Home Empathy – Real-Life and Fiction-Based
Article
Licensed
Unlicensed Requires Authentication

Empathy – Real-Life and Fiction-Based

  • Anja Berninger EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: September 11, 2018
Become an author with De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

In response to the so-called paradox of fiction, Kendall Walton famously argued that our affective reactions to fictions differ structurally from real-life emotions. Many authors now reject the idea that there really is a paradox of fiction. But, even if this is true, Walton may have been right in that there really are far reaching differences between the way we respond to fictions and our real-life emotional reactions. That is, even if we do not believe the paradox of fiction is a paradox, it can still lead us to doubt the homogeneity of our emotional responses and to reflect on the relation between real-life and fiction-based emotional reactions. In this paper, I want to further discuss this issue focusing on the case of empathy.

The main questions I want to answer are: What are the differences between our real-life and fiction-based empathic reactions? Are there any far reaching structural differences between the two? In my discussion, I will stress the idea that real-life empathy is often built on a relatively complex interaction between the person that empathizes and the emotional subject. I will show, first of all, that this type of social interaction is not possible in literary fiction. Secondly, I will stress that literature often offers an introspective perspective on a character’s inner life. This is a perspective not open to us in real-life settings, which allows for a distinct kind of empathy.

In discussing real-life and fiction-based empathy I differentiate between two different functions empathic reactions might fulfill. Thus, following Matthew Kieran, I suggest that some forms of empathy might allow us to infer the emotional state an agent is in and to predict his subsequent behavior. In other cases, however, the aim of empathy is not to achieve some sort of epistemic aim, but rather to feel a kind of solidarity with those that are in the grip of an emotion. In this paper, I concentrate on this second kind of empathy.

I will start with some general remarks on the structure of real-life empathy. Drawing on some ideas originally voiced by Adam Smith, I will highlight the fact that empathy is a deeply social process involving two individuals: the one that empathizes (the empathizer or the spectator) and the one that is empathized with (the empathizee or the actor). According to Smith, both actor and spectator will often put themselves in the other’s shoes to bring empathy about. Furthermore, both sides engage in some form of emotion regulation: the spectator tries to regulate his emotions so they match those of the empathizee. The empathizee, in turn, may need to down-regulate his emotional reactions, so that they can indeed match. In how far he must do so, depends on his relation with the empathizer. I suggest that, additionally to these forms of emotion regulation, the empathizee also engages in some forms of reason giving. The exact form this takes again depends on his relationship with the empathizer.

I then go on to show that this theory enables us to understand why empathy is sometimes so difficult to achieve in real life. Here, I show that high degrees of emotional intensity but also the type of emotion felt may make it difficult for the empathizee to engage in the sort of down-regulation and reason giving discussed.

With these distinctions in place, I then turn to the case of fiction-based empathy. I will show that fiction-based empathy is not a social phenomenon in the same sense as real-life empathy. There is thus an important structural difference between the two. I then suggest that fiction often confronts us with the type of cases that present challenges to real-life empathy (i. e. cases where there is a lack of down-regulation, high emotional intensity and so on). Fiction, however, also provides us with additional resources that facilitate empathy even in these difficult cases. Fiction often gives us access to the stream of thought of a fictional character. Fictional texts thus allow us to get a glimpse on how emotional intensity and emotion type affect a character’s thinking, as well as offering us insight into the raw emotional feel, the intensity and urgency connected to many emotions. Fictional texts generally use aesthetic means to give us access to these aspects. Thus, when feeling empathy in response to a work of fiction we must therefore not only understand the situation in question, but must also be sensitive to (some of the) aesthetic features of the text.

References

Ben Ze’ev, Aaron, The Subtlety of Emotions, Cambridge, MA 2000.10.7551/mitpress/6548.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Berninger, Anja, Thinking Sadly. In Favor of an Adverbial Theory of Emotions, Philosophical Psychology 29:6 (2016), 799–812.10.1080/09515089.2016.1159294Search in Google Scholar

Butler, Emily, Interpersonal Affective Dynamics. It Takes Two and Time to Tango, Emotion Review 7:4 (2015), 336–341.10.1177/1754073915590622Search in Google Scholar

Cikara, Mina/Emile G. Bruneau/Rebecca R. Saxe, Us and Them. Intergroup Failures of Empathy, Current Directions in Psychological Science 20:3 (2011), 149–153.10.1177/0963721411408713Search in Google Scholar

Cochrane, Tom, Eight Dimensions for the Emotions, Social Science Information 48:3 (2009), 379–420.10.1177/0539018409106198Search in Google Scholar

Coplan, Amy, Empathic Engagement with Narrative Fictions, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62:2 (2004), 141–152.10.1111/j.1540-594X.2004.00147.xSearch in Google Scholar

Cova, Florian/Fabrice Teroni, Is the Paradox of Fiction Soluble in Psychology?, Philosophical Psychology 29:6 (2016), 930–942.10.1080/09515089.2016.1164306Search in Google Scholar

De Vignemont, Frederique/Tania Singer, The Empathic Brain. How, When and Why?, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10:10 (2006), 435–441.10.1016/j.tics.2006.08.008Search in Google Scholar

De Vignemont, Frederique, Drawing the Boundary between Low-Level and High-Level Mind Reading, Philosophical Studies 144:3 (2009), 457–466.10.1007/s11098-009-9354-1Search in Google Scholar

Gibson, John, Empathy, in: Noël Carroll/J.G. (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Literature, London/New York 2016, 234–246.10.4324/9781315708935-20Search in Google Scholar

Joyce, James, Dubliners [1914], New York 1969.Search in Google Scholar

Kauppinen, Antti, Empathy, Emotion Regulation, and Moral Judgment, in: Heidi Maibom (ed.), Empathy and Morality, Oxford et al. 2014, 97–121.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199969470.003.0005Search in Google Scholar

Keen, Suzanne, Empathy and the Novel, Oxford et al. 2007.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195175769.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Kieran, Matthew, In Search of a Narrative. Narrative Understanding, Imagination, Sympathy and Empathy, in: M.K./Dominic Lopes (eds.), Imagination, Philosophy and the Arts, London 2003, 70–88.10.4324/9780203498644Search in Google Scholar

Lamarque, Peter, How can We Fear and Pity Fictions?, British Journal of Aesthetics 21:4 (1981), 291–304.10.1093/bjaesthetics/21.4.291Search in Google Scholar

Lopes, Dominic M., An Empathic Eye, in: Amy Coplan/Peter Goldie (eds.), Empathy. Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford 2011, 118–133.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199539956.003.0009Search in Google Scholar

Maibom, Heidi, Feeling for Others. Empathy, Sympathy, and Morality, Inquiry 52:5 (2009), 483–499.10.1080/00201740903302626Search in Google Scholar

Mar, Raymond A. et al., Bookworms Versus Nerds. Exposure to Fiction Versus Non-Fiction, Divergent Associations with Social Ability, and the Simulation of Fictional Social Worlds, Journal of Research in Personality 40 (2006), 694–702.10.1016/j.jrp.2005.08.002Search in Google Scholar

Moran, Richard, The Expression of Feeling in Imagination, The Philosophical Review 103:1 (1994), 75–106.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190633776.003.0001Search in Google Scholar

Pettersson, Anders, The Concept of Literary Application. Readers’ Analogies from Text to Life, Basingstoke, NY 2012.Search in Google Scholar

Pronin, Emily/Elana Jacobs, Mental Motion. Thought Speed, Mood and the Experience of Mental Motion, Perspectives on Psychological Science 3 (2008), 461–485.10.1111/j.1745-6924.2008.00091.xSearch in Google Scholar

Pronin, Emily/Daniel M. Wegner, Manic Thinking. Independent Effects of Thought Speed and Thought Content on Mood, Psychological Science 17 (2006), 807–813.10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01786.xSearch in Google Scholar

Smith, Adam, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Facsimile Edition, Edinburgh 1761, http://find.galegoup.com.008963dp0745.emedia.bsb-muenchen.de (01. 03. 2018).Search in Google Scholar

Stecker, Robert, Should We Still Care about the Paradox of Fiction?, British Journal of Aesthetics 51:3 (2011), 295–308.10.1093/aesthj/ayr019Search in Google Scholar

Valihora, Karen, The Judgement of Judgement. Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments, British Journal of Aesthetics 41:2 (2001), 138–161.10.1093/bjaesthetics/41.2.138Search in Google Scholar

Walton, Kendall, Fearing Fictions, The Journal of Philosophy 75:1 (1978), 5–27.10.2307/2025831Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2018-09-11
Published in Print: 2018-09-03

© 2018 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 27.9.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/jlt-2018-0013/html
Scroll to top button