Home “Legitimate Authority” in the Chinese Tradition: Ethics-Politics
Article Open Access

“Legitimate Authority” in the Chinese Tradition: Ethics-Politics

  • Lun Du EMAIL logo
Published/Copyright: September 5, 2022
Become an author with De Gruyter Brill

Abstract

Max Weber proposed three types of legitimate authority: charismatic, traditional and rational-legal. Roughly at the same time, the Chinese scholar Liang Qichao, fully aware of the strong link between ethics and politics in ancient China, put forward the concept of “ethics-politics”, which launched a major debate. None of Weber’s three types of legitimate authority is applicable to the ancient Chinese model of “ethics-politics”, and “ethics-politics” should be considered and explored as a fourth type of legitimate authority. This article gives an outline of the historical origins of “ethics-politics” as well as the principles that gave rise to the concept. Then it cites pre-Qin Confucianism, particularly the thoughts of Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzi, to exemplify the legitimate authority of “ethics-politics” from five aspects: (1) inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king; (2) rule of the man of virtue, viz. “to govern by virtue” and “rule by rites” or “rule of rites”; (3) benevolence as the core value; (4) everyone should become good as the goal of government; (5) Heaven/Tian as the supreme divinity.

1 Introduction

Over 100 years ago, Max Weber (1864–1920) proposed three types of “legitimate authority” (drei Arten der legitimen Herrschaft): charismatic (charismatische Herrschaft), traditional (traditionelle Herrschaft), and rational-legal (legale/rationale Herrschaft) (Weber, 1980, pp. 122–124). Interestingly, he classified the ruling order in ancient China as charismatic (Weber, 1980, pp. 140–141), in stark contrast to some Chinese scholars, who expected to see it fall into the category of traditional authority (Mao, 2001, p. 87; Yue, 2006, p. 220).

Weber’s types of “legitimate authority (合法统治)” were imported into China from the West, while the concept and theory of “ethics-politics (伦理政治)” were home-grown, representing Chinese scholars’ self-understanding of the Chinese political tradition and political thought. “Ethics-politics” advanced first by Liang Qichao (梁启超 1873–1929) about 100 years ago, summarized his perception of the close connections between ethics and politics in ancient China. According to him, the perfect clan organization blurred the boundary between family and state, shaping the Chinese style of government closely connected with ethics (Liang, 1996, pp. 44–48). Liang Shuming (梁漱溟 1893–1988) stated that this constituted a striking characteristic of Chinese political practice, which was heavily intertwined and integrated with ethics (Dai & Jiang, 2001, p. 272). Some contemporary Chinese scholars have inherited this view and developed it rather systematically (Yang, 2007, pp. 373–374) “political model” and a “cultural type” characterized by the “homogeneity (同构同化)” of ethics and politics: “Political issues are measured by ethical standards (伦理标准) and ethical rules (伦理规则) are implemented by political control” (Ren, 2005, pp. 28–29).

This article argues that none of Weber’s three types of legitimate authority corresponds to the political structure that existed in ancient China or the ideal framework advcated in Confucianism. And “ethics-politics” can act as the fourth type of legitimate authority, which may serve as a reference when comparing the political systems and ideas of China and the West.

2 “Ethics-Politics” as the Fourth Type of Legitimate Authority

Weber labeled the model of government in ancient China “charismatic” because adversity (such as a defeat in a war, a drought or a flood) would force a monarch to repent publicly or even abdicate. It indicated that the monarch had lost his “charisma (魅力)” or “virtue (德)” (Du, 2018, pp. 66–69), as mandated by Heaven/Tian (天), and was no longer a legitimate “son of Tian” (天子). Weber captured the core of political legitimacy in ancient China, namely that the legitimacy of a monarch was built on his virtues, but he erroneously equated “virtue” with “charisma”. According to him, “charisma” was “above the everyday life” (Weber, 1980, p. 142), that is, transcendent. “Virtue” nevertheless has been infused into China’s political daily routines ever since the rulers of the Western Zhou Dynasty advocated the legitimacy theory of “virtuous practice being worthy of the mandate of Tian.” Furthermore, Weber’s charismatic authority was built on the worship of a ruler by his followers and could transcend certain values. Traditional Chinese “virtue,” is inseparable from values, and is a requirement for any ruler (Barnwell, 2013, pp. 77–78).

In the following part, we will examine why Weber did not regard the ruling order in ancient Chinese as “traditional authority” from the aspects of the “types of legitimacy belief” and “the relationship between the monarch and his administration.” On the former, Weber argued that the legitimacy of the traditional authority was based on the traditional order, the power of the master, and belief in the sanctity of that power. The master was chosen according to rules that were handed down (Weber, 1980, p. 130). Apparently this seems true of ancient China. For instance, succession to the crown and the imperial throne were either according to the system of lineal primogeniture, or granted by the reigning monarch. However, this procedure for power transfer did not touch upon the nature of legitimacy, as the so-called “traditional ruling order” (政统) could not be the reason for legitimacy or reflect the “principle of legitimacy.”[1] (Weber, 1980, pp. 549–550), viz. “to govern by humanity” (Du, 2021, pp. 64–66), approved of by Confucianism. For Confucians, a person assuming the throne did not become a legitimate ruler unless he demonstrated that he had met their standards known as “Confucian orthodoxy.” Perhaps it is for this reason that Deng Yong believes that ancient Chinese tended to favor “the legitimacy of governance of a political power” rather than “the legitimacy of the source of political power” (Deng, 2011, pp. 47–75).

Indeed, from the Western Zhou Dynasty onwards, three elements constituted the political legitimacy in Chinese political thought: the mandate of Tian, the virtue of the ruler, and the will of the people. Tian as the source of legitimacy was the formal element, while the ruler’s virtue and the will of the people were essential reasons for legitimacy. After Emperor Wu of the Han Dynasty (汉武帝), Confucianism became the resource of national ideology and the political legitimacy. Confucianism neither denied the traditional ruling order featured by “the son of Tian ruling the people,” nor gave much consideration to the issue of legitimacy of power acquisition. Instead, it focused on the monarch’s level of moral development and his attitude toward the people according to the tradition of “Tian nurtures the people and appoints a king for their benefit,” as was declared in “13th Year of Duke Wen” of Zuo’s Commentary to The Spring and Autumn Annals (《左传 · 文公十三年》).

The relationship between the sovereign and his administration provides another perspective on the issue of the political legitimacy. Weber defined the relationship between the two factors as “personal.” The executive branch, he wrote, is subordinate not to the law, but to specific individuals appointed by the rulers who are either prescribed or established conventionally. If in ancient China, the state officials were genuinely mainly composed of Confucians or those who had received Confucian ideas, then these officials should have had no personal relationship with the emperor. Although they served in the imperial court and carried out the emperor’s decrees, they did not obey the emperor as an individual, but the person on the throne. According to the Confucian ideal, a specific emperor played merely one role in the ruling order, performing the duties of that position. Therefore, the officials actually did no more than obey their own ideal, or the so-called “Confucian orthodoxy.” This tradition was established by Confucius, who observed, “A minister serves his monarch by following the Way (dao, 道), and resigns if he can’t” (from “Xian Jin” of The Analects,《论语 · 先进》). And Xunzi put it more explicitly: “Follow the Way, not the monarch” (“On the Way of Ministers” in Xunzi,《荀子 · 臣道》).

In ancient China, it was not the succession of the throne according to the rules of “the traditional ruling order” but the inclusive “virtue” required of the monarch (as approved by Confucianism) that determined the legitimacy of his authority. Only by virtue of this “virtue” can the correctness and validity of his authority and the ruling order be guaranteed. Correctness, which is a belief in the right of authorities to rule and of members to obey (Easton, 1965, p. 288) and validity (Weber, 1980, pp. 122–124) lie at the core of legitimacy, so we should, on the grounds of its unique correctness and validity, present our conception of a unique “type of legitimate authority” of ancient China —“ethics-politics.” In this way, we can truly grasp the essence of Chinese politics and understand it better. At the same time, we take advantage of and modernize this ideological resource in a way proper to China.

3 The Historical Origins and Principles of “Ethics-Politics”

“Ethics-politics” as a “type of legitimate authority” is not just an “ideal type” of concept for government or a fantasy, but a crystal clear historical fact, which dates back at least to the Western Zhou Dynasty.

After Emperor Wu of Zhou overthrew the Shang Dynasty through the Battle of Muye, the Zhou ruling clique established a feudal kingdom on the basis of the patriarchal clan system. The Zhou Dynasty “developed a political system that unified the state-level and the family-level organizations” (Chen, 2007 p. 66), forming a homogeneous pattern (同质模式) that integrated “the family with the state” (Han, 2001, p. 61; Lü et al., 2004, p. 2 & Pi, 2007, p. 26). A good case in point is the king of Zhou. He was both the political authority and the patriarch of the Ji clan. “The state is a representation of the clan on the political level, whereas the clan is at the core of the state governing structure.” (Tian & Zang, 1996, p. 32) This indicates that ethical and political principles are inseparable.

It is generally believed that there were two important principles underlying the patriarchal system of the Western Zhou Dynasty: “loving one’s relatives” and “honoring one’s seniors” (Gan, 2006, p. 26; Pi, 2007, pp. 160–163 & Yang, 2007, p. 60). The “Great Treatise” in The Book of Rites (《礼记 · 大传》) states, “Regulating the hierarchical relationship to one’s ancestors and deceased father is a case of honoring one’s seniors. Regulating the hierarchical relationship to one’s offspring is a case of loving one’s later generations. Regulating the order of brothers and cousins, gathering members of the same clan to dine together, arranging them orderly according to blood relations, and making difference of the relationship between them according to the rituals, are all truths pertaining to humanity.” Although the “Great Treatise” mainly talks about patriarchal rituals, they are directly related to political governance. In the paragraph quoted above, “to regulate” means “to rectify.” Therefore, “Regulating the hierarchical relationship to one’s ancestors and one’s deceased father is a case of honoring the seniors” means “rectifying the relationship between oneself and his father and ancestors,” and “respecting one’s seniors.” “Regulating the hierarchical relationship to one’s descendants” means “rectifying the relationship between oneself and one’s offspring,” or “loving one’s descendants (恩爱后代)” (Liu et al., 1993, p. 489). The last statement, “[the aforementioned] are all the truths pertaining to humanity,” declares that human relations, viz. ethics, is the theme of the book.

The book then goes on to say, “When the sagely king assumes the throne and rules the world, he must begin with the way of humankind.” And “loving one’s relatives” and “honoring one’s seniors” are discussed again. It can be justifiably concluded that “loving one’s relatives” was meant to highlight the blood lineage and the family affection between clan members, so as to maintain unity. The principle of “honoring one’s seniors” similarly bears the dual meanings of ethics and politics. Confucius remarked, “To his son and heir, a ruler is a father in terms of blood relations, and a monarch in terms of politics. The ruler has both fatherly love and monarchical honor, thus the capacity for ruling the whole world.” (“Wenwang Shizi 8” in The Book of Rites, 《礼记 · 文王世子第八》)

In short, these two principles determined the status of a clan member in the internal hierarchy of the clan according to age, sex, and relationship to the eldest son and heir of the firstborn. At the same time, the daily political activities of the upper class members in the clan also had a strict order to follow, so that the daily life and political system within the clan could operate orderly.

Beyond doubt, Confucians added their own notions to the rituals and rites practiced by the ruling class of the Western Zhou Dynasty, and thence developed a number of theories, part of which were what we designate as “thought of ethics-politics”. Meanwhile, Confucians also absorbed the political theory of the ruling group of the Western Zhou Dynasty, especially the idea of legitimacy, and finally formed the “thought on legitimacy of ethics-politics” particular to Confucianism.

4 The Five Components of the “Thought on Legitimacy of Ethics-Politics” of Confucianism in the Pre-Qin Period

“Virtue” runs through the “thought on legitimacy of ethics-politics,” which is related to the traits of Chinese philosophy, especially Confucianism. Mou Zongsan summarized Chinese philosophy with two words “subjectivity (主体性)” and “inner-morality (内在道德性)” ― and held that Confucianism alone developed “moral subjectivity (道德主体性)” (Mou, 2010, p. 5).

Historically, there are probably two reasons for this. First, the pre-Qin Confucians inherited and improved the political thought of the early Western Zhou Dynasty, especially the thought of legitimacy, that is, the theory centered around “mandate of Heaven (天命)”, “respect virtue (敬德)” and “protect ruled people (保民).” (Du, 2017, pp. 67–80) “Virtue” was the prerequisite for a ruler to receive the will of Heaven and to perceive the wishes and worries of the people. Second, the pre-Qin Confucians did not query the existing “monarchies” [be it the feudal system established in the Western Zhou Dynasty or the centralized system of prefectures and counties (Zou, 2004, pp. 24–29)] that emerged in the late Spring and Autumn Period). In order to ensure long-term peace and stability, Confucians seem to have focused on the morality of the rulers and government officials.

In the following part, we will look at the core position of “virtue” in the five components of the “thought on the legitimacy of ethics-politics.”

4.1 The Ideal of “Ethics-Politics”: Inwardly Being a Sage and Outwardly Being a King”

If we take “inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king (内圣外王)” as the ideal of “ethics-politics” then “inwardly being a sage” is the ethical part while “outwardly being a king”[2] is the political part. “Inwardly being a sage” means to acquire the virtues of sages through self-cultivation while “outwardly being a king” is to inspire the mass with one’s talents and virtues and to practice “the kingly way or the benevolent governance” (王道).

“What the Great Learning teaches, is to illustrate illustrious virtue; to make new people (Zhu, 1983, p. 3); and to rest in the highest goodness.” This is the opening sentence of “Great Learning” in The Book of Rites (《礼记 · 大学》). The academic circle generally regard this sentence as a Confucian interpretation of “inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king”. These are the same process. The “inner sage” is the premise of “outer king” and “outer king” is the result of the “inner sage”, which must be expressed through “outer king”. Morality determines political capabilities, which must in turn reflect it.

It is difficult to achieve the ideal of “inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king,” because the talents and virtues of a sage are far out of reach.[3] However, being unattainable, one is impelled to keep trying. “Inwardly being a sage” sets both the direction and goal, and starts a process of continuous efforts, leading to the highest talents and the best model of governance. Since it is a process, it entails different degrees of efforts to achieve this goal. The higher one’s morality is, the stronger one’s ability of leadership is. These are the Confucian requirements for rulers.

4.2 The Path Toward “Ethics-Politics”: “Rule of the Man of Virtue”

If a “sage” was an illusory “ideal personality” far above real life, what could be found was a “man of virtue (君子).”[4] The realization of “inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king” was accomplished by being a “man of virtue” in real politics (Yang, 2006, p. 39).

In other words, the Confucian minimum requirement of a ruler is that he be a “man of virtue.” Here the “man of virtue” could be the ruler himself or his officials. A man of virtue runs a country (君子治国) by means of his internal virtue and the external order and rules. When he utilizes his internal “virtue,” it is about “to govern by virtue (德政)”; when he relies on the external order and rules, it is about “rule by rites (礼治)” or “rule of rites ”

4.2.1 “To Govern by Virtue” or “to Govern by the Power of Virtue”

In ancient China, “political” thought was actually thought on “governance,” which is only partly conveyed in Western languages (such as the English word “politics”) (Du, 2018, p. 66–69). The word “to govern” can better reflect this idea. The pre-Qin Confucian concepts of “virtue” and “to govern by virtue (德政)” were the development of the ideas of “respecting virtue and protecting ruled people (敬德保民)” and “matching virtue with Heaven (以德配天)” of the Western Zhou Dynasty. They mainly emphasized the moral abilities and model function of the rulers, which were embodied in the two phrases of Confucius: “Governing by virtue” and “guiding ruled people by virtue.”

“A ruler governing by means of his virtue is like the north polar star, which stays still, surrounded and followed by all the other stars”, which is from “On Governance” of The Analects (《论语 · 为政》). First of all, the ruler himself had to have a high moral standard, which was a prerequisite for government. This was not only in line with the goal of “everyone should become good (人人向善)” in Confucian political thought, but also in accordance with the spirit of “inwardly being a sage and outwardly being a king.” Only those who had high moral standards could influence the common people.

“Guiding the people by means of virtue” comes from “On Governance” of The Analects (《论语 · 为政》). Confucius said, “If the people are guided by decree, and their behavior is unified by criminal law, they will try to avoid the punishment, but have no sense of shame. If they are guided by virtue, and their behavior is unified by rites, they will have a sense of shame, and moreover will behave correct.” We can definitely relate “guiding the people by virtue” to “teaching them by moral” from “The Black Robes” in The Book of Rites (《礼记 · 缁衣》), and interpret de (德) as socially recognized “virtue (美德)” or “moral (道德)” (Liu, 1990, p. 41), rather than the ruler’s moral appeal as suggested by “governing by means of his virtue.” Similarly, the sentence of “guiding by means of virtue” can be understood as the ruler using his moral behavior as a standard to guide the people. Zhu Xi said, “To guide is to lead, meaning to take the lead.” (Zhu, 1983, p. 54; Li, 2004, p. 50). Although de bears the meaning of “moral standard (道德标准),” it refers to the “moral model (道德典范)” and its influence radiating from inside, as reflected in the ruler, but it is not some norms outside the person, like “laws” and “rites,” which are constraints imposed upon people from outside.

4.2.2 “Rule by Rites” and “Rule of Rites” (礼治)

For Confucians, the function of “rites” was to regulate and straighten out (“On Rites” of Family Analects of Confucius,《孔子家语 · 论礼》) social relations, so as to differentiate the top of society from the bottom, but with family affection, distinguishing those with stronger kinship and those with weaker kinship, and thus form an effective social and political mechanism. “Rites” bear the sense of family affection. This is because “rites” were external rules that integrated and socialized social members. Confucius commented, “If you don’t study rites, you can’t take your stand (in der society).” (“Ji Shi” of The Analects,《论语 · 季氏》) and “If you don’t know about rites, you can’t take your stand (in der society).” (“Yong Ye” of The Analects,《论语 · 雍也》) To the rulers, “rites” were outlines of governing the state, and the standards that could be followed. Confucius clearly said: “Make rites for the state.” (“Xian Jin” of The Analects, 《论语 · 先进》).

Of course, “rites” were not only normative etiquette, rules and order, but also contained values, viz. “moral” or moral standards. They were a comprehensive system of moral norms and moral values. Social members would naturally internalize the moral values contained in “rites” in the process of practicing them. In this sense, the Confucian “rule by rites” was a means of governance, “If the behavior of the people is unified by rites,” as mentioned by Confucius. At the same time, it is the result of rites, which means the “rule of rites.”

“Rule by rites” and “rule of rites” could not be achieved unless the ruler set the public a role model in “obeying the rites.”[5] As Confucius observed, “When the ruler loves rites, the people dare not to be irreverent.” (“Zi Lu” of The Analects,《论语 · 子路》) In other words, the realization of “rule by rites,” especially “rule of rites,” ultimately depends on the role model of the man of virtue’s example of “to govern by virtue”. This is the dialectic of “to govern by virtue” and “rule by rites” complementing each other in the “rule of the man of virtue (君子之治)” (Du, 2015, pp. 143–147).

4.3 The Core Value of “Ethics-Politics”: Humanity (仁)

Chinese academic circles generally regard “benevolence” as the “core value” of Confucianism. It is also proposed that “benevolence” is the “core value (核心价值)” of “ethic-politics”. If “inwardly being a sage (内圣)” represents the highest level of moral cultivation, and “outwardly being a king (外王)” symbolizes the best state of governance, then “humanity” occupies a core position in between. “Humanity” finds expression in people’s ethical and political behaviors.

“To love people”, “loyalty” and “consideration” are usually taken as the three pillars of “humanity,” among which “loyalty” and “consideration” serve as approaches to “to love people”. The “Great Treatise” in The Book of Rites (《礼记 · 大传》) advocates that the patriarch should be “a paragon of humanity for his clan to emulate” and believes that “It is way of humankind to love relatives.” The “Discourses of the States” (国语) contains a similar saying, “Humanity is what protect ruled people.” Mencius also advocated, “Men of virtue love and care for their loved ones, they are therefore kind (human) to ruled people. When they are kind to ruled people, they treasure everything on Earth.” (Mengzi) A man of virtue should first of all harbor love for his relatives, and a ruler must extend this love to the common people. This is the essence of “human to the people,” or in Confucius’s words, “ a broad love for the multitude” (泛爱众), and “to bring peace to the common people.” (安百姓) “To love people” is thus realized through the extension from “love for one’s relatives” to “generous love for the multitude.”

The core of consideration is to put oneself in other people’s shoes. It means in passive sence, “Do not do unto others what you would not have others do unto you.” When Ran Yong (冉雍 522 B.C.E.—?) asked Confucius what “humanity” meant, the master replied, “When you go out your front gate, treat each person as though receiving an honored guest. When directing the actions of subordinates, do so as though managing a great ritual sacrifice. Do not due to others what you would not wish others do unto you.” (“Yan Yuan” of The Analects, 《论语 · 颜渊》) “Consideration” mainly means that one should treat others as one’s equals, putting oneself in their place. Consideration also has its positive side. Confucius once told Zi Gong (子贡 520 B.C.E.-?), “A person with humanity is one who, wishing himself to take a stand (in the society), helps others to take a stand (in the society), and who, wishing himself to make progresses in cultivation, helps others make progress in cultivation. The ability to proceed by analogy from what lies nearby is the key to humanity.” (“Yong Ye” of The Analects《论语 · 雍也》).

Some scholars interpret Confucius’s words as “loyalty” (Du, 2011, pp. 27–36). However, I agree with Zhu Xi, who put it this way, “Doing one’s best is loyalty; putting oneself in another’s place is consideration.”(Zhu Xi, 1983, p. 72) “Doing one’s best” first of all means preserving and cultivating humanity benevolence good heart, cultivating one’s ideal personality, and striving to become a man of virtue. No matter what other people are like, a man of virtue will act according to the principle of humanity. “Loyalty” itself involves being kind to others and teaching them to do good. Confucius once said, “If there are things which are not good,” a man of virtue will try “to change them by loyalty.” (“The 10th Chapter of Hao Sheng” in Family Analects of Confucius,《孔子家语 · 好生 第十》) Mencius also said, “Teaching people to be good is a sign of loyalty.” (“Duke Wen of Teng I” of Mencius 《孟子 · 滕文公上》) In short, “loyalty” is the foremost requirement of a ruler.

4.4 The Governance Purpose of “Ethics-Politics”: Everyone Should Become Good (人人成善)

According to Zhu Xi, the above mentioned “highest goodness” (至善) means “to illustrate illustrious virtue” and “to make new people” to reach the place of the highest goodness” (Zhu Xi, 1983, p. 3), namely: “The utmost point which things should develop to.” In other words, it is the state that “illustrate illustrious virtue” and “make new people” should attain. My understanding is that “illustrate illustrious virtue” refers to the ruler conducting self-governance, enlightening and promoting himself to the state of goodness. By applying it in life,” he also helps his people become good.

Yang Guorong argued, “To rest in the highest goodness is to achieve the highest standard of values.” (Yang, 2006, pp. 118–119) Seen in this way, “goodness” seems to be “moral standards,” with moral values included. The Mawangdui Silk Texts (《马王堆帛书》) and The Guodian Chu Slips (《郭店楚墓竹简》) both contain a chapter titled “Five Elements” (五行篇) (Ding, 2000, pp. 126–133). The chapter has the following words: “Humanity (仁) is a form of inner virtue (德之行) and an action (行) when externalized. Righteousness (义) is an inner virtue, and an action when externalized. Rites (礼) are a virtue and an action when externalized. Wisdom (智) is an inner virtue, and an action when externalized. Sagacity (圣) is an inner virtue, and an action when externalized. These five inner forms are all virtues. The five actions are called goodness. Goodness is the way of humanity; virtue is the way of Heaven (Liu, 2005, pp. 72–73).

Whether we understand xing (行) which is not shaped in one’s mind as an “external action shaped by inner virtue,” or “moral behavior of some social norms yet to be perceived or internalized,” (Liang, 2008, pp. 185–186) “goodness” includes the four values of humanity, righteousness, rites and wisdom. “The harmonious integration of these four values is called goodness. Goodness is the principle for humankind,” argued Liu Zhao (Liu, 2005, p. 74). The word “principle” might be replaced by “standards” ― standards of conduct for being a good person. Ding Sixin (丁四新) explained that “Goodness is the way of humankind; virtue is the way of Heaven” meaning that goodness “is a thing that focuses on human relations with the purpose of maintaining the social order and ethics.” (Ding, 2000, p. 135)

It is generally said that Mencius held the “theory of original goodness of human nature,” while Xunzi maintained the “theory of original evil of human nature” (Liang, 2015, pp. 71–80). In reality, both aimed at becoming good. Mencius’s approach was to keep and develop one’s original (moral) mind (good mind or good nature), Xunzi’s approach was to change one’s original “evil” through learning and self-cultivation. Yang Gaonan observed, “The theory of original goodness is a straightforward description of the goodness of human nature, while the theory of original evil is to appeal to the goodness in human nature.” (Yang, 2007, p. 405)

In short, for the ruler, “becoming good” required that he should first cultivate and increase his own morality, so as to be able to implement a “rule of the men of virtue,” “govern by virtue,” “rule of rites,” and “govern by humanity.” For the common people, “becoming good” meant that the ruler established a set of social norms, such as “benevolence, righteousness, courtesy, wisdom and credibility,” for them to internalize. In this way, the common people joined the specific process of social construction to become good people, thus achieving the purpose of lasting peace and stability.

4.5 The Source of Value and Moral Judgment in “Ethics-Politics”: Heaven/Tian (天)

“The Doctrine of the Mean” in The Book of Rites (《礼记 · 中庸》) begins with the following sentences, “What Heaven has determined is called human nature. Accordance with this nature is called the right way. Fostering this way is called education.” We can interpret them in this way: What Heaven has conferred is the nature of goodness; following the nature of goodness of each individual is the way; seeking and nurturing the way is learning and moral education. The important position Heaven occupies in Confucianism and its political philosophy is clear.

First, since “What Heaven has determined is called human nature (天命谓之性),” we can say that human moral values come from Heaven. As early as the Western Zhou Dynasty, the ancient Chinese people began to regard Heaven as the supreme force in the universe similar to the Christian God, and developed therefrom the belief of “the mandate of Heaven.” They also formed the thoughts of “the unity of Heaven and humankind (天人合一)” and “the unified virtue of Tian and humankind (天人合德).” Human beings can approach Heaven by cultivating their own morality. Heaven not only confers the nature of goodness, but also assigns to them the mission of understanding and developing their nature of goodness.

The author believes that “the mandate of Heaven” constitutes the basis of “thought on legitimacy of Ethics-politics.” The Chinese cultural tradition makes demanding requirements of the ruler, as reflected in this declarative sentence “Heaven nurtures people and sets up a monarch for their well-being.”[6] One could not make a ruler unless he possessed superb morality, conducted governance according to the “way of Heaven,” and met the aforementioned requirements. Nor would he respect the power conferred on him and govern the state prudently unless he had faith in “the mandate of Heaven” and was fully aware that Heaven above him is the supreme judge on the legitimacy of human behavior, that is, Heaven determines his destiny according to his governance.


Corresponding author: Lun Du, Institute of East Asian Studies and Institute of Political Science of Social Sciences, University of Duisburg-Essen, Duisburg, Germany, E-mail:

Article note: This is an abridged version of the article which was first published in Chinese in Issue 2, Volume 1 of International Studies on Confucianism (《国际儒学》) in 2021. The English version was translated by Yunping Niu, with some corrections made by Lun Du.


References

Barnwell, S. A. (2013). The evolution of the concept of de (德) in early China. Sino-Platonic Papers, 235, 77–78.Search in Google Scholar

Chen, J. S. (2007). 儒学社会通论 [General Theory about the Confucian society]. China Renmin University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Dai, M. T., & Jiang, C. (2001). 传统价值观念与当代中国 [Traditional values and modern China]. Hubei People’s Press.Search in Google Scholar

Deng, Y. (2011). 政权的来源合法性与治理合法性 [The legitimacy of the source of political power and the legitimacy of governance of a political power]. Confucian Cultural Studies, 16, 47–75.Search in Google Scholar

Ding, S. X. (2000). 郭店楚墓竹简思想研究 [The thought of bamboo slips in Guo Dian’s chu tomb]. The Oriental Press.Search in Google Scholar

Du, L. (2011). 仁学” “体系概述” [An outline of the system of benevolence]. History of Chinese Philosophy, (2), 27–36.Search in Google Scholar

Du, L. (2015). 先秦儒家 “德政” 与 “礼治” 思想对当今建立法治国家的意义 [The significance of the Pre-Qin Confucian thought of “moral authority” and “rule by rites” to the establishment of rule of law in contemporary China]. International Sinology, (2), 143–147.Search in Google Scholar

Du, L. (2017). The early Zhou Period: Origin of the idea of political legitimacy and the political philosophy of Confucianism. Asian Studies, 5(1), 67–80. doi:https://doi.org/10.4312/as.2017.5.1.67-80.Search in Google Scholar

Du, L. (2018). 先秦儒家思想的仁义道德:以古希腊(雅典)道德哲学为参照系的概述 [An overview of “benevolence, justice and morality” in pre-Qin Confucianism: With ancient Greek (Athens) moral philosophy as a reference system]. In A. Q. Deng (Ed.), Ethics (Vol. 4, pp. 66–69). Shanghai Educational Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Du, L. (2021). 中国传统的 “合法统治类型”:伦理政治 [The Chinese traditional “type of legitimate authority”: Ethics-politics]. International Studies on Confucianism, 1(2), 64–66.Search in Google Scholar

Easton, D. (1965). A system analysis of political life. John Wiley & Sons.Search in Google Scholar

Gan, C. S. (2006). 制度儒学 [Institutional confucianism]. Shanghai People’s Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Han, D. M. (2001). 荀子与儒家的社会理想 [Xunzi and the Confucian social ideal]. Shandong Qilu Press.Search in Google Scholar

Li, Z. H. (2004). 论语今读 [Reading the analects today]. SDX Joint Publishing Company.Search in Google Scholar

Liang, Q. C. (1996). 先秦政治思想史 [History of political thought in Pre-Qin period]. The Oriental Press.Search in Google Scholar

Liang, T. (2008). 郭店竹简与思孟学派 [Guodian Chu slips and the school of Zisi-Mencius]. China Renmin University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Liang, T. (2015). 荀子人性论辩证:论荀子的性恶、心善说 [Xunzi’s on human nature: A study on Xunzi’s theory of the original evil of human nature and goodness of heart]. Philosophical Studies, (5), 71–80.Search in Google Scholar

Liu, B. N. (1990). 论语正义 [Correct meaning of the analects]. Zhonghua Book Company.Search in Google Scholar

Liu, Z. (2005). 郭店楚简校释 [Guodian Chu slips collated and annotated]. Fujian People’s Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Liu, F. Y., Liu, S. L., & Tang, M. X. (1993). 十三经直解:第二卷下 [A plain interpretation of the thirteen Confucian classics (2b)]. Jiangxi People’s Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Lü, M. Z., Wang, J. L., Zhang, P. G., & Quan, X. J. (2004). 儒学与近代以来中国政治 [Confucianism and modern China]. Shandong Qilu Press.Search in Google Scholar

Mao, S. L. (2001). Political sociology [政治社会学]. China Social Sciences Press.Search in Google Scholar

Mou, Z. S. (2010). 中国哲学的特质 [The essence of Chinese philosophy]. Jilin Publishing Group.Search in Google Scholar

Pi, W. B. (2007). 和为贵” 的政治伦理追求— “和” 视域中的先秦儒家政治伦理思想研究 [The Political and ethical pursuit of “harmony is the most precious”: The political ethics of pre-Qin Confucianism from the perspective of “harmony”]. SDX Joint Publishing Company.Search in Google Scholar

Ren, J. T. (2005). 伦理王国的构造—现代性视野中的儒家伦理政治 [The construction of ethical kingdoms: Confucian ethics-politics viewed from the modern perspective]. China Social Sciences Press.Search in Google Scholar

Tian, C. W., & Zang, Z. F. (1996). 周秦社会结构研究 [The social structure of the Zhou and Qin dynasties]. Northwest University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Weber, M. (1980). Economy and society (5th reprint, Study Edition). Mohr.Search in Google Scholar

Yang, G. R. (2006). 善的历程:儒家价值体系研究 [The course of goodness: A study of the Confucian value system]. Shanghai People’s Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Yang, G. N. (2007). 原始儒家伦理政治引论 [An analysis of ancient Confucian ethics-politics]. Hunan People’s Publishing House.Search in Google Scholar

Yue, T. M. (2006). 政治合法性研——基于多民族国家的政治社会学分析 [Political legitimacy: Political sociology based on multinational country]. China Social Sciences Press.Search in Google Scholar

Zhu, X. (1983). 四书章句集注 [Interlinear analysis of and collected commentaries on the four books]. Zhonghua Book Company.Search in Google Scholar

Zou, S. J. (2004). 郡县制,天下安 [The system of prefectures and counties brought peace and stability to the world]. Historical Review, (4), 24–29.Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2022-09-05

© 2022 the author(s), published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 8.10.2025 from https://www.degruyterbrill.com/document/doi/10.1515/icos-2022-2010/html?lang=en&srsltid=AfmBOoqBDvRgsJedUyIgi5K9D9WVja4ioe7RRzdp5kep8-dCGRSuPyUl
Scroll to top button