satisfying F ≠ {1}, then aF. Since F is chosen arbitrarily from VF(L), then a ∈ ∩ {FVF(L)|F≠ {1}}. Hence ∩ {FVF(L)|F ≠ {1}} ≠ {1}, i.e., (L, τ) is a subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebra.

In what follows, we introduce the stabilizer of a nonempty subset set X with respect to a very true operator τ and study some properties of them. Let (L, τ) be a very tue MTL-algebra. Given a nonempty subset X of L, we put Rτ(X) = {aL|τ(a)→ x = x, ∀ xX}, and Lτ(X) = {aL|x → τ (a) = τ(a), ∀ xX}, which are called right and left stabilizer of X with respect to τ. Clearly, Rτ (X), Lτ (X) ≠ Ø. In fact, 1 ∈ Rτ (X) ∩ Lτ (X). In particular, if τ = idL, which is a right and left stabilizer of X (see [26]).

Example 4.25

ConsideringExample 3.2 (c). LetX = {a, b}. ThenLτ(X) = {a, b, 1} andRτ(X) = {1}.

Proposition 4.26

LetLbe a MTL-algebra andX, YL. Then the following conditions hold:

  1. 1 ∈ Rτ(X)∩ Lτ(X),

  2. IfXY, thenLτ(X) ⊆ Lτ(Y) and Rτ(X) ⊆ Rτ(Y),

  3. XLτ (Rτ(X)) ∩ Rτ(Lτ(X)),

  4. Rτ(X) = Rτ(Lτ (Rτ(X))) andLτ (X) = Lτ (Rτ (Lτ(X))),

  5. Lτ(L) = Rτ (L) = {1} andLτ (1) = Rτ (1) = L,

  6. If Ø ≠ XL, thenRτ (X) is a very true filter of (L, τ).

Proof

The proof of (1)-(5) is easy by Proposition 2.2.

(6) Let a, bRτ(X). Then τ(a)→ x = x and τ(b) → x = x for all xX. Hence by Proposition 2.2 (12), (τ(a) ⊙ τ(b))→ x = τ(a) → (τ(b) → x) = τ(a) → x = x for all xX and so τ(ab) → x ≤(τ(a) ⊙ τ(b)) → x = x. On the other hand, we have x ≤ τ(ab) → x. Therefore x = τ(ab) → x for all xX and hence abRτ(X). Now, let ab and aRτ (X). Then τ(a) → x = x, for all xX. Hence by Proposition 3.3, τ(b) → x ≤ τ(a) → x = x. Since by x ≤ τ(b) → x, then τ(b)→ x = x and bRτ(X). Finally, one can easy check that if aRτ(X) then τ(a)∈ Rτ(X). Therefore Rτ(X) is a very true filter of (L, τ).

Theorem 4.27

LetFbe a very true filter of (L, τ). ThenRτ(F) is a pseudocomplemented ofFin the complete Heyting algebra (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L).

Proof

First, we prove that FRτ (F) = {1}. Let xFRτ (F). Since xRτ (F), then for any aF, τ(x) → a = a. Now, since xF, put a = x we have x = 1. Therefore, FRτ (F) = {1}. Now, let G be a very true filter of (L, τ) such that FG = {1}. Let aG, then τ(a) ∈ G. Then for any xF, since τ(a), x ≤ τ(a) ∨ x, xF, then τ(a) ∨ xF and τ(a) ∨ xG and so τ(a) ∨ x ∈ {1}. Hence τ(a) ∨ x = 1, that is ((τ(a) → x) → x) ∧ ((x → τ(a)) → τ(a)) = 1 and so ((τ(a) → x) → x) = 1. Hence, τ(a) → xx. On the other hand, x ≤ τ(a) → x, then τ(a) → x = x and aRτ (F). Thus GRτ (F). Therefore, Rτ (F) is a pseudocomplemented of F in the complete Heyting algebra (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L).

Theorem 4.28

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra. Then (VF(L), ∧, ∨, ↦, 1, L) is a complete pseudocomple-mented Heyting lattice.

Proof

It follows from Theorem 4.6 and Theorem 4.27

Now, we use of the right and left stabilizers of a very true MTL-algebra to produce a basis for a topology on it. Then we show that the generated topology by this basis is Baire, connected, locally connected and separable.

Theorem 4.29

Let (L, τ) be a very true MTL-algebra andXL. Define a mapping α : P( L,≪) → P( L,≪)such that α(X) = Rτ(Lτ(X)) for allXP( L). Then the following conditions hold,

  1. α is a closure map on (L, τ),

  2. X ⊆ α(Y) if and only if α(X) ⊆ α(Y), for allYL,

  3. βα = {XP(L)|α(X) = X} is a basis for a topology on (L, τ).

Proof

  1. It follows from Proposition 4.26 (2),(3),(4).

  2. The proof is easy.

  3. Let βα = {XP(L) |α(X) = X}. It is clear that Ø ∈ βα. Also, by Proposition 4.26 (5), α(L)= Rτ (Lτ(L)) = Rτ ({1}). Thus, α(L) = L, and L ∈ βα. Now, suppose that X, Y ∈ βα. Then α(X) = X and α(Y) = Y. We prove that XY ∈ βα. Since XYX, Y, by (1), α(XY) ⊆ α(X), α (Y). Thus, α(XY) ⊆ α(X) ∩ α(Y). Also, since X, Y ∈ βα, we have α(XY) ⊆ XY. Moreover, by Proposition 4.26 (3), XY ⊆ α(XY). Then α(XY) = XY, and so XY ∈ βα. Therefore, βα is a basis.

Definition 4.30

Based onTheorem 4.29, we introduce the topological space, (L,T) is called stabilizer topology on very true MTL-algebras.

From Proposition 4.26(6), one can obtain that Rτ(X) ∈ VF(L), for any XL and hence every element of βα is a very true filter of (L, τ).

Theorem 4.31

The stabilizer topology (L,T) is connected and locally connected.

Proof

The proof is easy, and we hence omit the details.

Theorem 4.32

The stabilizer topology (L,T) is Hausdorffspace if and only ifL = {1}.

Proof

The proof is easy, so we hence omit the details.

Theorem 4.33

The stabilizer topology (L,T) is separable.

Proof

First, we show that if Ø ≠ XL such that 1 ∈ X, then X¯ = L. Let Ø ≠ XL such that 1 ∈ X. We only show that LX¯. Let xL. If x = 1, then xX¯. Hence X¯ = L. Now, suppose that 1 ≠ xL. Then there exists an open subset U ∈ βα such that xU. Since UVF(L) and 1 ∈ U, we have U ∩(X − {x}) ≠ Ø. Hence xX¯, and so X¯ = L. Since 1 ∈ βα, thus 1¯ = L. Hence (L,T) is separable.

Theorem 4.34

The stabilizer topology (L,T) is a Baire space.

Proof

Let UT). Since UVF(L), we have 1 ∈ U. Then by Theorem 4.32, U¯ = L. Thus, every open set of (L,T) is dense. On the other hand, for each collection of open set Un, ∩ UnVF(L), so 1 ∈ ∩ Un. Thus, by Theorem 4.32, ∩ Un is dense. Therefore, (L,T) is a Baire space.

5 Very true MTL-logic

In this section, we translate the defining properties of very true MTL-algebras into logical axioms, and show that the resulting logic, i.e. very true MTL logic (MTLvt, for short) is sound and complete with respect to the variety of very true MTL-algebras.

Now, we deal with propositional calculus and define the axioms of the logic MTLvt to be those of MTL [2] plus the following ones:

  1. (vtl) vt(φ) ⇒ φ,

  2. (vt2) vt(φψ) ⇒ (vtφvtψ),

  3. (vt3) vt(φ) ⇒ vt(vtφ),

  4. (vt4) vt(φψ) ⊔ vt(ψφ).

The deduction rules are modus ponens (MP, from ϕ and ϕψ infer ψ), and Generalization (G, from ϕ infer vtϕ).

To prove the completeness theorem, we need some definitions and results about MTLvt logic.

The consequence relation ⊢ is defined in the usual way. Let T be a theory, i.e., a set of formulas in MTLvt. A (formula) proof of a formula ϕ in T is a finite sequence of formulas with ϕ at its end, such that every formula in the sequence is either an axiom of MTLvt, a formula of T, or the result of an application of an deduction rule to previous formulas in the sequence. If a proof of ϕ exists in T, we say that ϕ can be deduced from T and we denote this by Tϕ. Moreover T is complete if for each pair ϕ,ψ, Tϕψ or Tψϕ.

Definition 5.1

Let (L, τ) be a very trueMTL-algebra andTbe a theory. AnL-evaluation is a mappingefrom the set of formulas ofMTLvttoLthat satisfies, for each two formulasϕandψ : e(ϕψ) = e (ϕ) → e(ψ), e(ϕψ) = e(ϕ) ∨ e(ψ), e(ϕψ)= e(ϕ)∧ e(ψ), e (ϕ&ψ) = e(ϕ) ⊙e (ψ), e(vtϕ) = τ e(ϕ), e (0¯)=0 ande(1¯)=1. If anL- evaluationesatisfiese(χ) = 1 for every χ inT, it is called anL-model ofT.

Now, we stress our attention to the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra of MTLvt

Definition 5.2

LetTbe a fixed theory overMTLvt. For each formulaϕ, let [ϕ]Tbe the set of all formulasψsuch thatTϕψ ( whereϕψstands for (ϕψ) & (ψφ)) andLTbe the set of all the class [ϕ]T. We define: 0 = [0]T, 1 = [1]T, [ϕ]T ⇒ [ψ]T = [ϕψ]T, [ϕ]τ & [ψ]T = [ϕ&ψ]T, [ϕ]T ⊔[ψ]T = [ϕψ]T, [ϕ]T ⊓[ψ]T = [ϕψ]T, τT[ϕ]T = [vtϕ]T. This algebra is denoted by (LT, τT).

Proposition 5.3

(LT, τT) is a very trueMTL-algebra.

Proof

It follows similarly from the proof of Proposition 4.11.

Theorem 5.4

Let T be a theory overMTLvt. Then T is complete if and only if the very true MTL-algebra (LT, τT) is linearly ordered.

Proof

It follows similarly from the proof of Theorem 4.14.

It is easy to check that MTLvt is sound with respect to the variety of very true MTL-algebras, i.e., that if a formula ϕ can be deduced from a theory T in MTLvt, then for every very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) and for every L-model e of T, e(ϕ) = 1. Indeed, we need to verify the soundness of the new axioms and deduction of MTLvt (for the axioms and rules of MTL, the reader can check [2]). For the axioms this is easy, as they are straightforward generalizations of axioms of very true MTL-algebras. We will now verify the soundness of the new deduction rules.

Proposition 5.5

The deduction rules of MTLvt are sound in the following sense, for any formula ϕ and ψ.

  1. If for all very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) andfor allL-modeleforT, e(ϕ) = 1, then for all very trueMTL-algebra (L, τ) and for allL-modeleforT, e(vtϕ) = 1.

  2. If for all very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) and for allL-modeleforT, e(ϕ) = 1 ande(ϕψ) = 1, then for all very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) and for allL-modeleforT, e(ψ) = 1.

Proof

  1. Take such a very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) and such a model e. Then e(ϕ) = 1, and e(vtϕ)= τ e(ϕ) = τ(1)=1.

  2. Take such very true MTL-algebra and a model e. Then e(ϕ)→ e(ψ)= e(ϕ)→ e (ψ) = 1, which means e (ϕ) ≤ e(ψ). If e(ϕ) = 1, we have 1 = e(ϕ)≤ e(ψ) and thus e(ψ)= 1.

Theorem 5.6

LetTbe a theory overMTLvt. If T is a theory andTϕ, then there is a consistent complete supertheoryTTsuch thatTϕ.

Proof

It follows similarly with the proof of Theorem 4.15.

The next result in the sequence is the completeness of very true MTL-logic is proved based on the variety of very true MTL-algebras.

Theorem 5.7

Let T be a theory overMTLvt. For each formulaφ, the following are equivalent:

  1. Tϕ;

  2. for each very true MTL-algebra (L, τ) and for everyL-modeleofT, e(ϕ) = 1;

  3. for each linearly ordered very trueMTL-algebra (L, τ) and for everyL-modeleofT, e(ϕ) = 1.

Proof

It follows from Theorems 4.16, 5.4, 5.6 and Proposition 5.5.

Theorem 5.8

MTLvt is a conservative extension of MTL.

Proof

Suppose MTLφ then there is a linearly ordered MTL-algebra L such that φ is not an L-model. Expand an MTL-algebra L to a very true MTL-algebra follows from Example 3.2 (b). By Theorem 5.7, we have MTLvtφ. Therefore, MTLvt is a conservative extension of MTL.

6 Conclusion

In this paper, motivated by the previous research of very true operators on BL-algebras, we extended the concept of very true operators to MTL-algebras. Also, we gave s characterizations of MV-algebras and Gödel algebras via this operator. Moreover, we investigated very true filters of very true MTL-algebras and focus on an analogous of representation theorem for very true MTL-algebras and characterize subdirectly irreducible very true MTL-algebras by very true filters. Then, we introduced the left and right stabilizers of very true MTL-algebras and constructed stabilizer topology via it. Finally, the corresponding logic very true MTL-logic was constructed and the soundness and completeness of this logic were proved based on very true MTL-algebras. Our further work on this topic will focus on the varieties of very true MTL-algebras. In particular, we will investigate semisimple, locally finite, finitely approximated and splitting varieties of very true MTL-algebras as well as varieties with the disjunction and the existence properties.

Acknowledgements

The authors thank the editors and the anonymous reviewers for their valuable suggestions in improving this paper. This research was partially supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (11571281).

References

[1] Hájek P., Metamathematics of Fuzzy logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrech, 1998.10.1007/978-94-011-5300-3Search in Google Scholar

[2] Esteva F., Godo L., Monoidal t-norm based logic: towards a logic for left-continuoust-norms, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2001, 124, 271-288.10.1016/S0165-0114(01)00098-7Search in Google Scholar

[3] Jenei S., Montagna F., A proof of standard completeness for Esteva and Godo’s logic MTL, Stud Log., 2002, 70, 183-192.10.1023/A:1015122331293Search in Google Scholar

[4] Vetterlein T., MTL-algebras arising from partially ordered groups, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2010, 161, 433-443.10.1016/j.fss.2009.09.008Search in Google Scholar

[5] Noguera C., Esteva F., Gispert J., On Some Varieties of MTL-algebras, Log. J. IGPL., 2004, 13, 443-466.10.1093/jigpal/jzi034Search in Google Scholar

[6] Haveshki M., Saeid A. B., Eslami E., Some type of filters in BL-algebras, Soft Comput., 2006, 10, 657-664.10.1007/s00500-005-0534-4Search in Google Scholar

[7] Borzooei R. A., Shoar S. Khosravi., Ameri. R., Some type of filters in MTL-algebras, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2012, 187, 92-102.10.1016/j.fss.2011.09.001Search in Google Scholar

[8] Haveshki M., A note on some types of filters in MTL-algebras, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2014, 16, 135-137.10.1016/j.fss.2013.08.014Search in Google Scholar

[9] Hájek P., On very true, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2001, 124, 329-333.10.1016/S0165-0114(01)00103-8Search in Google Scholar

[10] Zadeh L., Fuzzy logic and approximate reasoning, Synthese., 1975, 30, 407-428.10.1142/9789814261302_0016Search in Google Scholar

[11] Ganter B., Wille R., Formal concept analysis, Mathematical Foundations, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1999.10.1007/978-3-642-59830-2Search in Google Scholar

[12] Bělohlávek R., Vyhodil V., Reducing the size of fuzzy concept lattices by hedges, In: FUZZ-IEEE 2005, the IEEE internationnal conference on fuzzy systems (25-25 May 2005), Reno, NV, USA, 2005, 65-74.Search in Google Scholar

[13] Chajda I., Hedges and successors in basic algebras. Soft Comput., 2011, 15, 613-618.10.1007/s00500-010-0570-6Search in Google Scholar

[14] Hájek P., Harmancová D., A hedge for Gödel fuzzy logic, lnternational Journal of Uncertainly, Fuzziness and Knowledge-Based Systems., 2000, 8, 495-498.10.1142/S0218488500000332Search in Google Scholar

[15] Leuştean l., Non-commutative Łukasiewicz propositional logic, Arch Math Logic., 2006, 45, 191-213.10.1007/s00153-005-0297-8Search in Google Scholar

[16] Rachunek J., Šalounová D., Truth values on generalizations of some commutative fuzzy structures, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2006,157,3159-3168.10.1016/j.fss.2006.08.007Search in Google Scholar

[17] Botur M., Švrček F., Very true on CBA fuzzy logic, Math Slovaca., 2010, 60, 435-446.10.2478/s12175-010-0023-9Search in Google Scholar

[18] Wang J T., Xin X L., Young B J., Very true operators on equality algebras, submitted for publication.Search in Google Scholar

[19] Chajda I., Kolařík M., Very true operators in effect algebras, Soft Comput., 2012, 16, 1213-1218.10.1007/s00500-012-0807-7Search in Google Scholar

[20] Grätzer G., Lattice theory, W H Freeman and Company, San Franciso, 1979.10.1007/978-3-0348-7633-9Search in Google Scholar

[21] Joshi K. D., lntroduction to general topology, New Age lnternational Publisher, lndia, 1983.Search in Google Scholar

[22] Blyth T. S., Lattices and Ordered Algebraic Structures, Springer, London, 2005.Search in Google Scholar

[23] Turunen E., BL-algebras of basic fuzzy logic, Mathware Soft Comput., 1998, 6, 49-61.Search in Google Scholar

[24] Zhang J. L., Topological properties of prime filters in MTL-algebras and fuzzy set representations for MTL-algebras, Fuzzy Sets Syst., 2011, 178, 38-53.10.1016/j.fss.2011.03.002Search in Google Scholar

[25] Abbasloo M., Saeid A. B., Coatoms and comolecules of BL-algebras, J Intell Fuzzy Syst., 2014, 27, 351-360.10.3233/IFS-131002Search in Google Scholar

[26] Saeid A. B., Mohtashamnia N., Stabilizer in residuated lattices, Politehn. Univ. Bucharest Sci. Bull. Ser. A Appl. Math. Phys., 2012, 74, 65-74.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2016-5-27
Accepted: 2016-10-18
Published Online: 2016-12-10
Published in Print: 2016-1-1

© 2016 Wang et al.

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.

Articles in the same Issue

  1. Regular Article
  2. A metric graph satisfying w41=1 that cannot be lifted to a curve satisfying dim(W41)=1
  3. Regular Article
  4. On the Riemann-Hilbert problem in multiply connected domains
  5. Regular Article
  6. Hamilton cycles in almost distance-hereditary graphs
  7. Regular Article
  8. Locally adequate semigroup algebras
  9. Regular Article
  10. Parabolic oblique derivative problem with discontinuous coefficients in generalized weighted Morrey spaces
  11. Corrigendum
  12. Corrigendum to: parabolic oblique derivative problem with discontinuous coefficients in generalized weighted Morrey spaces
  13. Regular Article
  14. Some new bounds of the minimum eigenvalue for the Hadamard product of an M-matrix and an inverse M-matrix
  15. Regular Article
  16. Integral inequalities involving generalized Erdélyi-Kober fractional integral operators
  17. Regular Article
  18. Results on the deficiencies of some differential-difference polynomials of meromorphic functions
  19. Regular Article
  20. General numerical radius inequalities for matrices of operators
  21. Regular Article
  22. The best uniform quadratic approximation of circular arcs with high accuracy
  23. Regular Article
  24. Multiple gcd-closed sets and determinants of matrices associated with arithmetic functions
  25. Regular Article
  26. A note on the rate of convergence for Chebyshev-Lobatto and Radau systems
  27. Regular Article
  28. On the weakly(α, ψ, ξ)-contractive condition for multi-valued operators in metric spaces and related fixed point results
  29. Regular Article
  30. Existence of a common solution for a system of nonlinear integral equations via fixed point methods in b-metric spaces
  31. Regular Article
  32. Bounds for the Z-eigenpair of general nonnegative tensors
  33. Regular Article
  34. Subsymmetry and asymmetry models for multiway square contingency tables with ordered categories
  35. Regular Article
  36. End-regular and End-orthodox generalized lexicographic products of bipartite graphs
  37. Regular Article
  38. Refinement of the Jensen integral inequality
  39. Regular Article
  40. New iterative codes for 𝓗-tensors and an application
  41. Regular Article
  42. A result for O2-convergence to be topological in posets
  43. Regular Article
  44. A fixed point approach to the Mittag-Leffler-Hyers-Ulam stability of a fractional integral equation
  45. Regular Article
  46. Uncertainty orders on the sublinear expectation space
  47. Regular Article
  48. Generalized derivations of Lie triple systems
  49. Regular Article
  50. The BV solution of the parabolic equation with degeneracy on the boundary
  51. Regular Article
  52. Malliavin method for optimal investment in financial markets with memory
  53. Regular Article
  54. Parabolic sublinear operators with rough kernel generated by parabolic calderön-zygmund operators and parabolic local campanato space estimates for their commutators on the parabolic generalized local morrey spaces
  55. Regular Article
  56. On annihilators in BL-algebras
  57. Regular Article
  58. On derivations of quantales
  59. Regular Article
  60. On the closed subfields of Q¯~p
  61. Regular Article
  62. A class of tridiagonal operators associated to some subshifts
  63. Regular Article
  64. Some notes to existence and stability of the positive periodic solutions for a delayed nonlinear differential equations
  65. Regular Article
  66. Weighted fractional differential equations with infinite delay in Banach spaces
  67. Regular Article
  68. Laplace-Stieltjes transform of the system mean lifetime via geometric process model
  69. Regular Article
  70. Various limit theorems for ratios from the uniform distribution
  71. Regular Article
  72. On α-almost Artinian modules
  73. Regular Article
  74. Limit theorems for the weights and the degrees in anN-interactions random graph model
  75. Regular Article
  76. An analysis on the stability of a state dependent delay differential equation
  77. Regular Article
  78. The hybrid mean value of Dedekind sums and two-term exponential sums
  79. Regular Article
  80. New modification of Maheshwari’s method with optimal eighth order convergence for solving nonlinear equations
  81. Regular Article
  82. On the concept of general solution for impulsive differential equations of fractional-order q ∈ (2,3)
  83. Regular Article
  84. A Riesz representation theory for completely regular Hausdorff spaces and its applications
  85. Regular Article
  86. Oscillation of impulsive conformable fractional differential equations
  87. Regular Article
  88. Dynamics of doubly stochastic quadratic operators on a finite-dimensional simplex
  89. Regular Article
  90. Homoclinic solutions of 2nth-order difference equations containing both advance and retardation
  91. Regular Article
  92. When do L-fuzzy ideals of a ring generate a distributive lattice?
  93. Regular Article
  94. Fully degenerate poly-Bernoulli numbers and polynomials
  95. Commentary
  96. Commentary to: Generalized derivations of Lie triple systems
  97. Regular Article
  98. Simple sufficient conditions for starlikeness and convexity for meromorphic functions
  99. Regular Article
  100. Global stability analysis and control of leptospirosis
  101. Regular Article
  102. Random attractors for stochastic two-compartment Gray-Scott equations with a multiplicative noise
  103. Regular Article
  104. The fuzzy metric space based on fuzzy measure
  105. Regular Article
  106. A classification of low dimensional multiplicative Hom-Lie superalgebras
  107. Regular Article
  108. Structures of W(2.2) Lie conformal algebra
  109. Regular Article
  110. On the number of spanning trees, the Laplacian eigenvalues, and the Laplacian Estrada index of subdivided-line graphs
  111. Regular Article
  112. Parabolic Marcinkiewicz integrals on product spaces and extrapolation
  113. Regular Article
  114. Prime, weakly prime and almost prime elements in multiplication lattice modules
  115. Regular Article
  116. Pochhammer symbol with negative indices. A new rule for the method of brackets
  117. Regular Article
  118. Outcome space range reduction method for global optimization of sum of affine ratios problem
  119. Regular Article
  120. Factorization theorems for strong maps between matroids of arbitrary cardinality
  121. Regular Article
  122. A convergence analysis of SOR iterative methods for linear systems with weak H-matrices
  123. Regular Article
  124. Existence theory for sequential fractional differential equations with anti-periodic type boundary conditions
  125. Regular Article
  126. Some congruences for 3-component multipartitions
  127. Regular Article
  128. Bound for the largest singular value of nonnegative rectangular tensors
  129. Regular Article
  130. Convolutions of harmonic right half-plane mappings
  131. Regular Article
  132. On homological classification of pomonoids by GP-po-flatness of S-posets
  133. Regular Article
  134. On CSQ-normal subgroups of finite groups
  135. Regular Article
  136. The homogeneous balance of undetermined coefficients method and its application
  137. Regular Article
  138. On the saturated numerical semigroups
  139. Regular Article
  140. The Bruhat rank of a binary symmetric staircase pattern
  141. Regular Article
  142. Fixed point theorems for cyclic contractive mappings via altering distance functions in metric-like spaces
  143. Regular Article
  144. Singularities of lightcone pedals of spacelike curves in Lorentz-Minkowski 3-space
  145. Regular Article
  146. An S-type upper bound for the largest singular value of nonnegative rectangular tensors
  147. Regular Article
  148. Fuzzy ideals of ordered semigroups with fuzzy orderings
  149. Regular Article
  150. On meromorphic functions for sharing two sets and three sets in m-punctured complex plane
  151. Regular Article
  152. An incremental approach to obtaining attribute reduction for dynamic decision systems
  153. Regular Article
  154. Very true operators on MTL-algebras
  155. Regular Article
  156. Value distribution of meromorphic solutions of homogeneous and non-homogeneous complex linear differential-difference equations
  157. Regular Article
  158. A class of 3-dimensional almost Kenmotsu manifolds with harmonic curvature tensors
  159. Regular Article
  160. Robust dynamic output feedback fault-tolerant control for Takagi-Sugeno fuzzy systems with interval time-varying delay via improved delay partitioning approach
  161. Regular Article
  162. New bounds for the minimum eigenvalue of M-matrices
  163. Regular Article
  164. Semi-quotient mappings and spaces
  165. Regular Article
  166. Fractional multilinear integrals with rough kernels on generalized weighted Morrey spaces
  167. Regular Article
  168. A family of singular functions and its relation to harmonic fractal analysis and fuzzy logic
  169. Regular Article
  170. Solution to Fredholm integral inclusions via (F, δb)-contractions
  171. Regular Article
  172. An Ulam stability result on quasi-b-metric-like spaces
  173. Regular Article
  174. On the arrowhead-Fibonacci numbers
  175. Regular Article
  176. Rough semigroups and rough fuzzy semigroups based on fuzzy ideals
  177. Regular Article
  178. The general solution of impulsive systems with Riemann-Liouville fractional derivatives
  179. Regular Article
  180. A remark on local fractional calculus and ordinary derivatives
  181. Regular Article
  182. Elastic Sturmian spirals in the Lorentz-Minkowski plane
  183. Topical Issue: Metaheuristics: Methods and Applications
  184. Bias-variance decomposition in Genetic Programming
  185. Topical Issue: Metaheuristics: Methods and Applications
  186. A novel generalized oppositional biogeography-based optimization algorithm: application to peak to average power ratio reduction in OFDM systems
  187. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  188. Modeling of vibration for functionally graded beams
  189. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  190. Decomposition of a second-order linear time-varying differential system as the series connection of two first order commutative pairs
  191. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  192. Differential equations associated with generalized Bell polynomials and their zeros
  193. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  194. Differential equations for p, q-Touchard polynomials
  195. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  196. A new approach to nonlinear singular integral operators depending on three parameters
  197. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  198. Performance and stochastic stability of the adaptive fading extended Kalman filter with the matrix forgetting factor
  199. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  200. On new characterization of inextensible flows of space-like curves in de Sitter space
  201. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  202. Convergence theorems for a family of multivalued nonexpansive mappings in hyperbolic spaces
  203. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  204. Fractional virus epidemic model on financial networks
  205. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  206. Reductions and conservation laws for BBM and modified BBM equations
  207. Special Issue on Recent Developments in Differential Equations
  208. Extinction of a two species non-autonomous competitive system with Beddington-DeAngelis functional response and the effect of toxic substances
Downloaded on 23.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/math-2016-0086/html?lang=en
Scroll to top button